<SPAN name="startofbook"></SPAN>
<p class="TI1-2pt1">KANT'S PROLEGOMENA</p>
<p class="TI2-1pt25">TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS</p>
<p class="TI3-0pt8">EDITED IN ENGLISH</p>
<p class="TI3-0pt8">BY</p>
<p class="TI4-1pt3">DR. PAUL CARUS</p>
<p class="TI5-0pt8">THIRD EDITION</p>
<p class="TI6-1pt25">CHICAGO</p>
<p class="TI7-1">THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY</p>
<p class="TI8-1">1912</p>
<p class="TI9-1pt1">TRANSLATION COPYRIGHTED</p>
<p class="TI9-1pt1">BY</p>
<p class="TI9-1pt1">The Open Court Publishing Co.</p>
<p class="TI9-1pt1">1902.</p>
<p class="TI10-0pt75">[Transcriber's note: ** Supplemental material and
table of contents are omitted from this etext. **]</p>
<p class="TOCTitle">Contents</p>
<p class="TOC1"><SPAN href="#__RefHeading___Toc3097" class="Index_20_Link">PUBLISHERS' PREFACE.</SPAN></p>
<p class="TOC1"><SPAN href="#__RefHeading___Toc3099" class="Index_20_Link">INTRODUCTION.</SPAN></p>
<p class="TOC1"><SPAN href="#__RefHeading___Toc3101" class="Index_20_Link">PROLEGOMENA.</SPAN></p>
<p class="TOC2">PREAMBLE ON THE PECULIARITIES OF ALL METAPHYSICAL
COGNITION.</p>
<p class="TOC1"><SPAN href="#__RefHeading___Toc3103" class="Index_20_Link">FIRST PART OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL PROBLEM.</SPAN></p>
<p class="TOC2">HOW IS PURE MATHEMATICS POSSIBLE?</p>
<p class="TOC1"><SPAN href="#__RefHeading___Toc3105" class="Index_20_Link">SECOND PART OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL PROBLEM.</SPAN></p>
<p class="TOC2">HOW IS THE SCIENCE OF NATURE POSSIBLE?</p>
<p class="TOC1"><SPAN href="#__RefHeading___Toc3107" class="Index_20_Link">THIRD PART OF THE MAIN TRANSCENDENTAL PROBLEM.</SPAN></p>
<p class="TOC2">HOW IS METAPHYSICS IN GENERAL POSSIBLE?</p>
<p class="TOC1"><SPAN href="#__RefHeading___Toc3109" class="Index_20_Link">SCHOLIA.</SPAN></p>
<p class="TOC2">SOLUTION OF THE GENERAL QUESTION OF THE PROLEGOMENA,
"HOW IS METAPHYSICS POSSIBLE AS A SCIENCE?"</p>
<p class="TOC1"><SPAN href="#__RefHeading___Toc3111" class="Index_20_Link">APPENDIX.</SPAN></p>
<p class="TOC2">ON WHAT CAN BE DONE TO MAKE METAPHYSICS ACTUAL AS A
SCIENCE.</p>
<hr>
<h1><SPAN name="__RefHeading___Toc3097" name="__RefHeading___Toc3097"></SPAN>PUBLISHERS' PREFACE.</h1>
<p class="Standard">
KANT'S <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span>,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn1" id="body_ftn1">1</SPAN></sup> although
a small book, is indubitably
the most important of his writings. It furnishes us with a key to his main work,
<span class="T6">The Critique of Pure Reason</span>; in fact, it is an extract
containing all the salient ideas of Kant's system. It approaches the subject in the
simplest and most direct way, and is therefore best adapted as an introduction into
his philosophy. For this reason, The Open Court Publishing Company has deemed it
advisable to bring out a new edition of the work, keeping in view its broader use as
a preliminary survey and explanation of Kant's philosophy in general. In order to
make the book useful for this broader purpose, the editor has not only stated his own
views concerning the problem underlying the <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span> (see
page 167 et seq.), but has also collected the most important materials which have
reference to Kant's philosophy, or to the reception which was accorded to it in
various quarters (see page 241 et seq.). The selections have not been made from a
partisan standpoint, but have been chosen with a view to characterising the attitude
of different minds, and to directing the student to the best literature on the
subject.</p>
<p class="Standard">It is not without good reasons that the appearance of the <span class="T6">Critique
of Pure Reason</span> is regarded as the beginning of a new era in the
history of philosophy; and so it seems that a comprehension of Kant's position, whether
we accept or reject it, is indispensable to the student of philosophy. It is not his
solution which makes the sage of Königsberg the initiator of
modern thought, but his formulation of the problem.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">* * *</p>
<p class="Standard">The present translation is practically new, but it goes without
saying that the editor utilised the labors of his predecessors, among whom Prof. John
P. Mahaffy and John H. Bernard deserve special credit. Richardson's translation of 1818
may be regarded as superseded and has not been consulted, but occasional reference has
been made to that of Prof. Ernest Belfort Bax. Considering the difficulties under which
even these translators labored we must recognise the fact that they did their work
well, with painstaking diligence, great love of the subject, and good judgment. The
editor of the present translation has the advantage of being to the manor born;
moreover, he is pretty well versed in Kant's style; and wherever he differs from his
predecessors in the interpretation of a construction, he has deviated from them not
without good reasons. Nevertheless there are some passages which will still remain
doubtful, though happily they are of little consequence.</p>
<p class="Standard">
As a <span class="T6">curiosum</span> in Richardson's translation Professor Mahaffy
mentions that the words <span class="T6">widersinnig gewundene Schnecken</span>,
which simply means "symmetric helices,"<sup><SPAN href="#ftn2" id="body_ftn2">2</SPAN></sup> are rendered by "snails rolled up
contrary to all sense"—a wording that is itself contrary to all sense and makes the
whole paragraph unintelligible. We may add an instance of another mistake that misses
the mark. Kant employs in the Appendix a word that is no longer used in German. He
speaks of the <span class="T6">Cento der Metaphysik</span> as having <span class="T6">neue Lappen</span> and <span class="T6">einen
veränderten Zuschnitt</span>. Mr. Bax translates <span class="T6">Cento</span> by "body," <span class="T6">Lappen</span> by "outgrowths,"
and <span class="T6">Zuschnitt</span> by "figure." His mistake is perhaps not less excusable than Richardson's; it is certainly not less comical,
and it also destroys the sense, which in the present case is a very striking simile. <span class="T6">Cento</span> is a Latin
word<sup><SPAN href="#ftn3" id="body_ftn3">3</SPAN></sup> derived from the Greek κεντρων,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn4" id="body_ftn4">4</SPAN></sup> meaning
"a garment of many patches sewed together," or, as we might now say, "a crazy quilt."</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">* * *</p>
<p class="Standard">In the hope that this book will prove useful, The Open Court
Publishing Company offers it as a help to the student of philosophy.</p>
<p class="EditorInitials">
P.C.</p>
<h1><SPAN name="__RefHeading___Toc3099" name="__RefHeading___Toc3099"></SPAN>INTRODUCTION.</h1>
<p class="Standard">THESE Prolegomena are destined for the use, not of pupils, but of
future teachers, and even the latter should not expect that they will be serviceable
for the systematic exposition of a ready-made science, but merely for the discovery of
the science itself.</p>
<p class="Standard">There are scholarly men, to whom the history of philosophy (both
ancient and modern) is philosophy itself; for these the present Prolegomena are not
written. They must wait till those who endeavor to draw from the fountain of reason
itself have completed their work; it will then be the historian's turn to inform the
world of what has been done. Unfortunately, nothing can be said, which in their opinion
has not been said before, and truly the same prophecy applies to all future time; for
since the human reason has for many centuries speculated upon innumerable objects in
various ways, it is hardly to be expected that we should not be able to discover
analogies for every new idea among the old sayings of past ages.</p>
<p class="Standard">My object is to persuade all those who think Metaphysics worth
studying, that it is absolutely necessary to pause a moment, and, neglecting all that
has been done, to propose first the preliminary question, ‘Whether such a thing as
metaphysics be at all possible?’</p>
<p class="Standard">If it be a science, how comes it that it cannot, like other
sciences, obtain universal and permanent recognition? If not, how can it maintain its
pretensions, and keep the human mind in suspense with hopes, never ceasing, yet never
fulfilled? Whether then we demonstrate our knowledge or our ignorance in this field, we
must come once for all to a definite conclusion respecting the nature of this so-called
science, which cannot possibly remain on its present footing. It seems almost
ridiculous, while every other science is continually advancing, that in this, which
pretends to be Wisdom incarnate, for whose oracle every one inquires, we should
constantly move round the same spot, without gaining a single step. And so its
followers having melted away, we do not find men confident of their ability to shine in
other sciences venturing their reputation here, where everybody, however ignorant in
other matters, may deliver a final verdict, as in this domain there is as yet no
standard weight and measure to distinguish sound knowledge from shallow talk.</p>
<p class="Standard">After all it is nothing extraordinary in the elaboration of a
science, when men begin to wonder how far it has advanced, that the question should at
last occur, whether and how such a science is possible? Human reason so delights in
constructions, that it has several times built up a tower, and then razed it to examine
the nature of the foundation. It is never too late to become wise; but if the change
comes late, there is always more difficulty in starting a reform.</p>
<p class="Standard">The question whether a science be possible, presupposes a doubt as
to its actuality. But such a doubt offends the men whose whole possessions consist of
this supposed jewel; hence he who raises the doubt must expect opposition from all
sides. Some, in the proud consciousness of their possessions, which are ancient, and
therefore considered legitimate, will take their metaphysical compendia in their hands,
and look down on him with contempt; others, who never see anything except it be
identical with what they have seen before, will not understand him, and everything will
remain for a time, as if nothing had happened to excite the concern, or the hope, for
an impending change.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Nevertheless, I venture to predict that the independent reader of these Prolegomena
will not only doubt his previous science, but ultimately be fully persuaded, that it
cannot exist unless the demands here stated on which its possibility depends, be
satisfied; and, as this has never been done, that there is, as yet, no such thing as
Metaphysics. But as it can never cease to be in demand,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn5" id="body_ftn5">5</SPAN></sup>—since the interests of common sense are
intimately interwoven with it, he must confess that a radical reform, or rather a new
birth of the science after an original plan, are unavoidable, however men may
struggle against it for a while.</p>
<p class="Standard">Since the Essays of Locke and Leibnitz, or rather since the origin
of metaphysics so far as we know its history, nothing has ever happened which was more
decisive to its fate than the attack made upon it by David Hume. He threw no light on
this species of knowledge, but he certainly struck a spark from which light might have
been obtained, had it caught some inflammable substance and had its smouldering fire
been carefully nursed and developed.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Hume started from a single but important concept in Metaphysics, viz., that of Cause
and Effect (including its derivatives force and action, etc.). He challenges reason,
which pretends to have given birth to this idea from herself, to answer him by what
right she thinks anything to be so constituted, that if that thing be posited,
something else also must necessarily be posited; for this is the meaning of the
concept of cause. He demonstrated irrefutably that it was perfectly impossible for
reason to think <span class="T6">a priori</span> and by means of concepts a
combination involving necessity. We cannot at all see why, in consequence of the
existence of one thing, another must necessarily exist, or how the concept of such a
combination can arise <span class="T6">a priori</span>. Hence he inferred, that
reason was altogether deluded with reference to this concept, which she erroneously
considered as one of her children, whereas in reality it was nothing but a bastard of
imagination, impregnated by experience, which subsumed certain representations under
the Law of Association, and mistook the subjective necessity of habit for an
objective necessity arising from insight. Hence he inferred that reason had no power
to think such combinations, even generally, because her concepts would then be purely
fictitious, and all her pretended <span class="T6">a priori</span> cognitions nothing
but common experiences marked with a false stamp. In plain language there is not, and
cannot be, any such thing as metaphysics at all.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn6" id="body_ftn6">6</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">However hasty and mistaken Hume's conclusion may appear, it was at
least founded upon investigation, and this investigation deserved the concentrated
attention of the brighter spirits of his day as well as determined efforts on their
part to discover, if possible, a happier solution of the problem in the sense proposed
by him, all of which would have speedily resulted in a complete reform of the
science.</p>
<p class="Standard">But Hume suffered the usual misfortune of metaphysicians, of not
being understood. It is positively painful to see how utterly his opponents, Reid,
Oswald, Beattie, and lastly Priestley, missed the point of the problem; for while they
were ever taking for granted that which he doubted, and demonstrating with zeal and
often with impudence that which he never thought of doubting, they so misconstrued his
valuable suggestion that everything remained in its old condition, as if nothing had
happened.</p>
<p class="Standard">The question was not whether the concept of cause was right,
useful, and even indispensable for our knowledge of nature, for this Hume had never
doubted; but whether that concept could be thought by reason <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, and consequently whether it possessed an inner truth, independent of all
experience, implying a wider application than merely to the objects of experience. This
was Hume's problem. It was a question concerning the origin, not concerning the
indispensable need of the concept. Were the former decided, the conditions of the use
and the sphere of its valid application would have been determined as a matter of
course.</p>
<p class="Standard">But to satisfy the conditions of the problem, the opponents of the
great thinker should have penetrated very deeply into the nature of reason, so far as
it is concerned with pure thinking,—a task which did not suit them. They found a more
convenient method of being defiant without any insight, viz., the appeal to
<span class="T6">common sense</span>. It is indeed a great gift of God, to possess
right, or (as they now call it) plain common sense. But this common sense must be shown
practically, by well-considered and reasonable thoughts and words, not by appealing to
it as an oracle, when no rational justification can be advanced. To appeal to common
sense, when insight and science fail, and no sooner—this is one of the subtile
discoveries of modern times, by means of which the most superficial ranter can safely
enter the lists with the most thorough thinker, and hold his own. But as long as a
particle of insight remains, no one would think of having recourse to this subterfuge.
For what is it but an appeal to the opinion of the multitude, of whose applause the
philosopher is ashamed, while the popular charlatan glories and confides in it? I
should think that Hume might fairly have laid as much claim to common sense as Beattie,
and in addition to a critical reason (such as the latter did not possess), which keeps
common sense in check and prevents it from speculating, or, if speculations are under
discussion, restrains the desire to decide because it cannot satisfy itself concerning
its own arguments. By this means alone can common sense remain sound. Chisels and
hammers may suffice to work a piece of wood, but for steel-engraving we require an
engraver's needle. Thus common sense and speculative understanding are each serviceable
in their own way, the former in judgments which apply immediately to experience, the
latter when we judge universally from mere concepts, as in metaphysics, where sound
common sense, so called in spite of the inapplicability of the word, has no right to
judge at all.</p>
<p class="Standard">I openly confess, the suggestion of David Hume was the very thing,
which many years ago first interrupted my dogmatic slumber, and gave my investigations
in the field of speculative philosophy quite a new direction. I was far from following
him in the conclusions at which he arrived by regarding, not the whole of his problem,
but a part, which by itself can give us no information. If we start from a
well-founded, but undeveloped, thought, which another has bequeathed to us, we may well
hope by continued reflection to advance farther than the acute man, to whom we owe the
first spark of light.</p>
<p class="Standard">I therefore first tried whether Hume's objection could not be put
into a general form, and soon found that the concept of the connexion of cause and
effect was by no means the only idea by which the understanding thinks the connexion of
things <span class="T6">a priori</span>, but rather that metaphysics consists
altogether of such connexions. I sought to ascertain their number, and when I had
satisfactorily succeeded in this by starting from a single principle, I proceeded to
the deduction of these concepts, which I was now certain were not deduced from
experience, as Hume had apprehended, but sprang from the pure understanding. This
deduction (which seemed impossible to my acute predecessor, which had never even
occurred to any one else, though no one had hesitated to use the concepts without
investigating the basis of their objective validity) was the most difficult task ever
undertaken in the service of metaphysics; and the worst was that metaphysics, such as
it then existed, could not assist me in the least, because this deduction alone can
render metaphysics possible. But as soon as I had succeeded in solving Hume's problem
not merely in a particular case, but with respect to the whole faculty of pure reason,
I could proceed safely, though slowly, to determine the whole sphere of pure reason
completely and from general principles, in its circumference as well as in its
contents. This was required for metaphysics in order to construct its system according
to a reliable method.</p>
<p class="Standard">But I fear that the execution of Hume's problem in its widest
extent (viz., my Critique of the Pure Reason) will fare as the problem itself fared,
when first proposed. It will be misjudged because it is misunderstood, and
misunderstood because men choose to skim through the book, and not to think through
it—a disagreeable task, because the work is dry, obscure, opposed to all ordinary
notions, and moreover long-winded. I confess, however, I did not expect to hear from
philosophers complaints of want of popularity, entertainment, and facility, when the
existence of a highly prized and indispensable cognition is at stake, which cannot be
established otherwise than by the strictest rules of methodic precision. Popularity may
follow, but is inadmissible at the beginning. Yet as regards a certain obscurity,
arising partly from the diffuseness of the plan, owing to which the principal points of
the investigation are easily lost sight of, the complaint is just, and I intend to
remove it by the present Prolegomena.</p>
<p class="Standard">The first-mentioned work, which discusses the pure faculty of
reason in its whole compass and bounds, will remain the foundation, to which the
Prolegomena, as a preliminary exercise, refer; for our critique must first be
established as a complete and perfected science, before we can think of letting
Metaphysics appear on the scene, or even have the most distant hope of attaining
it.</p>
<p class="Standard">We have been long accustomed to seeing antiquated knowledge
produced as new by taking it out of its former context, and reducing it to system in a
new suit of any fancy pattern under new titles. Most readers will set out by expecting
nothing else from the Critique; but these Prolegomena may persuade him that it is a
perfectly new science, of which no one has ever even thought, the very idea of which
was unknown, and for which nothing hitherto accomplished can be of the smallest use,
except it be the suggestion of Hume's doubts. Yet ever, he did not suspect such a
formal science, but ran his ship ashore, for safety's sake, landing on scepticism,
there to let it lie and rot; whereas my object is rather to give it a pilot, who, by
means of safe astronomical principles drawn from a knowledge of the globe, and provided
with a complete chart and compass, may steer the ship safely, whither he listeth.</p>
<p class="Standard">If in a new science, which is wholly isolated and unique in its
kind, we started with the prejudice that we can judge of things by means of our
previously acquired knowledge, which is precisely what has first to be called in
question, we should only fancy we saw everywhere what we had already known, the
expressions, having a similar sound, only that all would appear utterly metamorphosed,
senseless and unintelligible, because we should have as a foundation our own notions,
made by long habit a second nature, instead of the author's. But the longwindedness of
the work, so far as it depends on the subject, and not the exposition, its consequent
unavoidable dryness and its scholastic precision are qualities which can only benefit
the science, though they may discredit the book.</p>
<p class="Standard">Few writers are gifted with the subtilty, and at the same time with
the grace, of David Hume, or with the depth, as well as the elegance, of Moses
Mendelssohn. Yet I flatter myself I might have made my own exposition popular, had my
object been merely to sketch out a plan and leave its completion to others, instead of
having my heart in the welfare of the science, to which I had devoted myself so long;
in truth, it required no little constancy, and even self-denial, to postpone the sweets
of an immediate success to the prospect of a slower, but more lasting, reputation.</p>
<p class="Standard">Making plans is often the occupation of an opulent and boastful
mind, which thus obtains the reputation of a creative genius, by demanding what it
cannot itself supply; by censuring, what it cannot improve; and by proposing, what it
knows not where to find. And yet something more should belong to a sound plan of a
general critique of pure reason than mere conjectures, if this plan is to be other than
the usual declamations of pious aspirations. But pure reason is a sphere so separate
and self-contained, that we cannot touch a part without affecting all the rest. We can
therefore do nothing without first determining the position of each part, and its
relation to the rest; for, as our judgment cannot be corrected by anything without, the
validity and use of every part depends upon the relation in which it stands to all the
rest within the domain of reason.</p>
<p class="Standard">So in the structure of an organized body, the end of each member
can only be deduced from the full conception of the whole. It may, then, be said of
such a critique that it is never trustworthy except it be perfectly complete, down to
the smallest elements of pure reason. In the sphere of this faculty you can determine
either everything or nothing.</p>
<p class="Standard">But although a mere sketch, preceding the Critique of Pure Reason,
would be unintelligible, unreliable, and useless, it is all the more useful as a
sequel. For so we are able to grasp the whole, to examine in detail the chief points of
importance in the science, and to improve in many respects our exposition, as compared
with the first execution of the work.</p>
<p class="Standard">
After the completion of the work I offer here such a plan which is sketched out after
an analytical method, while the work itself had to be executed in the synthetical
style, in order that the science may present all its articulations, as the structure
of a peculiar cognitive faculty, in their natural combination. But should any reader
find this plan, which I publish as the Prolegomena to any future Metaphysics, still
obscure, let him consider that not every one is bound to study Metaphysics, that many
minds will succeed very well, in the exact and even in deep sciences, more closely
allied to practical experience,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn7" id="body_ftn7">7</SPAN></sup> while they cannot succeed in
investigations dealing exclusively with abstract concepts. In such cases men should
apply their talents to other subjects. But he who undertakes to judge, or still more,
to construct, a system of Metaphysics, must satisfy the demands here made, either by
adopting my solution, or by thoroughly refuting it, and substituting another. To
evade it is impossible.</p>
<p class="Standard">In conclusion, let it be remembered that this much-abused obscurity
(frequently serving as a mere pretext under which people hide their own indolence or
dullness) has its uses, since all who in other sciences observe a judicious silence,
speak authoritatively in metaphysics and make bold decisions, because their ignorance
is not here contrasted with the knowledge of others. Yet it does contrast with sound
critical principles, which we may therefore commend in the words of Virgil:</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">"Ignavum, fucos, pecus a praesepibus arcent."</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">"Bees are defending their hives against drones, those indolent
creatures."</p>
<h1><SPAN name="__RefHeading___Toc3101" name="__RefHeading___Toc3101"></SPAN>PROLEGOMENA.</h1>
<h2>PREAMBLE ON THE PECULIARITIES OF ALL METAPHYSICAL COGNITION.</h2>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">§ 1. <span class="T6">Of the
Sources of Metaphysics</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">IF it becomes desirable to formulate any cognition as science, it
will be necessary first to determine accurately those peculiar features which no other
science has in common with it, constituting its characteristics; otherwise the
boundaries of all sciences become confused, and none of them can be treated thoroughly
according to its nature.</p>
<p class="Standard">The characteristics of a science may consist of a simple difference
of object, or of the sources of cognition, or of the kind of cognition, or perhaps of
all three conjointly. On this, therefore, depends the idea of a possible science and
its territory.</p>
<p class="Standard">First, as concerns the sources of metaphysical cognition, its very
concept implies that they cannot be empirical. Its principles (including not only its
maxims but its basic notions) must never be derived from experience. It must not be
physical but metaphysical knowledge, viz., knowledge lying beyond experience. It can
therefore have for its basis neither external experience, which is the source of
physics proper, nor internal, which is the basis of empirical psychology. It is
therefore <span class="T6">a priori</span> knowledge, coming from pure Understanding
and pure Reason.</p>
<p class="Standard">But so far Metaphysics would not be distinguish able from pure
Mathematics; it must therefore be called pure philosophical cognition; and for the
meaning of this term I refer to the Critique of the Pure Reason (II. "Method of
Transcendentalism," Chap. I., Sec. i), where the distinction between these two
employments of the reason is sufficiently explained. So far concerning the sources of
metaphysical cognition.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">§ 2. <span class="T6">Concerning the Kind of Cognition which can
alone be called Metaphysical.</span></p>
<p class="Standard"><span class="T6">a.</span> <span class="T6">Of the
Distinction between Analytical and Synthetical Judgments in general.</span>—The
peculiarity of its sources demands that metaphysical cognition must consist of nothing
but <span class="T6">a priori</span> judgments. But whatever be their origin, or their
logical form, there is a distinction in judgments, as to their content, according to
which they are either merely explicative, adding nothing to the content of the
cognition, or expansive, increasing the given cognition: the former may be called
analytical, the latter synthetical, judgments.</p>
<p class="Standard">Analytical judgments express nothing in the predicate but what has
been already actually thought in the concept of the subject, though not so distinctly
or with the same (full) consciousness. When I say: All bodies are extended, I have not
amplified in the least my concept of body, but have only analysed it, as extension was
really thought to belong to that concept before the judgment was made, though it was
not expressed; this judgment is therefore analytical. On the contrary, this judgment,
All bodies have weight, contains in its predicate something not actually thought in the
general concept of the body; it amplifies my knowledge by adding something to my
concept, and must therefore be called synthetical.</p>
<p class="Standard"><span class="T6">b. The Common Principle of all Analytical
Judgments is the Law of Contradiction.</span>—All analytical judgments depend wholly on
the law of Contradiction, and are in their nature <span class="T6">a priori</span>
cognitions, whether the concepts that supply them with matter be empirical or not. For
the predicate of an affirmative analytical judgment is already contained in the concept
of the subject, of which it cannot be denied without contradiction. In the same way its
opposite is necessarily denied of the subject in an analytical, but negative, judgment,
by the same law of contradiction. Such is the nature of the judgments: all bodies are
extended, and no bodies are unextended (i.e., simple).</p>
<p class="Standard">For this very reason all analytical judgments are <span class="T6">a priori</span> even when the concepts are empirical, as, for example, Gold is a
yellow metal; for to know this I require no experience beyond my concept of gold as a
yellow metal: it is, in fact, the very concept, and I need only analyse it, without
looking beyond it elsewhere.</p>
<p class="Standard"><span class="T6">c. Synthetical Judgments require a different
Principle from the Law of Contradiction.</span>—There are synthetical <span class="T6">a posteriori</span> judgments of empirical origin; but there are also others which
are proved to be certain <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and which spring from pure
Understanding and Reason. Yet they both agree in this, that they cannot possibly spring
from the principle of analysis, viz., the law of contradiction, alone; they require a
quite different principle, though, from whatever they may be deduced, they must be
subject to the law of contradiction, which must never be violated, even though
everything cannot be deduced from it. I shall first classify synthetical judgments.</p>
<p class="Standard">1. <span class="T6">Empirical Judgments</span> are always
synthetical. For it would be absurd to base an analytical judgment on experience, as
our concept suffices for the purpose without requiring any testimony from experience.
That body is extended, is a judgment established <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and
not an empirical judgment. For before appealing to experience, we already have all the
conditions of the judgment in the concept, from which we have but to elicit the
predicate according to the law of contradiction, and thereby to become conscious of the
necessity of the judgment, which experience could not even teach us.</p>
<p class="Standard">2. <span class="T6">Mathematical Judgments</span> are all
synthetical. This fact seems hitherto to have altogether escaped the observation of
those who have analysed human reason; it even seems directly opposed to all their
conjectures, though incontestably certain, and most important in its consequences. For
as it was found that the conclusions of mathematicians all proceed according to the law
of contradiction (as is demanded by all apodeictic certainty), men persuaded themselves
that the fundamental principles were known from the same law. This was a great mistake,
for a synthetical proposition can indeed be comprehended according to the law of
contradiction, but only by presupposing another synthetical proposition from which it
follows, but never in itself.</p>
<p class="Standard">First of all, we must observe that all proper mathematical
judgments are <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and not empirical, because they carry
with them necessity, which cannot be obtained from experience. But if this be not
conceded to me, very good; I shall confine my assertion to <span class="T6">pure
Mathematics</span>, the very notion of which implies that it contains pure <span class="T6">a priori</span> and not empirical cognitions.</p>
<p class="Standard">It might at first be thought that the proposition 7 + 5 = 12 is a
mere analytical judgment, following from the concept of the sum of seven and five,
according to the law of contradiction. But on closer examination it appears that the
concept of the sum of 7 + 5 contains merely their union in a single number, without its
being at all thought what the particular number is that unites them. The concept of
twelve is by no means thought by merely thinking of the combination of seven and five;
and analyse this possible sum as we may, we shall not discover twelve in the concept.
We must go beyond these concepts, by calling to our aid some concrete image
(<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>), i.e., either our five fingers, or five points (as
Segner has it in his Arithmetic), and we must add successively the units of the five,
given in some concrete image (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>), to the concept of
seven. Hence our concept is really amplified by the proposition 7 + 5 = 12, and we add
to the first a second, not thought in it. Arithmetical judgments are therefore
synthetical, and the more plainly according as we take larger numbers; for in such
cases it is clear that, however closely we analyse our concepts without calling visual
images (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>) to our aid, we can never find the sum by
such mere dissection.</p>
<p class="Standard">All principles of geometry are no less analytical. That a straight
line is the shortest path between two points, is a synthetical proposition. For my
concept of straight contains nothing of quantity, but only a quality. The attribute of
shortness is therefore altogether additional, and cannot be obtained by any analysis of
the concept. Here, too, visualisation (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>) must come to
aid us. It alone makes the synthesis possible.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Some other principles, assumed by geometers, are indeed actually analytical, and
depend on the law of contradiction; but they only serve, as identical propositions,
as a method of concatenation, and not as principles, e.g., a = a, the whole is equal
to itself, or a + b > a, the whole is greater than its part. And yet even these,
though they are recognised as valid from mere concepts, are only admitted in
mathematics, because they can be represented in some visual form (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>). What usually makes us believe that the predicate of such
apodeictic<sup><SPAN href="#ftn8" id="body_ftn8">8</SPAN></sup> judgments is already contained in our
concept, and that the judgment is therefore analytical, is the duplicity of the
expression, requesting us to think a certain predicate as of necessity implied in the
thought of a given concept, which necessity attaches to the concept. But the question
is not what we are requested to join in thought <span class="T6">to</span> the given
concept, but what we actually think together with and in it, though obscurely; and so
it appears that the predicate belongs to these concepts necessarily indeed, yet not
directly but indirectly by an added visualisation (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>).</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">§ 3. <span class="T6">A Remark on the General Division of
Judgments into Analytical and Synthetical.</span></p>
<p class="Standard">This division is indispensable, as concerns the Critique of human
understanding, and therefore deserves to be called classical, though otherwise it is of
little use, but this is the reason why dogmatic philosophers, who always seek the
sources of metaphysical judgments in Metaphysics itself, and not apart from it, in the
pure laws of reason generally, altogether neglected this apparently obvious
distinction. Thus the celebrated Wolf, and his acute follower Baumgarten, came to seek
the proof of the principle of Sufficient Reason, which is clearly synthetical, in the
principle of Contradiction. In Locke's Essay, however, I find an indication of my
division. For in the fourth book (chap. iii. § 9, seq.), having discussed the
various connexions of representations in judgments, and their sources, one of which he
makes "identity and contradiction" (analytical judgments), and another the coexistence
of representations in a subject, he confesses (§ 10) that our <span class="T6">a
priori</span> knowledge of the latter is very narrow, and almost nothing. But in his
remarks on this species of cognition, there is so little of what is definite, and
reduced to rules, that we cannot wonder if no one, not even Hume, was led to make
investigations concerning this sort of judgments. For such general and yet definite
principles are not easily learned from other men, who have had them obscurely in their
minds. We must hit on them first by our own reflexion, then we find them elsewhere,
where we could not possibly have found them at first, because the authors themselves
did not know that such an idea lay at the basis of their observations. Men who never
think independently have nevertheless the acuteness to discover everything, after it
has been once shown them, in what was said long since, though no one ever saw it there
before.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">§ 4. <span class="T6">The General Question of the
Prolegomena.—Is Metaphysics at all Possible?</span></p>
<p class="Standard">Were a metaphysics, which could maintain its place as a science,
really in existence; could we say, here is metaphysics, learn it, and it will convince
you irresistibly and irrevocably of its truth: this question would be useless, and
there would only remain that other question (which would rather be a test of our
acuteness, than a proof of the existence of the thing itself), "How is the science
possible, and how does reason come to attain it?" But human reason has not been so
fortunate in this case. There is no single book to which you can point as you do to
Euclid, and say: This is Metaphysics; here you may find the noblest objects of this
science, the knowledge of a highest Being, and of a future existence, proved from
principles of pure reason. We can be shown indeed many judgments, demonstrably certain,
and never questioned; but these are all analytical, and rather concern the materials
and the scaffolding for Metaphysics, than the extension of knowledge, which is our
proper object in studying it (§ 2). Even supposing you produce synthetical judgments
(such as the law of Sufficient Reason, which you have never proved, as you ought to,
from pure reason <span class="T6">a priori</span>, though we gladly concede its truth),
you lapse when they come to be employed for your principal object, into such doubtful
assertions, that in all ages one Metaphysics has contradicted another, either in its
assertions, or their proofs, and thus has itself destroyed its own claim to lasting
assent. Nay, the very attempts to set up such a science are the main cause of the early
appearance of scepticism, a mental attitude in which reason treats itself with such
violence that it could never have arisen save from complete despair of ever satisfying
our most important aspirations. For long before men began to inquire into nature
methodically, they consulted abstract reason, which had to some extent been exercised
by means of ordinary experience; for reason is ever present, while laws of nature must
usually be discovered with labor. So Metaphysics floated to the surface, like foam,
which dissolved the moment it was scooped off. But immediately there appeared a new
supply on the surface, to be ever eagerly gathered up by some, while others, instead of
seeking in the depths the cause of the phenomenon, thought they showed their wisdom by
ridiculing the idle labor of their neighbors.</p>
<p class="Standard">The essential and distinguishing feature of pure mathematical
cognition among all other <span class="T6">a priori</span> cognitions is, that it
cannot at all proceed from concepts, but only by means of the construction of concepts
(see Critique II., Method of Transcendentalism, chap. I., sect. 1). As therefore in its
judgments it must proceed beyond the concept to that which its corresponding
visualisation (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>) contains, these judgments neither
can, nor ought to, arise analytically, by dissecting the concept, but are all
synthetical.</p>
<p class="Standard">I cannot refrain from pointing out the disadvantage resulting to
philosophy from the neglect of this easy and apparently insignificant observation. Hume
being prompted (a task worthy of a philosopher) to cast his eye over the whole field of
<span class="T6">a priori</span> cognitions in which human understanding claims such
mighty possessions, heedlessly severed from it a whole, and indeed its most valuable,
province, viz., pure mathematics; for he thought its nature, or, so to speak, the
state-constitution of this empire, depended on totally different principles, namely, on
the law of contradiction alone; and although he did not divide Judgments in this manner
formally and universally as I have done here, what he said was equivalent to this: that
mathematics contains only analytical, but metaphysics synthetical, <span class="T6">a
priori</span> judgments. In this, however, he was greatly mistaken, and the mistake had
a decidedly injurious effect upon his whole conception. But for this, he would have
extended his question concerning the origin of our synthetical judgments far beyond the
metaphysical concept of Causality, and included in it the possibility of mathematics
<span class="T6">a priori</span> also, for this latter he must have assumed to be
equally synthetical. And then he could not have based his metaphysical judgments on
mere experience without subjecting the axioms of mathematics equally to experience, a
thing which he was far too acute to do. The good company into which metaphysics would
thus have been brought, would have saved it from the danger of a contemptuous
ill-treatment, for the thrust intended for it must have reached mathematics, which was
not and could not have been Hume's intention. Thus that acute man would have been led
into considerations which must needs be similar to those that now occupy us, but which
would have gained inestimably by his inimitably elegant style.</p>
<p class="Standard">Metaphysical judgments, properly so called, are all synthetical. We
must distinguish judgments pertaining to metaphysics from metaphysical judgments
properly so called. Many of the former are analytical, but they only afford the means
for metaphysical judgments, which are the whole end of the science, and which are
always synthetical. For if there be concepts pertaining to metaphysics (as, for
example, that of substance), the judgments springing from simple analysis of them also
pertain to metaphysics, as, for example, substance is that which only exists as
subject; and by means of several such analytical judgments, we seek to approach the
definition of the concept. But as the analysis of a pure concept of the understanding
pertaining to metaphysics, does not proceed in any different manner from the dissection
of any other, even empirical, concepts, not pertaining to metaphysics (such as: air is
an elastic fluid, the elasticity of which is not destroyed by any known degree of
cold), it follows that the concept indeed, but not the analytical judgment, is properly
metaphysical. This science has something peculiar in the production of its <span class="T6">a priori</span> cognitions, which must therefore be distinguished from the
features it has in common with other rational knowledge. Thus the judgment, that all
the substance in things is permanent, is a synthetical and properly metaphysical
judgment.</p>
<p class="Standard">If the <span class="T6">a priori</span> principles, which
constitute the materials of metaphysics, have first been collected according to fixed
principles, then their analysis will be of great value; it might be taught as a
particular part (as a <span class="T6">philosophia definitiva</span>), containing
nothing but analytical judgments pertaining to metaphysics, and could be treated
separately from the synthetical which constitute metaphysics proper. For indeed these
analyses are not elsewhere of much value, except in metaphysics, i.e., as regards the
synthetical judgments, which are to be generated by these previously analysed
concepts.</p>
<p class="Standard">The conclusion drawn in this section then is, that metaphysics is
properly concerned with synethetical propositions <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and
these alone constitute its end, for which it indeed requires various dissections of its
concepts, viz., of its analytical judgments, but wherein the procedure is not different
from that in every other kind of knowledge, in which we merely seek to render our
concepts distinct by analysis. But the generation of <span class="T6">a priori</span>
cognition by concrete images as well as by concepts, in fine of synthetical
propositions <span class="T6">a priori</span> in philosophical cognition, constitutes
the essential subject of Metaphysics.</p>
<p class="Standard">Weary therefore as well of dogmatism, which teaches us nothing, as
of scepticism, which does not even promise us anything, not even the quiet state of a
contented ignorance; disquieted by the importance of knowledge so much needed; and
lastly, rendered suspicious by long experience of all knowledge which we believe we
possess, or which offers itself, under the title of pure reason: there remains but one
critical question on the answer to which our future procedure depends, viz.,
<span class="T6">Is Metaphysics at all possible</span>? But this question must be
answered not by sceptical objections to the asseverations of some actual system of
metaphysics (for we do not as yet admit such a thing to exist), but from the
conception, as yet only problematical, of a science of this sort.</p>
<p class="Standard">In the <span class="T6">Critique of Pure Reason</span> I have
treated this question synthetically, by making inquiries into pure reason itself, and
endeavoring in this source to determine the elements as well as the laws of its pure
use according to principles. The task is difficult, and requires a resolute reader to
penetrate by degrees into a system, based on no data except reason itself, and which
therefore seeks, without resting upon any fact, to unfold knowledge from its original
germs. <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span>, however, are designed for preparatory
exercises; they are intended rather to point out what we have to do in order if
possible to actualise a science, than to propound it. They must therefore rest upon
something already known as trustworthy, from which we can set out with confidence, and
ascend to sources as yet unknown, the discovery of which will not only explain to us
what we knew, but exhibit a sphere of many cognitions which all spring from the same
sources. The method of <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span>, especially of those
designed as a preparation for future metaphysics, is consequently analytical.</p>
<p class="Standard">But it happens fortunately, that though we cannot assume
metaphysics to be an actual science, we can say with confidence that certain pure
<span class="T6">a priori</span> synthetical cognitions, pure Mathematics and pure
Physics are actual and given; for both contain propositions, which are thoroughly
recognised as apodeictically certain, partly by mere reason, partly by general consent
arising from experience, and yet as independent of experience. We have therefore some
at least uncontested synthetical knowledge <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and need
not ask <span class="T6">whether</span> it be possible, for it is actual, but
<span class="T6">how</span> it is possible, in order that we may deduce from the
principle which makes the given cognitions possible the possibility of all the
rest.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter"><span class="T6">The General Problem: How is Cognition from Pure Reason Possible?</span></p>
<p class="Standard">§ 5. We have above learned the significant distinction
between analytical and synthetical judgments. The possibility of analytical
propositions was easily comprehended, being entirely founded on the law of
Contradiction. The possibility of synthetical <span class="T6">a posteriori</span>
judgments, of those which are gathered from experience, also requires no particular
explanation; for experience is nothing but a continual synthesis of perceptions. There
remain therefore only synthetical propositions <span class="T6">a priori</span>, of
which the possibility must be sought or investigated, because they must depend upon
other principles than the law of contradiction.</p>
<p class="Standard">But here we need not first establish the possibility of such
propositions so as to ask whether they are possible. For there are enough of them which
indeed are of undoubted certainty, and as our present method is analytical, we shall
start from the fact, that such synthetical but purely rational cognition actually
exists; but we must now inquire into the reason of this possibility, and ask,
<span class="T6">how</span> such cognition is possible, in order that we may from the
principles of its possibility be enabled to determine the conditions of its use, its
sphere and its limits. The proper problem upon which all depends, when expressed with
scholastic precision, is therefore:</p>
<p class="Standard"><span class="T6">How are Synthetic Propositions a priori possible?</span></p>
<p class="Standard">
For the sake of popularity I have above expressed this problem somewhat differently,
as an inquiry into purely rational cognition, which I could do for once without
detriment to the desired comprehension, because, as we have only to do here with
metaphysics and its sources, the reader will, I hope, after the fore going remarks,
keep in mind that when we speak of purely rational cognition, we do not mean
analytical, but synthetical cognition.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn9" id="body_ftn9">9</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">Metaphysics stands or falls with the solution of this problem: its
very existence depends upon it. Let any one make metaphysical assertions with ever so
much plausibility, let him overwhelm us with conclusions, if he has not previously
proved able to answer this question satisfactorily, I have a right to say: this is all
vain baseless philosophy and false wisdom. You speak through pure reason, and claim, as
it were to create cognitions <span class="T6">a priori</span> by not only dissecting
given concepts, but also by asserting connexions which do not rest upon the law of
contradiction, and which you believe you conceive quite independently of all
experience; how do you arrive at this, and how will you justify your pretensions? An
appeal to the consent of the common sense of mankind cannot be allowed; for that is a
witness whose authority depends merely upon rumor. Says Horace:</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">"Quodcunque ostendis mihi sic, incredulus odi."</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">"To all that which thou provest me thus, I refuse to give
credence."</p>
<p class="Standard">The answer to this question, though indispensable, is difficult;
and though the principal reason that it was not made long ago is, that the possibility
of the question never occurred to anybody, there is yet another reason, which is this
that a satisfactory answer to this one question requires a much more persistent,
profound, and painstaking reflexion, than the most diffuse work on Metaphysics, which
on its first appearance promised immortality to its author. And every intelligent
reader, when he carefully reflects what this problem requires, must at first be struck
with its difficulty, and would regard it as insoluble and even impossible, did there
not actually exist pure synthetical cognitions <span class="T6">a priori</span>. This
actually happened to David Hume, though he did not conceive the question in its entire
universality as is done here, and as must be done, should the answer be decisive for
all Metaphysics. For how is it possible, says that acute man, that when a concept is
given me, I can go beyond it and connect with it another, which is not contained in it,
in such a manner as if the latter necessarily belonged to the former? Nothing but
experience can furnish us with such connexions (thus he concluded from the difficulty
which he took to be an impossibility), and all that vaunted necessity, or, what is the
same thing, all cognition assumed to be <span class="T6">a priori</span>, is nothing
but a long habit of accepting something as true, and hence of mistaking subjective
necessity for objective.</p>
<p class="Standard">Should my reader complain of the difficulty and the trouble which I
occasion him in the solution of this problem, he is at liberty to solve it himself in
an easier way. Perhaps he will then feel under obligation to the person who has
undertaken for him a labor of so profound research, and will rather be surprised at the
facility with which, considering the nature of the subject, the solution has been
attained. Yet it has cost years of work to solve the problem in its whole universality
(using the term in the mathematical sense, viz., for that which is sufficient for all
cases), and finally to exhibit it in the analytical form, as the reader finds it
here.</p>
<p class="Standard">All metaphysicians are therefore solemnly and legally suspended
from their occupations till they shall have answered in a satisfactory manner the
question, "How are synthetic cognitions <span class="T6">a priori</span> possible?" For
the answer contains which they must show when they have anything to offer in the name
of pure reason. But if they do not possess these credentials, they can expect nothing
else of reasonable people, who have been deceived so often, than to be dismissed
without further ado.</p>
<p class="Standard">If they on the other hand desire to carry on their business, not as
a science, but as an art of wholesome oratory suited to the common sense of man, they
cannot in justice be prevented. They will then speak the modest language of a rational
belief, they will grant that they are not allowed even to conjecture, far less to know,
anything which lies beyond the bounds of all possible experience, but only to assume
(not for speculative use, which they must abandon, but for practical purposes only) the
existence of something that is possible and even indispensable for the guidance of the
understanding and of the will in life. In this manner alone can they be called useful
and wise men, and the more so as they renounce the title of metaphysicians; for the
latter profess to be speculative philosophers, and since, when judgments <span class="T6">a priori</span> are under discussion, poor probabilities cannot be admitted (for
what is declared to be known <span class="T6">a priori</span> is thereby announced as
necessary), such men cannot be permitted to play with conjectures, but their assertions
must be either science, or are worth nothing at all.</p>
<p class="Standard">It may be said, that the entire transcendental philosophy, which
necessarily precedes all metaphysics, is nothing but the complete solution of the
problem here propounded, in systematical order and completeness, and hitherto we have
never had any transcendental philosophy; for what goes by its name is properly a part
of metaphysics, whereas the former science is intended first to constitute the
possibility of the latter, and must therefore precede all metaphysics. And it is not
surprising that when a whole science, deprived of all help from other sciences, and
consequently in itself quite new, is required to answer a single question
satisfactorily, we should find the answer troublesome and difficult, nay even shrouded
in obscurity.</p>
<p class="Standard">As we now proceed to this solution according to the analytical
method, in which we assume that such cognitions from pure reasons actually exist, we
can only appeal to two sciences of theoretical cognition (which alone is under
consideration here), pure mathematics and pure natural science (physics). For these
alone can exhibit to us objects in a definite and actualisable form (<span class="T6">in der Anschauung</span>), and consequently (if there should occur in them a
cognition <span class="T6">a priori</span>) can show the truth or conformity of the
cognition to the object <span class="T6">in concreto</span>, that is, its actuality,
from which we could proceed to the reason of its possibility by the analytic method.
This facilitates our work greatly for here universal considerations are not only
applied to facts, but even start from them, while in a synthetic procedure they must
strictly be derived <span class="T6">in abstracto</span> from concepts.</p>
<p class="Standard">But, in order to rise from these actual and at the same time
well-grounded pure cognitions <span class="T6">a priori</span> to such a possible
cognition of the same as we are seeking, viz., to metaphysics as a science, we must
comprehend that which occasions it, I mean the mere natural, though in spite of its
truth not unsuspected, cognition <span class="T6">a priori</span> which lies at the
bottom of that science, the elaboration of which without any critical investigation of
its possibility is commonly called metaphysics. In a word, we must comprehend the
natural conditions of such a science as a part of our inquiry, and thus the
transcendental problem will be gradually answered by a division into four
questions:</p>
<p class="StandardNoSpaceFirst">1. <span class="T6">How is pure mathematics
possible?</span></p>
<p class="StandardNoSpace">2. <span class="T6">How is pure natural science
possible?</span></p>
<p class="StandardNoSpace">3. <span class="T6">How is metaphysics in general
possible?</span></p>
<p class="StandardNoSpaceLast">4. <span class="T6">How is metaphysics as a science
possible?</span></p>
<p class="Standard">It may be seen that the solution of these problems, though chiefly
designed to exhibit the essential matter of the Critique, has yet something peculiar,
which for itself alone deserves attention. This is the search for the sources of given
sciences in reason itself, so that its faculty of knowing something <span class="T6">a
priori</span> may by its own deeds be investigated and measured. By this procedure
these sciences gain, if not with regard to their contents, yet as to their proper use,
and while they throw light on the higher question concerning their common origin, they
give, at the same time, an occasion better to explain their own nature.</p>
<h1><SPAN name="__RefHeading___Toc3103" name="__RefHeading___Toc3103"></SPAN>FIRST PART OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL PROBLEM.</h1>
<h2>HOW IS PURE MATHEMATICS POSSIBLE?</h2>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">§ 6.</p>
<p class="Standard">HERE is a great and established branch of knowledge, encompassing
even now a wonderfully large domain and promising an unlimited extension in the future.
Yet it carries with it thoroughly apodeictical certainty, i.e., absolute necessity,
which therefore rests upon no empirical grounds. Consequently it is a pure product of
reason, and moreover is thoroughly synthetical. [Here the question arises:]</p>
<p class="Standard">"How then is it possible for human reason to produce a cognition of
this nature entirely <span class="T6">a priori</span>?"</p>
<p class="Standard">Does not this faculty [which produces mathematics], as it neither
is nor can be based upon experience, presuppose some ground of cognition <span class="T6">a priori</span>, which lies deeply hidden, but which might reveal itself by these
its effects, if their first beginnings were but diligently ferreted out?</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 7. But we find that all mathematical cognition has this
peculiarity: it must first exhibit its concept in a visual form (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>) and indeed <span class="T6">a priori</span>, therefore in a
visual form which is not empirical, but pure. Without this mathematics cannot take a
single step; hence its judgments are always visual, viz., "intuitive"; whereas
philosophy must be satisfied with discursive judgments from mere concepts, and though
it may illustrate its doctrines through a visual figure, can never derive them from it.
This observation on the nature of mathematics gives us a clue to the first and highest
condition of its possibility, which is, that some non-sensuous visualisation (called
pure intuition, or <span class="T6">reine Anschauung</span>) must form its basis, in
which all its concepts can be exhibited or constructed, <span class="T6">in
concreto</span> and yet <span class="T6">a priori</span>. If we can find out this pure
intuition and its possibility, we may thence easily explain how synthetical
propositions <span class="T6">a priori</span> are possible in pure mathematics, and
consequently how this science itself is possible. Empirical intuition [viz.,
sense-perception] enables us without difficulty to enlarge the concept which we frame
of an object of intuition [or sense-perception], by new predicates, which intuition
[i.e., sense-perception] itself presents synthetically in experience. Pure intuition
[viz., the visualisation of forms in our imagination, from which every thing sensual,
i.e., every thought of material qualities, is excluded] does so likewise, only with
this difference, that in the latter case the synthetical judgment is <span class="T6">a
priori</span> certain and apodeictical, in the former, only <span class="T6">a
posteriori</span> and empirically certain; because this latter contains only that which
occurs in contingent empirical intuition, but the former, that which must necessarily
be discovered in pure intuition. Here intuition, being an intuition <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, is <span class="T6">before all experience</span>, viz., before any
perception of particular objects, inseparably conjoined with its concept.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 8. But with this step our perplexity seems rather to
increase than to lessen. For the question now is, "How is it possible to intuite [in a
visual form] anything <span class="T6">a priori</span>?" An intuition [viz., a visual
sense-perception] is such a representation as immediately depends upon the presence of
the object. Hence it seems impossible to intuite from the outset <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, because intuition would in that event take place without either a former
or a present object to refer to, and by consequence could not be intuition. Concepts
indeed are such, that we can easily form some of them <span class="T6">a priori</span>,
viz., such as contain nothing but the thought of an object in general; and we need not
find ourselves in an immediate relation to the object. Take, for instance, the concepts
of Quantity, of Cause, etc. But even these require, in order to make them under stood,
a certain concrete use—that is, an application to some sense-experience (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>), by which an object of them is given us. But how can the
intuition of the object [its visualisation] precede the object itself?</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 9. If our intuition [i.e., our sense-experience] were
perforce of such a nature as to represent things as they are in themselves, there would
not be any intuition <span class="T6">a priori</span>, but intuition would be always
empirical. For I can only know what is contained in the object in itself when it is
present and given to me. It is indeed even then incomprehensible how the visualising
(<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>) of a present thing should make me know this thing
as it is in itself, as its properties cannot migrate into my faculty of representation.
But even granting this possibility, a visualising of that sort would not take place
<span class="T6">a priori</span>, that is, before the object were presented to me; for
without this latter fact no reason of a relation between my representation and the
object can be imagined, unless it depend upon a direct inspiration.</p>
<p class="Standard">Therefore in one way only can my intuition (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>) anticipate the actuality of the object, and be a cognition
<span class="T6">a priori</span>, viz.: if my intuition contains nothing but the form
of sensibility, antedating in my subjectivity all the actual impressions through which
I am affected by objects.</p>
<p class="Standard">
For that objects of sense can only be intuited according to this form of sensibility
I can know <span class="T6">a priori</span>. Hence it follows: that
propositions, which concern this form of sensuous intuition only, are possible and
valid for objects of the senses; as also, conversely, that intuitions which are
possible <span class="T6">a priori</span> can never concern any other things than
objects of our senses.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn10" id="body_ftn10">10</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">§ 10. Accordingly, it is only the form of the sensuous
intuition by which we can intuite things <span class="T6">a priori</span>, but by which
we can know objects only as they <span class="T6">appear</span> to us (to our senses),
not as they are in themselves; and this assumption is absolutely necessary if
synthetical propositions <span class="T6">a priori</span> be granted as possible, or
if, in case they actually occur, their possibility is to be comprehended and determined
beforehand.</p>
<p class="Standard">Now, the intuitions which pure mathematics lays at the foundation
of all its cognitions and judgments which appear at once apodeictic and necessary are
Space and Time. For mathematics must first have all its concepts in intuition, and pure
mathematics in pure intuition, that is, it must construct them. If it proceeded in any
other way, it would be impossible to make any headway, for mathematics proceeds, not
analytically by dissection of concepts, but synthetically, and if pure intuition be
wanting, there is nothing in which the matter for synthetical judgments <span class="T6">a priori</span> can be given. Geometry is based upon the pure intuition of space.
Arithmetic accomplishes its concept of number by the successive addition of units in
time; and pure mechanics especially cannot attain its concepts of motion without
employing the representation of time. Both representations, however, are only
intuitions; for if we omit from the empirical intuitions of bodies and their
alterations (motion) everything empirical, or belonging to sensation, space and time
still remain, which are therefore pure intuitions that lie <span class="T6">a
priori</span> at the basis of the empirical. Hence they can never be omitted, but at
the same time, by their being pure intuitions <span class="T6">a priori</span>, they
prove that they are mere forms of our sensibility, which must precede all empirical
intuition, or perception of actual objects, and conformably to which objects can be
known <span class="T6">a priori</span>, but only as they appear to us.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 11. The problem of the present section is therefore solved.
Pure mathematics, as synthetical cognition <span class="T6">a priori</span>, is only
possible by referring to no other objects than those of the senses. At the basis of
their empirical intuition lies a pure intuition (of space and of time) which is
<span class="T6">a priori</span>. This is possible, because the latter intuition is
nothing but the mere form of sensibility, which precedes the actual appearance of the
objects, in that it, in fact, makes them possible. Yet this faculty of intuiting
<span class="T6">a priori</span> affects not the matter of the phenomenon (that is, the
sense-element in it, for this constitutes that which is empirical), but its form, viz.,
space and time. Should any man venture to doubt that these are determinations adhering
not to things in themselves, but to their relation to our sensibility, I should be glad
to know how it can be possible to know the constitution of things <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, viz., before we have any acquaintance with them and before they are
presented to us. Such, however, is the case with space and time. But this is quite
comprehensible as soon as both count for nothing more than formal conditions of our
sensibility, while the objects count merely as phenomena; for then the form of the
phenomenon, i.e., pure intuition, can by all means be represented as proceeding from
ourselves, that is, <span class="T6">a priori</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 12. In order to add something by way of illustration and
confirmation, we need only watch the ordinary and necessary procedure of geometers. All
proofs of the complete congruence of two given figures (where the one can in every
respect be substituted for the other) come ultimately to this that they may be made to
coincide; which is evidently nothing else than a synthetical proposition resting upon
immediate intuition, and this intuition must be pure, or given <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, otherwise the proposition could not rank as apodeictically certain, but
would have empirical certainty only. In that case, it could only be said that it is
always found to be so, and holds good only as far as our perception reaches. That
everywhere space (which [in its entirety] is itself no longer the boundary of another
space) has three dimensions, and that space cannot in any way have more, is based on
the proposition that not more than three lines can intersect at right angles in one
point; but this proposition cannot by any means be shown from concepts, but rests
immediately on intuition, and indeed on pure and <span class="T6">a priori</span>
intuition, because it is apodeictically certain. That we can require a line to be drawn
to infinity (<span class="T6">in indefinitum</span>), or that a series of changes (for
example, spaces traversed by motion) shall be infinitely continued, presupposes a
representation of space and time, which can only attach to intuition, namely, so far as
it in itself is bounded by nothing, for from concepts it could never be inferred.
Consequently, the basis of mathematics actually are pure intuitions, which make its
synthetical and apodeictically valid propositions possible. Hence our transcendental
deduction of the notions of space and of time explains at the same time the possibility
of pure mathematics. Without some such deduction its truth may be granted, but its
existence could by no means be understood, and we must assume "that everything which
can be given to our senses (to the external senses in space, to the internal one in
time) is intuited by us as it appears to us, not as it is in itself."</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 13. Those who cannot yet rid themselves of the notion that
space and time are actual qualities inhering in things in themselves, may exercise
their acumen on the following paradox. When they have in vain attempted its solution,
and are free from prejudices at least for a few moments, they will suspect that the
degradation of space and of time to mere forms of our sensuous intuition may perhaps be
well founded.</p>
<p class="Standard">If two things are quite equal in all respects as much as can be
ascertained by all means possible, quantitatively and qualitatively, it must follow,
that the one can in all cases and under all circumstances replace the other, and this
substitution would not occasion the least perceptible difference. This in fact is true
of plane figures in geometry; but some spherical figures exhibit, notwithstanding a
complete internal agreement, such a contrast in their external relation, that the one
figure cannot possibly be put in the place of the other. For instance, two spherical
triangles on opposite hemispheres, which have an arc of the equator as their common
base, may be quite equal, both as regards sides and angles, so that nothing is to be
found in either, if it be described for itself alone and completed, that would not
equally be applicable to both; and yet the one cannot be put in the place of the other
(being situated upon the opposite hemisphere). Here then is an internal difference
between the two triangles, which difference our understanding cannot describe as
internal, and which only manifests itself by external relations in space.</p>
<p class="Standard">But I shall adduce examples, taken from common life, that are more
obvious still.</p>
<p class="Standard">What can be more similar in every respect and in every part more
alike to my hand and to my ear, than their images in a mirror? And yet I cannot put
such a hand as is seen in the glass in the place of its archetype; for if this is a
right hand, that in the glass is a left one, and the image or reflexion of the right
ear is a left one which never can serve as a substitute for the other. There are in
this case no internal differences which our understanding could determine by thinking
alone. Yet the differences are internal as the senses teach, for, notwithstanding their
complete equality and similarity, the left hand cannot be enclosed in the same bounds
as the right one (they are not congruent); the glove of one hand cannot be used for the
other. What is the solution? These objects are not representations of things as they
are in themselves, and as the pure understanding would cognise them, but sensuous
intuitions, that is, appearances, the possibility of which rests upon the relation of
certain things unknown in themselves to something else, viz., to our sensibility. Space
is the form of the external intuition of this sensibility, and the internal
determination of every space is only possible by the determination of its external
relation to the whole space, of which it is a part (in other words, by its relation to
the external sense). That is to say, the part is only possible through the whole, which
is never the case with things in themselves, as objects of the mere understanding, but
with appearances only. Hence the difference between similar and equal things, which are
yet not congruent (for instance, two symmetric helices), cannot be made intelligible by
any concept, but only by the relation to the right and the left hands which immediately
refers to intuition.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter"><SPAN name="Page40" name="Page40"></SPAN>Remark I.</p>
<p class="Standard">Pure Mathematics, and especially pure geometry, can only have
objective reality on condition that they refer to objects of sense. But in regard to
the latter the principle holds good, that our sense representation is not a
representation of things in themselves, but of the way in which they appear to us.
Hence it follows, that the propositions of geometry are not the results of a mere
creation of our poetic imagination, and that therefore they cannot be referred with
assurance to actual objects; but rather that they are necessarily valid of space, and
consequently of all that may be found in space, because space is nothing else than the
form of all external appearances, and it is this form alone in which objects of sense
can be given. Sensibility, the form of which is the basis of geometry, is that upon
which the possibility of external appearance depends. Therefore these appearances can
never contain anything but what geometry prescribes to them.</p>
<p class="Standard">It would be quite otherwise if the senses were so constituted as to
represent objects as they are in themselves. For then it would not by any means follow
from the conception of space, which with all its properties serves to the geometer as
an <span class="T6">a priori</span> foundation, together with what is thence inferred,
must be so in nature. The space of the geometer would be considered a mere fiction, and
it would not be credited with objective validity, because we cannot see how things must
of necessity agree with an image of them, which we make spontaneously and previous to
our acquaintance with them. But if this image, or rather this formal intuition, is the
essential property of our sensibility, by means of which alone objects are given to us,
and if this sensibility represents not things in themselves, but their appearances: we
shall easily comprehend, and at the same time indisputably prove, that all external
objects of our world of sense must necessarily coincide in the most rigorous way with
the propositions of geometry; because sensibility by means of its form of external
intuition, viz., by space, the same with which the geometer is occupied, makes those
objects at all possible as mere appearances.</p>
<p class="Standard">It will always remain a remarkable phenomenon in the history of
philosophy, that there was a time, when even mathematicians, who at the same time were
philosophers, began to doubt, not of the accuracy of their geometrical propositions so
far as they concerned space, but of their objective validity and the applicability of
this concept itself, and of all its corollaries, to nature. They showed much concern
whether a line in nature might not consist of physical points, and consequently that
true space in the object might consist of simple [discrete] parts, while the space
which the geometer has in his mind [being continuous] cannot be such. They did not
recognise that this mental space renders possible the physical space, i.e., the
extension of matter; that this pure space is not at all a quality of things in
themselves, but a form of our sensuous faculty of representation; and that all objects
in space are mere appearances, i.e., not things in themselves but representations of
our sensuous intuition. But such is the case, for the space of the geometer is exactly
the form of sensuous intuition which we find <span class="T6">a priori</span> in us,
and contains the ground of the possibility of all external appearances (according to
their form), and the latter must necessarily and most rigidly agree with the
propositions of the geometer, which he draws not from any fictitious concept, but from
the subjective basis of all external phenomena, which is sensibility itself. In this
and no other way can geometry be made secure as to the undoubted objective reality of
its propositions against all the intrigues of a shallow Metaphysics, which is surprised
at them [the geometrical propositions], because it has not traced them to the sources
of their concepts.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">Remark II.</p>
<p class="Standard">Whatever is given us as object, must be given us in intuition. All
our intuition however takes place by means of the senses only; the understanding
intuites nothing, but only reflects. And as we have just shown that the senses never
and in no manner enable us to know things in themselves, but only their appearances,
which are mere representations of the sensibility, we conclude that 'all bodies,
together with the space in which they are, must be considered nothing but mere
representations in us, and exist nowhere but in our thoughts.' You will say: Is not
this manifest idealism?</p>
<p class="Standard">Idealism consists in the assertion, that there are none but
thinking beings, all other things, which we think are perceived in intuition, being
nothing but representations in the thinking beings, to which no object external to them
corresponds in fact. Whereas I say, that things as objects of our senses existing
outside us are given, but we know nothing of what they may be in themselves, knowing
only their appearances, i.e., the representations which they cause in us by affecting
our senses. Consequently I grant by all means that there are bodies without us, that
is, things which, though quite unknown to us as to what they are in themselves, we yet
know by the representations which their influence on our sensibility procures us, and
which we call bodies, a term signifying merely the appearance of the thing which is
unknown to us, but not therefore less actual. Can this be termed idealism? It is the
very contrary.</p>
<p class="Standard">Long before Locke's time, but assuredly since him, it has been
generally assumed and granted without detriment to the actual existence of external
things, that many of their predicates may be said to belong not to the things in
themselves, but to their appearances, and to have no proper existence outside our
representation. Heat, color, and taste, for instance, are of this kind. Now, if I go
farther, and for weighty reasons rank as mere appearances the remaining qualities of
bodies also, which are called primary, such as extension, place, and in general space,
with all that which belongs to it (impenetrability or materiality, space, etc.)—no one
in the least can adduce the reason of its being inadmissible. As little as the man who
admits colors not to be properties of the object in itself, but only as modifications
of the sense of sight, should on that account be called an idealist, so little can my
system be named idealistic, merely because I find that more, nay,</p>
<p class="Standard"><span class="T6">All the properties which constitute the intuition
of a body belong merely to its appearance</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">The existence of the thing that appears is thereby not destroyed,
as in genuine idealism, but it is only shown, that we cannot possibly know it by the
senses as it is in itself.</p>
<p class="Standard">I should be glad to know what my assertions must be in order to
avoid all idealism. Undoubtedly, I should say, that the representation of space is not
only perfectly conformable to the relation which our sensibility has to objects—that I
have said—but that it is quite similar to the object,—an assertion in which I can find
as little meaning as if I said that the sensation of red has a similarity to the
property of vermilion, which in me excites this sensation.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">Remark III.</p>
<p class="Standard">Hence we may at once dismiss an easily foreseen but futile
objection, "that by admitting the ideality of space and of time the whole sensible
world would be turned into mere sham." At first all philosophical insight into the
nature of sensuous cognition was spoiled, by making the sensibility merely a confused
mode of representation, according to which we still know things as they are, but
without being able to reduce everything in this our representation to a clear
consciousness; whereas proof is offered by us that sensibility consists, not in this
logical distinction of clearness and obscurity, but in the genetical one of the origin
of cognition itself. For sensuous perception represents things not at all as they are,
but only the mode in which they affect our senses, and consequently by sensuous
perception appearances only and not things themselves are given to the understanding
for reflexion. After this necessary corrective, an objection rises from an unpardonable
and almost intentional misconception, as if my doctrine turned all the things of the
world of sense into mere illusion.</p>
<p class="Standard">When an appearance is given us, we are still quite free as to how
we should judge the matter. The appearance depends upon the senses, but the judgment
upon the understanding, and the only question is, whether in the determination of the
object there is truth or not. But the difference between truth and dreaming is not
ascertained by the nature of the representations, which are referred to objects (for
they are the same in both cases), but by their connexion according to those rules,
which determine the coherence of the representations in the concept of an object, and
by ascertaining whether they can subsist together in experience or not. And it is not
the fault of the appearances if our cognition takes illusion for truth, i.e., if the
intuition, by which an object is given us, is considered a concept of the thing or of
its existence also, which the understanding can only think. The senses represent to us
the paths of the planets as now progressive, now retrogressive, and herein is neither
falsehood nor truth, because as long as we hold this path to be nothing but appearance,
we do not judge of the objective nature of their motion. But as a false judgment may
easily arise when the understanding is not on its guard against this subjective mode of
representation being considered objective, we say they appear to move backward; it is
not the senses however which must be charged with the illusion, but the understanding,
whose province alone it is to give an objective judgment on appearances.</p>
<p class="Standard">Thus, even if we did not at all reflect on the origin of our
representations, whenever we connect our intuitions of sense (whatever they may
contain), in space and in time, according to the rules of the coherence of all
cognition in experience, illusion or truth will arise according as we are negligent or
careful. It is merely a question of the use of sensuous representations in the
understanding, and not of their origin. In the same way, if I consider all the
representations of the senses, together with their form, space and time, to be nothing
but appearances, and space and time to be a mere form of the sensibility, which is not
to be met with in objects out of it, and if I make use of these representations in
reference to possible experience only, there is nothing in my regarding them as
appearances that can lead astray or cause illusion. For all that they can correctly
cohere according to rules of truth in experience. Thus all the propositions of geometry
hold good of space as well as of all the objects of the senses, consequently of all
possible experience, whether I consider space as a mere form of the sensibility, or as
something cleaving to the things themselves. In the former case however I comprehend
how I can know <span class="T6">a priori</span> these propositions concerning all the
objects of external intuition. Otherwise, everything else as regards all possible
experience remains just as if I had not departed from the vulgar view.</p>
<p class="Standard">But if I venture to go beyond all possible experience with my
notions of space and time, which I cannot refrain from doing if I proclaim them
qualities inherent in things in themselves (for what should prevent me from letting
them hold good of the same things, even though my senses might be different, and
unsuited to them?), then a grave error may arise due to illusion, for thus I would
proclaim to be universally valid what is merely a subjective condition of the intuition
of things and sure only for all objects of sense, viz., for all possible experience; I
would refer this condition to things in themselves, and do not limit it to the
conditions of experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">My doctrine of the ideality of space and of time, therefore, far
from reducing the whole sensible world to mere illusion, is the only means of securing
the application of one of the most important cognitions (that which mathematics
propounds <span class="T6">a priori</span>) to actual objects, and of preventing its
being regarded as mere illusion. For without this observation it would be quite
impossible to make out whether the intuitions of space and time, which we borrow from
no experience, and which yet lie in our representation <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, are not mere phantasms of our brain, to which objects do not correspond,
at least not adequately, and consequently, whether we have been able to show its
unquestionable validity with regard to all the objects of the sensible world just
because they are mere appearances.</p>
<p class="Standard">Secondly, though these my principles make appearances of the
representations of the senses, they are so far from turning the truth of experience
into mere illusion, that they are rather the only means of preventing the
transcendental illusion, by which metaphysics has hitherto been deceived, leading to
the childish endeavor of catching at bubbles, because appearances, which are mere
representations, were taken for things in themselves. Here originated the remarkable
event of the antimony of Reason which I shall mention by and by, and which is destroyed
by the single observation, that appearance, as long as it is employed in experience,
produces truth, but the moment it transgresses the bounds of experience, and
consequently becomes transcendent, produces nothing but illusion.</p>
<p class="Standard">Inasmuch, therefore, as I leave to things as we obtain them by the
senses their actuality, and only limit our sensuous intuition of these things to this,
that they represent in no respect, not even in the pure intuitions of space and of
time, anything more than mere appearance of those things, but never their constitution
in themselves, this is not a sweeping illusion invented for nature by me. My
protestation too against all charges of idealism is so valid and clear as even to seem
superfluous, were there not incompetent judges, who, while they would have an old name
for every deviation from their perverse though common opinion, and never judge of the
spirit of philosophic nomenclature, but cling to the letter only, are ready to put
their own conceits in the place of well-defined notions, and thereby deform and distort
them. I have myself given this my theory the name of transcendental idealism, but that
cannot authorise any one to confound it either with the empirical idealism of
Descartes, (indeed, his was only an insoluble problem, owing to which he thought every
one at liberty to deny the existence of the corporeal world, because it could never be
proved satisfactorily), or with the mystical and visionary idealism of Berkeley,
against which and other similar phantasms our Critique contains the proper antidote. My
idealism concerns not the existence of things (the doubting of which, however,
constitutes idealism in the ordinary sense), since it never came into my head to doubt
it, but it concerns the sensuous representation of things, to which space and time
especially belong. Of these [viz., space and time], consequently of all appearances in
general, I have only shown, that they are neither things (but mere modes of
representation), nor determinations belonging to things in themselves. But the word
"transcendental," which with me means a reference of our cognition, i.e., not to
things, but only to the cognitive faculty, was meant to obviate this misconception. Yet
rather than give further occasion to it by this word, I now retract it, and desire this
idealism of mine to be called critical. But if it be really an objectionable idealism
to convert actual things (not appearances) into mere representations, by what name
shall we call him who conversely changes mere representations to things? It may, I
think, be called "dreaming idealism," in contradistinction to the former, which may be
called "visionary," both of which are to be refuted by my transcendental, or, better,
critical idealism.</p>
<h1><SPAN name="__RefHeading___Toc3105" name="__RefHeading___Toc3105"></SPAN>SECOND PART OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL PROBLEM.</h1>
<h2>HOW IS THE SCIENCE OF NATURE POSSIBLE?</h2>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">§ 14.</p>
<p class="Standard">NATURE is the existence of things, so far as it is determined
according to universal laws. Should nature signify the existence of things in
themselves, we could never cognise it either <span class="T6">a priori</span> or
<span class="T6">a posteriori</span>. Not <span class="T6">a priori</span>, for how can
we know what belongs to things in themselves, since this never can be done by the
dissection of our concepts (in analytical judgments)? We do not want to know what is
contained in our concept of a thing (for the [concept describes what] belongs to its
logical being), but what is in the actuality of the thing superadded to our concept,
and by what the thing itself is determined in its existence outside the concept. Our
understanding, and the conditions on which alone it can connect the determinations of
things in their existence, do not prescribe any rule to things themselves; these do not
conform to our understanding, but it must conform itself to them; they must therefore
be first given us in order to gather these determinations from them, wherefore they
would not be cognised <span class="T6">a priori</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">A cognition of the nature of things in themselves <span class="T6">a posteriori</span> would be equally impossible. For, if experience is to teach us
laws, to which the existence of things is subject, these laws, if they regard things in
themselves, must belong to them of necessity even outside our experience. But
experience teaches us what exists and how it exists, but never that it must necessarily
exist so and not otherwise. Experience therefore can never teach us the nature of
things in themselves.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 15. We nevertheless actually possess a pure science of
nature in which are propounded, <span class="T6">a priori</span> and with all the
necessity requisite to apodeictical propositions, laws to which nature is subject. I
need only call to witness that propaedeutic of natural science which, under the title
of the universal Science of Nature, precedes all Physics (which is founded upon
empirical principles). In it we have Mathematics applied to appearance, and also merely
discursive principles (or those derived from concepts), which constitute the
philosophical part of the pure cognition of nature. But there are several things in it,
which are not quite pure and independent of empirical sources: such as the concept of
<span class="T6">motion</span>, that of <span class="T6">impenetrability</span> (upon
which the empirical concept of matter rests), that of <span class="T6">inertia</span>,
and many others, which prevent its being called a perfectly pure science of nature.
Besides, it only refers to objects of the external sense, and therefore does not give
an example of a universal science of nature, in the strict sense, for such a science
must reduce nature in general, whether it regards the object of the external or that of
the internal sense (the object of Physics as well as Psychology), to universal laws.
But among the principles of this universal physics there are a few which actually have
the required universality; for instance, the propositions that "substance is
permanent," and that "every event is determined by a cause according to constant laws,"
etc. These are actually universal laws of nature, which subsist completely <span class="T6">a priori</span>. There is then in fact a pure science of nature, and the question
arises, <span class="T6">How is it possible?</span></p>
<p class="Standard">§ 16. The word "nature" assumes yet another meaning, which
determines the object, whereas in the former sense it only denotes the conformity to
law [<span class="T6">Gesetzmässigkeit</span>] of the determinations of the existence of things generally. If we
consider it <span class="T6">materialiter</span> (i.e., in the matter that forms its
objects) "nature is the complex of all the objects of experience." And with this only
are we now concerned, for besides, things which can never be objects of experience, if
they must be cognised as to their nature, would oblige us to have recourse to concepts
whose meaning could never be given <span class="T6">in concreto</span> (by any example
of possible experience). Consequently we must form for ourselves a list of concepts of
their nature, the reality whereof (i.e., whether they actually refer to objects, or are
mere creations of thought) could never be determined. The cognition of what cannot be
an object of experience would be hyperphysical, and with things hyperphysical we are
here not concerned, but only with the cognition of nature, the actuality of which can
be confirmed by experience, though it [the cognition of nature] is possible
<span class="T6">a priori</span> and precedes all experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 17. The formal [aspect] of nature in this narrower sense is
therefore the conformity to law of all the objects of experience, and so far as it is
cognised <span class="T6">a priori</span>, their necessary conformity. But it has just
been shown that the laws of nature can never be cognised a priori in objects so far as
they are considered not in reference to possible experience, but as things in
themselves. And our inquiry here extends not to things in themselves (the properties of
which we pass by), but to things as objects of possible experience, and the complex of
these is what we properly designate as nature. And now I ask, when the possibility of a
cognition of nature <span class="T6">a priori</span> is in question, whether it is
better to arrange the problem thus: How can we cognise <span class="T6">a priori</span>
that things as objects of experience necessarily conform to law? or thus: How is it
possible to cognise <span class="T6">a priori</span> the necessary conformity to law of
experience itself as regards all its objects generally?</p>
<p class="Standard">Closely considered, the solution of the problem, represented in
either way, amounts, with regard to the pure cognition of nature (which is the point of
the question at issue), entirely to the same thing. For the subjective laws, under
which alone an empirical cognition of things is possible, hold good of these things, as
Objects of possible experience (not as things in themselves, which are not considered
here). Either of the following statements means quite the same:</p>
<p class="Standard">A judgment of observation can never rank as experience, without the
law, that "whenever an event is observed, it is always referred to some antecedent,
which it follows according to a universal rule."</p>
<p class="Standard">"Everything, of which experience teaches that it happens, must have
a cause."</p>
<p class="Standard">It is, however, more commendable to choose the first formula. For
we can <span class="T6">a priori</span> and previous to all given objects have a
cognition of those conditions, on which alone experience is possible, but never of the
laws to which things may in themselves be subject, without reference to possible
experience. We cannot therefore study the nature of things <span class="T6">a
priori</span> otherwise than by investigating the conditions and the universal (though
subjective) laws, under which alone such a cognition as experience (as to mere form) is
possible, and we determine accordingly the possibility of things, as objects of
experience. For if I should choose the second formula, and seek the conditions
<span class="T6">a priori</span>, on which nature as an object of experience is
possible, I might easily fall into error, and fancy that I was speaking of nature as a
thing in itself, and then move round in endless circles, in a vain search for laws
concerning things of which nothing is given me.</p>
<p class="Standard">Accordingly we shall here be concerned with experience only, and
the universal conditions of its possibility which are given <span class="T6">a
priori</span>. Thence we shall determine nature as the whole object of all possible
experience. I think it will be understood that I here do not mean the rules of the
observation of a nature that is already given, for these already presuppose experience.
I do not mean how (through experience) we can study the laws of nature; for these would
not then be laws <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and would yield us no pure science
of nature; but [I mean to ask] how the conditions <span class="T6">a priori</span> of
the possibility of experience are at the same time the sources from which all the
universal laws of nature must be derived.</p>
<p class="Standard">
§ 18. In the first place we must state that, while all judgments of experience
(<span class="T6">Erfahrungsurtheile</span>) are empirical (i.e., have their ground
in immediate sense perception), <span class="T6">vice versa</span>, all empirical
judgments (<span class="T6">empirische Urtheile</span>) are not judgments of
experience, but, besides the empirical, and in general besides what is given to the
sensuous intuition, particular concepts must yet be superadded—concepts which have
their origin quite <span class="T6">a priori</span> in the pure understanding, and
under which every perception must be first of all subsumed and then by their means
changed into experience.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn11" id="body_ftn11">11</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">Empirical judgments, so far as they have objective validity, are
<span class="T11">judgments of experience</span>; but those which are only subjectively
valid, I name mere <span class="T11">judgments of perception</span>. The latter require
no pure concept of the understanding, but only the logical connexion of perception in a
thinking subject. But the former always require, besides the representation of the
sensuous intuition, particular <span class="T6">concepts originally begotten in the
understanding</span>, which produce the objective validity of the judgment of
experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">All our judgments are at first merely judgments of perception; they
hold good only for us (i.e., for our subject), and we do not till afterwards give them
a new reference (to an object), and desire that they shall always hold good for us and
in the same way for everybody else; for when a judgment agrees with an object, all
judgments concerning the same object must likewise agree among themselves, and thus the
objective validity of the judgment of experience signifies nothing else than its
necessary universality of application. And conversely when we have reason to consider a
judgment necessarily universal (which never depends upon perception, but upon the pure
concept of the understanding, under which the perception is subsumed), we must consider
it objective also, that is, that it expresses not merely a reference of our perception
to a subject, but a quality of the object. For there would be no reason for the
judgments of other men necessarily agreeing with mine, if it were not the unity of the
object to which they all refer, and with which they accord; hence they must all agree
with one another.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 19. Therefore objective validity and necessary universality
(for everybody) are equivalent terms, and though we do not know the object in itself,
yet when we consider a judgment as universal, and also necessary, we understand it to
have objective validity. By this judgment we cognise the object (though it remains
unknown as it is in itself) by the universal and necessary connexion of the given
perceptions. As this is the case with all objects of sense, judgments of experience
take their objective validity not from the immediate cognition of the object (which is
impossible), but from the condition of universal validity in empirical judgments,
which, as already said, never rests upon empirical, or, in short, sensuous conditions,
but upon a pure concept of the understanding. The object always remains unknown in
itself; but when by the concept of the understanding the connexion of the
representations of the object, which are given to our sensibility, is determined as
universally valid, the object is determined by this relation, and it is the judgment
that is objective.</p>
<p class="Standard">
To illustrate the matter: When we say, "the room is warm, sugar sweet, and wormwood
bitter"<sup><SPAN href="#ftn12" id="body_ftn12">12</SPAN></sup>—we have only subjectively valid
judgments. I do not at all expect that I or any other person shall always find it as
I now do; each of these sentences only expresses a relation of two sensations to the
same subject, to myself, and that only in my present state of perception;
consequently they are not valid of the object. Such are judgments of perception.
Judgments of experience are of quite a different nature. What experience teaches me
under certain circumstances, it must always teach me and everybody; and its validity
is not limited to the subject nor to its state at a particular time. Hence I
pronounce all such judgments as being objectively valid. For instance, when I say the
air is elastic, this judgment is as yet a judgment of perception only—I do nothing
but refer two of my sensations to one another. But, if I would have it called a
judgment of experience, I require this connexion to stand under a condition, which
makes it universally valid. I desire therefore that I and everybody else should
always connect necessarily the same perceptions under the same circumstances.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 20. We must consequently analyse experience in order to see
what is contained in this product of the senses and of the understanding, and how the
judgment of experience itself is possible. The foundation is the intuition of
which I become conscious, i.e., perception (<span class="T6">perceptio</span>), which
pertains merely to the senses. But in the next place, there are acts of judging (which
belong only to the understanding). But this judging may be twofold—first, I may merely
compare perceptions and connect them in a particular state of my consciousness; or,
secondly, I may connect them in consciousness generally. The former judgment is merely
a judgment of perception, and of subjective validity only: it is merely a connexion of
perceptions in my mental state, without reference to the object. Hence it is not, as is
commonly imagined, enough for experience to compare perceptions and to connect them in
consciousness through judgment; there arises no universality and necessity, for which
alone judgments can become objectively valid and be called experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">Quite another judgment therefore is required before perception can
become experience. The given intuition must be subsumed under a concept, which
determines the form of judging in general relatively to the intuition, connects its
empirical consciousness in consciousness generally, and thereby procures universal
validity for empirical judgments. A concept of this nature is a pure <span class="T6">a
priori</span> concept of the Understanding, which does nothing but determine for an
intuition the general way in which it can be used for judgments. Let the concept be
that of cause, then it determines the intuition which is subsumed under it, e.g., that
of air, relative to judgments in general, viz., the concept of air serves with regard
to its expansion in the relation of antecedent to consequent in a hypothetical
judgment. The concept of cause accordingly is a pure concept of the understanding,
which is totally disparate from all possible perception, and only serves to determine
the representation subsumed under it, relatively to judgments in general, and so to
make a universally valid judgment possible.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Before, therefore, a judgment of perception can become a judgment of experience, it
is requisite that the perception should be subsumed under some such a concept of the
understanding; for instance, air ranks under the concept of causes, which determines
our judgment about it in regard to its expansion as hypothetical.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn13" id="body_ftn13">13</SPAN></sup> Thereby the expansion of the air is
represented not as merely belonging to the perception of the air in my present state
or in several states of mine, or in the state of perception of others, but as
belonging to it necessarily. The judgment, "the air is elastic," becomes universally
valid, and a judgment of experience, only by certain judgments preceding it, which
subsume the intuition of air under the concept of cause and effect: and they thereby
determine the perceptions not merely as regards one another in me, but relatively to
the form of judging in general, which is here hypothetical, and in this way they
render the empirical judgment universally valid.</p>
<p class="Standard">
If all our synthetical judgments are analysed so far as they are objectively valid,
it will be found that they never consist of mere intuitions connected only (as is
commonly believed) by comparison into a judgment; but that they would be impossible
were not a pure concept of the understanding superadded to the concepts abstracted
from intuition, under which concept these latter are subsumed, and in this manner
only combined into an objectively valid judgment. Even the judgments of pure
mathematics in their simplest axioms are not exempt from this condition. The
principle, "a straight line is the shortest between two points," presupposes that the
line is subsumed under the concept of quantity, which certainly is no mere intuition,
but has its seat in the understanding alone, and serves to determine the intuition
(of the line) with regard to the judgments which may be made about it, relatively to
their quantity, that is, to plurality (as <span class="T6">judicia
plurativa</span>).<sup><SPAN href="#ftn14" id="body_ftn14">14</SPAN></sup> For under them it is understood that
in a given intuition there is contained a plurality of homogenous parts.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 21. To prove, then, the possibility of experience so far as
it rests upon pure concepts of the understanding <span class="T6">a priori</span>, we
must first represent what belongs to judgments in general and the various functions of
the understanding, in a complete table. For the pure concepts of the understanding must
run parallel to these functions, as such concepts are nothing more than concepts of
intuitions in general, so far as these are determined by one or other of these
functions of judging, in themselves, that is, necessarily and universally. Hereby also
the <span class="T6">a priori</span> principles of the possibility of all experience,
as of an objectively valid empirical cognition, will be precisely determined. For they
are nothing but propositions by which all perception is (under certain universal
conditions of intuition) subsumed under those pure concepts of the understanding.</p>
<table class="table_1">
<tr>
<td class="td_1" colspan="2">
<span class="T6">Logical Table of Judgments</span>.
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">1.</td>
<td class="td_2">2.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2"><span class="T6">As to Quantity</span>.</td>
<td class="td_2"><span class="T6">As to Quality</span>.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">Universal.</td>
<td class="td_2">Affirmative.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">Particular.</td>
<td class="td_2">Negative.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_3">Singular.</td>
<td class="td_3">Infinite.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">3.</td>
<td class="td_2">4.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2"><span class="T6">As to Relation</span>.</td>
<td class="td_2"><span class="T6">As to Modality</span>.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">Categorical.</td>
<td class="td_2">Problematical.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">Hypothetical.</td>
<td class="td_2">Assertorial.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_3">Disjunctive.</td>
<td class="td_3">Apodeictical.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_1" colspan="2">
<span class="T6">Transcendental Table of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding</span>.
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">1.</td>
<td class="td_2">2.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2"><span class="T6">As to Quantity</span>.</td>
<td class="td_2"><span class="T6">As to Quality</span>.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">Unity (the Measure).</td>
<td class="td_2">Reality.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">Plurality (the Quantity).</td>
<td class="td_2">Negation.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_3">Totality (the Whole).</td>
<td class="td_3">Limitation.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">3.</td>
<td class="td_2">4.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2"><span class="T6">As to Relation</span>.</td>
<td class="td_2"><span class="T6">As to Modality</span>.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">Substance.</td>
<td class="td_2">Possibility.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">Cause.</td>
<td class="td_2">Existence.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_3">Community.</td>
<td class="td_3">Necessity.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_1" colspan="2">
<span class="T6">Pure Physiological Table of the Universal Principles of the Science of Nature</span>.
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">1.</td>
<td class="td_2">2.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_3">Axioms of Intuition.</td>
<td class="td_3">Anticipations of Perception.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_2">3.</td>
<td class="td_2">4.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="td_3">Analogies of Experience.</td>
<td class="td_3">Postulates of Empirical Thinking generally.</td>
</tr>
</table>
<p class="Standard">§ 21<span class="T6">a</span>. In order to comprise the whole
matter in one idea, it is first necessary to remind the reader that we are discussing
not the origin of experience, but of that which lies in experience. The former pertains
to empirical psychology, and would even then never be adequately explained without the
latter, which belongs to the Critique of cognition, and particularly of the
understanding.</p>
<p class="Standard">Experience consists of intuitions, which belong to the sensibility,
and of judgments, which are entirely a work of the understanding. But the judgments,
which the understanding forms alone from sensuous intuitions, are far from being
judgments of experience. For in the one case the judgment connects only the perceptions
as they are given in the sensuous intuition, while in the other the judgments must
express what experience in general, and not what the mere perception (which possesses
only subjective validity) contains. The judgment of experience must therefore add to
the sensuous intuition and its logical connexion in a judgment (after it has been
rendered universal by comparison) something that determines the synthetical judgment as
necessary and therefore as universally valid. This can be nothing else than that
concept which represents the intuition as determined in itself with regard to one form
of judgment rather than another, viz., a concept of that synthetical unity of
intuitions which can only be represented by a given logical function of judgments.</p>
<p class="Standard">
§ 22. The sum of the matter is this: the business of the senses is to
intuite—that of the understanding is to think. But thinking is uniting
representations in one consciousness. This union originates either merely relative to
the subject, and is accidental and subjective, or is absolute, and is necessary or
objective. The union of representations in one consciousness is judgment. Thinking
therefore is the same as judging, or referring representations to judgments in
general. Hence judgments are either merely subjective, when representations are
referred to a consciousness in one subject only, and united in it, or objective, when
they are united in a consciousness generally, that is, necessarily. The logical
functions of all judgments are but various modes of uniting representations in
consciousness. But if they serve for concepts, they are concepts of their necessary
union in a consciousness, and so principles of objectively valid judgments. This
union in a consciousness is either analytical, by identity, or synthetical, by the
combination and addition of various representations one to another. Experience
consists in the synthetical connexion of phenomena (perceptions) in consciousness, so
far as this connexion is necessary. Hence the pure concepts of the understanding are
those under which all perceptions must be subsumed ere they can serve for judgments
of experience, in which the synthetical unity of the perceptions is represented as
necessary and universally valid.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn15" id="body_ftn15">15</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">§ 23. Judgments, when considered merely as the condition
of the union of given representations in a consciousness, are rules. These rules, so
far as they represent the union as necessary, are rules <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, and so far as they cannot be deduced from higher rules, are fundamental
principles. But in regard to the possibility of all experience, merely in relation to
the form of thinking in it, no conditions of judgments of experience are higher than
those which bring the phenomena, according to the various form of their intuition,
under pure concepts of the understanding, and render the empirical judgment objectively
valid. These concepts are therefore the <span class="T6">a priori</span> principles of
possible experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">
The principles of possible experience are then at the same time universal laws of
nature, which can be cognised <span class="T6">a priori</span>. And thus the problem
in our second question, "How is the pure Science of Nature possible?" is solved. For
the system which is required for the form of a science is to be met with in
perfection here, because, beyond the above-mentioned formal conditions of all
judgments in general offered in logic, no others are possible, and these constitute a
logical system. The concepts grounded thereupon, which contain the <span class="T6">a
priori</span> conditions of all synthetical and necessary judgments, accordingly
constitute a transcendental system. Finally the principles, by means of which all
phenomena are subsumed under these concepts, constitute a physical<sup><SPAN href="#ftn16" id="body_ftn16">16</SPAN></sup> system, that is, a system of nature,
which precedes all empirical cognition of nature, makes it even possible, and hence
may in strictness be denominated the universal and pure science of nature.</p>
<p class="Standard">
§ 24. The first one<sup><SPAN href="#ftn17" id="body_ftn17">17</SPAN></sup> of the physiological principles
subsumes all phenomena, as intuitions in space and time, under the concept of
Quantity, and is so far a principle of the application of Mathematics to experience.
The second one subsumes the empirical element, viz., sensation which denotes the real
in intuitions, not indeed directly under the concept of quantity, because sensation
is not an intuition that contains either space or time, though it places the
respective object into both. But still there is between reality
(sense-representation) and the zero, or total void of intuition in time, a difference
which has a quantity. For between every given degree of light and of darkness,
between every degree of heat and of absolute cold, between every degree of weight and
of absolute lightness, between every degree of occupied space and of totally void
space, diminishing degrees can be conceived, in the same manner as between
consciousness and total unconsciousness (the darkness of a psychological blank) ever
diminishing degrees obtain. Hence there is no perception that can prove an absolute
absence of it; for instance, no psychological darkness that cannot be considered as a
kind of consciousness. This occurs in all cases of sensation, and so the
understanding can anticipate even sensations, which constitute the peculiar quality
of empirical representations (appearances), by means of the principle: "that they all
have (consequently that what is real in all phenomena has) a degree." Here is the
second application of mathematics (<span class="T6">mathesis intensorum</span>) to
the science of nature.</p>
<p class="Standard">
§ 25. Anent the relation of appearances merely with a view to their existence,
the determination is not mathematical but dynamical, and can never be objectively
valid, consequently never fit for experience, if it does not come under <span class="T6">a priori</span> principles by which the cognition of experience relative to
appearances becomes even possible. Hence appearances must be subsumed under the
concept of Substance, which is the foundation of all determination of existence, as a
concept of the thing itself; or secondly—so far as, a succession is found among
phenomena, that is, an event—under the concept of an Effect with reference to Cause;
or lastly—so far as coexistence is to be known objectively, that is, by a judgment of
experience—under the concept of Community (action and reaction).<sup><SPAN href="#ftn18" id="body_ftn18">18</SPAN></sup> Thus a priori principles form the
basis of objectively valid, though empirical judgments, that is, of the possibility
of experience so far as it must connect objects as existing in nature. These
principles are the proper laws of nature, which may be termed dynamical.</p>
<p class="Standard">Finally the cognition of the agreement and connexion not only of
appearances among themselves in experience, but of their relation to experience in
general, belongs to the judgments of experience. This relation contains either their
agreement with the formal conditions, which the understanding cognises, or their
coherence with the materials of the senses and of perception, or combines both into one
concept. Consequently it contains Possibility, Actuality, and Necessity according to
universal laws of nature; and this constitutes the physical doctrine of method, or the
distinction of truth and of hypotheses, and the bounds of the certainty of the
latter.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 26. The third table of Principles drawn from the nature of
the understanding itself after the critical method, shows an inherent perfection, which
raises it far above every other table which has hitherto though in vain been tried or
may yet be tried by analysing the objects themselves dogmatically. It exhibits all
synthetical <span class="T6">a priori</span> principles completely and according to one
principle, viz., the faculty of judging in general, constituting the essence of
experience as regards the understanding, so that we can be certain that there are no
more such principles, a satisfaction such as can never be attained by the dogmatical
method. Yet is this not all: there is a still greater merit in it.</p>
<p class="Standard">We must carefully bear in mind the proof which shows the
possibility of this cognition <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and at the same time
limits all such principles to a condition which must never be lost sight of, if we
desire it not to be misunderstood, and extended in use beyond the original sense which
the understanding attaches to it. This limit is that they contain nothing but the
conditions of possible experience in general so far as it is subjected to laws
<span class="T6">a priori</span>. Consequently I do not say, that things <span class="T6">in themselves</span> possess a quantity, that their actuality possesses a degree,
their existence a connexion of accidents in a substance, etc. This nobody can prove,
because such a synthetical connexion from mere concepts, without any reference to
sensuous intuition on the one side, or connexion of it in a possible experience on the
other, is absolutely impossible. The essential limitation of the concepts in these
principles then is: That all things stand necessarily <span class="T6">a priori</span>
under the afore-mentioned conditions, as objects of experience only.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Hence there follows secondly a specifically peculiar mode of proof of these
principles: they are not directly referred to appearances and to their relations, but
to the possibility of experience, of which appearances constitute the matter only,
not the form. Thus they are referred to objectively and universally valid synthetical
propositions, in which we distinguish judgments of experience from those of
perception. This takes place because appearances, as mere intuitions, occupying a
part of space and time, come under the concept of Quantity, which unites their
multiplicity <span class="T6">a priori</span> according to rules synthetically.
Again, so far as the perception contains, besides intuition, sensibility, and between
the latter and nothing (i.e., the total disappearance of sensibility), there is an
ever decreasing transition, it is apparent that that which is in appearances must
have a degree, so far as it (viz., the perception) does not itself occupy any part of
space or of time.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn19" id="body_ftn19">19</SPAN></sup> Still the transition to actuality
from empty time or empty space is only possible in time; consequently though
sensibility, as the quality of empirical intuition, can never be cognised
<span class="T6">a priori</span>, by its specific difference from other
sensibilities, yet it can, in a possible experience in general, as a quantity of
perception be intensely distinguished from every other similar perception. Hence the
application of mathematics to nature, as regards the sensuous intuition by which
nature is given to us, becomes possible and is thus determined.</p>
<p class="Standard">Above all, the reader must pay attention to the mode of proof of
the principles which occur under the title of Analogies of experience. For these do not
refer to the genesis of intuitions, as do the principles of applied mathematics, but to
the connexion of their existence in experience; and this can be nothing but the
determination of their existence in time according to necessary laws, under which alone
the connexion is objectively valid, and thus becomes experience. The proof therefore
does not turn on the synthetical unity in the connexion of things in themselves, but
merely of perceptions, and of these not in regard to their matter, but to the
determination of time and of the relation of their existence in it, according to
universal laws. If the empirical determination in relative time is indeed objectively
valid (i.e., experience), these universal laws contain the necessary determination of
existence in time generally (viz., according to a rule of the understanding
<span class="T6">a priori</span>).</p>
<p class="Standard">In these Prolegomena I cannot further descant on the subject, but
my reader (who has probably been long accustomed to consider experience a mere
empirical synthesis of perceptions, and hence not considered that it goes much beyond
them, as it imparts to empirical judgments universal validity, and for that purpose
requires a pure and <span class="T6">a priori</span> unity of the understanding) is
recommended to pay special attention to this distinction of experience from a mere
aggregate of perceptions, and to judge the mode of proof from this point of view.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 27. Now we are prepared to remove Hume's doubt. He justly
maintains, that we cannot comprehend by reason the possibility of Causality, that is,
of the reference of the existence of one thing to the existence of another, which is
necessitated by the former. I add, that we comprehend just as little the concept of
Subsistence, that is, the necessity that at the foundation of the existence of things
there lies a subject which cannot itself be a predicate of any other thing; nay, we
cannot even form a notion of the possibility of such a thing (though we can point out
examples of its use in experience). The very same in comprehensibility affects the
Community of things, as we cannot comprehend how from the state of one thing an
inference to the state of quite another thing beyond it, and <span class="T6">vice
versa</span>, can be drawn, and how substances which have each their own separate
existence should depend upon one another necessarily. But I am very far from holding
these concepts to be derived merely from experience, and the necessity represented in
them, to be imaginary and a mere illusion produced in us by long habit. On the
contrary, I have amply shown, that they and the theorems derived from them are firmly
established <span class="T6">a priori</span>, or before all experience, and have their
undoubted objective value, though only with regard to experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 28. Though I have no notion of such a connexion of things in
themselves, that they can either exist as substances, or act as causes, or stand in
community with others (as parts of a real whole), and I can just as little conceive
such properties in appearances as such (because those concepts contain nothing that
lies in the appearances, but only what the understanding alone must think): we have yet
a notion of such a connexion of representations in our understanding, and in judgments
generally; consisting in this that representations appear in one sort of judgments as
subject in relation to predicates, in another as reason in relation to consequences,
and in a third as parts, which constitute together a total possible cognition. Besides
we cognise <span class="T6">a priori</span> that without considering the representation
of an object as determined in some of these respects, we can have no valid cognition of
the object, and, if we should occupy ourselves about the object in itself, there is no
possible attribute, by which I could know that it is determined under any of these
aspects, that is, under the concept either of substance, or of cause, or (in relation
to other substances) of community, for I have no notion of the possibility of such a
connexion of existence. But the question is not how things in themselves, but how the
empirical cognition of things is determined, as regards the above aspects of judgments
in general, that is, how things, as objects of experience, can and shall be subsumed
under these concepts of the understanding. And then it is clear, that I completely
comprehend not only the possibility, but also the necessity of subsuming all phenomena
under these concepts, that is, of using them for principles of the possibility of
experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 29. When making an experiment with Hume's problematical
concept (his <span class="T6">crux metaphysicorum</span>), the concept of cause, we
have, in the first place, given <span class="T6">a priori</span>, by means of logic,
the form of a conditional judgment in general, i.e., we have one given cognition as
antecedent and another as consequence. But it is possible, that in perception we may
meet with a rule of relation, which runs thus: that a certain phenomenon is constantly
followed by another (though not conversely), and this is a case for me to use the
hypothetical judgment, and, for instance, to say, it the sun shines long enough upon a
body, it grows warm. Here there is indeed as yet no necessity of connexion, or concept
of cause. But I proceed and say, that if this proposition, which is merely a subjective
connexion of perceptions, is to be a judgment of experience, it must be considered as
necessary and universally valid. Such a proposition would be, "the sun is by its light
the cause of heat." The empirical rule is now considered as a law, and as valid not
merely of appearances but valid of them for the purposes of a possible experience which
requires universal and therefore necessarily valid rules. I therefore easily comprehend
the concept of cause, as a concept necessarily belonging to the mere form of
experience, and its possibility as a synthetical union of perceptions in consciousness
generally; but I do not at all comprehend the possibility of a thing generally as a
cause, because the concept of cause denotes a condition not at all belonging to things,
but to experience. It is nothing in fact but an objectively valid cognition of
appearances and of their succession, so far as the antecedent can be conjoined with the
consequent according to the rule of hypothetical judgments.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 30. Hence if the pure concepts of the understanding do not
refer to objects of experience but to things in themselves (<span class="T6">noumena</span>), they have no signification whatever. They serve, as it were, only
to decipher appearances, that we may be able to read them as experience. The principles
which arise from their reference to the sensible world, only serve our understanding
for empirical use. Beyond this they are arbitrary combinations, without objective
reality, and we can neither cognise their possibility <span class="T6">a priori</span>,
nor verify their reference to objects, let alone make it intelligible by any example;
because examples can only be borrowed from some possible experience, consequently the
objects of these concepts can be found nowhere but in a possible experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">This complete (though to its originator unexpected) solution of
Hume's problem rescues for the pure concepts of the understanding their <span class="T6">a priori</span> origin, and for the universal laws of nature their validity, as
laws of the understanding, yet in such a way as to limit their use to experience,
because their possibility depends solely on the reference of the understanding to
experience, but with a completely reversed mode of connexion which never occurred to
Hume, not by deriving them from experience, but by deriving experience from them.</p>
<p class="Standard">This is therefore the result of all our foregoing inquiries: "All
synthetical principles <span class="T6">a priori</span> are nothing more than
principles of possible experience, and can never be referred to things in themselves,
but to appearances as objects of experience. And hence pure mathematics as well as a
pure science of nature can never be referred to anything more than mere appearances,
and can only represent either that which makes experience generally possible, or else
that which, as it is derived from these principles, must always be capable of being
represented in some possible experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 31. And thus we have at last something definite, upon which
to depend in all metaphysical enterprises, which have hitherto, boldly enough but
always at random, attempted everything without discrimination. That the aim of their
exertions should be so near, struck neither the dogmatical thinkers nor those who,
confident in their supposed sound common sense, started with concepts and principles of
pure reason (which were legitimate and natural, but destined for mere empirical use) in
quest of fields of knowledge, to which they neither knew nor could know any determinate
bounds, because they had never reflected nor were able to reflect on the nature or even
on the possibility of such a pure understanding.</p>
<p class="Standard">Many a naturalist of pure reason (by which I mean the man who
believes he can decide in matters of metaphysics without any science) may pretend, that
he long ago by the prophetic spirit of his sound sense, not only suspected, but knew
and comprehended, what is here propounded with so much ado, or, if he likes, with
prolix and pedantic pomp: "that with all our reason we can never reach beyond the field
of experience." But when he is questioned about his rational principles individually,
he must grant, that there are many of them which he has not taken from experience, and
which are therefore independent of it and valid <span class="T6">a priori</span>. How
then and on what grounds will he restrain both himself and the dogmatist, who makes use
of these concepts and principles beyond all possible experience, because they are
recognised to be independent of it? And even he, this adept in sound sense, in spite of
all his assumed and cheaply acquired wisdom, is not exempt from wandering inadvertently
beyond objects of experience into the field of chimeras. He is often deeply enough
involved in them, though in announcing everything as mere probability, rational
conjecture, or analogy, he gives by his popular language a color to his groundless
pretensions.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 32. Since the oldest days of philosophy inquirers into pure
reason have conceived, besides the things of sense, or appearances (phenomena), which
make up the sensible world, certain creations of the understanding (<span class="T6">Verstandeswesen</span>), called noumena, which should constitute an intelligible
world. And as appearance and illusion were by those men identified (a thing which we
may well excuse in an undeveloped epoch), actuality was only conceded to the creations
of thought.</p>
<p class="Standard">And we indeed, rightly considering objects of sense as mere
appearances, confess thereby that they are based upon a thing in itself, though we know
not this thing in its internal constitution, but only know its appearances, viz., the
way in which our senses are affected by this unknown something. The understanding
therefore, by assuming appearances, grants the existence of things in themselves also,
and so far we may say, that the representation of such things as form the basis of
phenomena, consequently of mere creations of the understanding, is not only admissible,
but unavoidable.</p>
<p class="Standard">Our critical deduction by no means excludes things of that sort
(noumena), but rather limits the principles of the Aesthetic (the science of the
sensibility) to this, that they shall not extend to all things, as everything would
then be turned into mere appearance, but that they shall only hold good of objects of
possible experience. Hereby then objects of the understanding are granted, but with the
inculcation of this rule which admits of no exception: "that we neither know nor can
know anything at all definite of these pure objects of the understanding, because our
pure concepts of the understanding as well as our pure intuitions extend to nothing but
objects of possible experience, consequently to mere things of sense, and as soon as we
leave this sphere these concepts retain no meaning whatever."</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 33. There is indeed something seductive in our pure
concepts of the understanding, which tempts us to a transcendent use, —a use which
transcends all possible experience. Not only are our concepts of substance, of power,
of action, of reality, and others, quite independent of experience, containing nothing
of sense appearance, and so apparently applicable to things in themselves (noumena),
but, what strengthens this conjecture, they contain a necessity of determination in
themselves, which experience never attains. The concept of cause implies a rule,
according to which one state follows another necessarily; but experience can only show
us, that one state of things often, or at most, commonly, follows another, and
therefore affords neither strict universality, nor necessity.</p>
<p class="Standard">Hence the Categories seem to have a deeper meaning and import than
can be exhausted by their empirical use, and so the understanding inadvertently adds
for itself to the house of experience a much more extensive wing, which it fills with
nothing but creatures of thought, without ever observing that it has transgressed with
its otherwise lawful concepts the bounds of their use.</p>
<p class="Standard">
§ 34. Two important, and even indispensable, though very dry, investigations
had therefore become indispensable in the Critique of Pure Reason,—viz., the two
chapters "Vom Schematismus der reinen Verstandsbegriffe," and "Vom Grunde der
Unterscheidung aller Verstandesbegriffe überhaupt in
Phänomena und Noumena." In the former it is shown, that the
senses furnish not the pure concepts of the understanding <span class="T6">in
concreto</span>, but only the schedule for their use, and that the object conformable
to it occurs only in experience (as the product of the understanding from materials
of the sensibility). In the latter it is shown, that, although our pure concepts of
the understanding and our principles are independent of experience, and despite of
the apparently greater sphere of their use, still nothing whatever can be thought by
them beyond the field of experience, because they can do nothing but merely determine
the logical form of the judgment relatively to given intuitions. But as there is no
intuition at all beyond the field of the sensibility, these pure concepts, as they
cannot possibly be exhibited <span class="T6">in concreto</span>, are void of all
meaning; consequently all these noumena, together with their complex, the
intelligible world,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn20" id="body_ftn20">20</SPAN></sup> are nothing but representation of a
problem, of which the object in itself is possible, but the solution, from the nature
of our understanding, totally impossible. For our understanding is not a faculty of
intuition, but of the connexion of given intuitions in experience. Experience must
therefore contain all the objects for our concepts; but beyond it no concepts have
any significance, as there is no intuition that might offer them a foundation.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 35. The imagination may perhaps be forgiven for occasional
vagaries, and for not keeping carefully within the limits of experience, since it gains
life and vigor by such flights, and since it is always easier to moderate its boldness,
than to stimulate its languor. But the understanding which ought to think can never be
forgiven for indulging in vagaries; for we depend upon it alone for assistance to set
bounds, when necessary, to the vagaries of the imagination.</p>
<p class="Standard">But the understanding begins its aberrations very innocently and
modestly. It first elucidates the elementary cognitions, which inhere in it prior to
all experience, but yet must always have their application in experience. It gradually
drops these limits, and what is there to prevent it, as it has quite freely derived its
principles from itself? And then it proceeds first to newly-imagined powers in nature,
then to beings, outside nature; in short to a world, for whose construction the
materials cannot be wanting, because fertile fiction furnishes them abundantly, and
though not confirmed, is never refuted, by experience. This is the reason that young
thinkers are so partial to metaphysics of the truly dogmatical kind, and often
sacrifice to it their time and their talents, which might be otherwise better
employed.</p>
<p class="Standard">But there is no use in trying to moderate these fruitless endeavors
of pure reason by all manner of cautions as to the difficulties of solving questions so
occult, by complaints of the limits of our reason, and by degrading our assertions into
mere conjectures. For if their impossibility is not distinctly shown, and reason's
cognition of its own essence does not become a true science, in which the field of its
right use is distinguished, so to say, with mathematical certainty from that of its
worthless and idle use, these fruitless efforts will never be abandoned for good.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">§ 36. How is Nature itself possible?</p>
<p class="Standard">This question—the highest point that transcendental philosophy can
ever reach, and to which, as its boundary and completion, it must proceed—properly
contains two questions.</p>
<p class="Standard">First: How is nature at all possible in
the material sense, by intuition, considered as the totality of appearances; how are
space, time, and that which fills both—the object of sensation, in general possible?
The answer is: By means of the constitution of our Sensibility, according to which it
is specifically affected by objects, which are in themselves unknown to it, and totally
distinct from those phenomena. This answer is given in the <span class="T6">Critique</span> itself in the transcendental Aesthetic, and in these <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span> by the solution of the first general problem.</p>
<p class="Standard">Secondly: How is nature possible in the
formal sense, as the totality of the rules, under which all phenomena must come, in
order to be thought as connected in experience? The answer must be this: It is only
possible by means of the constitution of our Understanding, according to which all the
above representations of the sensibility are necessarily referred to a consciousness,
and by which the peculiar way in which we think (viz., by rules), and hence experience
also, are possible, but must be clearly distinguished from an insight into the objects
in themselves. This answer is given in the <span class="T6">Critique</span> itself in
the transcendental Logic, and in these <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span>, in the
course of the solution of the second main problem.</p>
<p class="Standard">But how this peculiar property of our sensibility itself is
possible, or that of our understanding and of the apperception which is necessarily its
basis and that of all thinking, cannot be further analysed or answered, because it is
of them that we are in need for all our answers and for all our thinking about
objects.</p>
<p class="Standard">There are many laws of nature, which we can only know by means of
experience; but conformity to law in the connexion of appearances, i.e., in nature in
general, we cannot discover by any experience, because experience itself requires laws
which are <span class="T6">a priori</span> at the basis of its possibility.</p>
<p class="Standard">The possibility of experience in general is therefore at the same
time the universal law of nature, and the principles of the experience are the very
laws of nature. For we do not know nature but as the totality of appearances, i.e., of
representations in us, and hence we can only derive the laws of its connexion from the
principles of their connexion in us, that is, from the conditions of their necessary
union in consciousness, which constitutes the possibility of experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">Even the main proposition expounded throughout this section—that
universal laws of nature can be distinctly cognised <span class="T6">a
priori</span>—leads naturally to the proposition: that the highest legislation of
nature must lie in ourselves, i.e., in our understanding, and that we must not seek the
universal laws of nature in nature by means of experience, but conversely must seek
nature, as to its universal conformity to law, in the conditions of the possibility of
experience, which lie in our sensibility and in our understanding. For how were it
otherwise possible to know <span class="T6">a priori</span> these laws, as they are not
rules of analytical cognition, but truly synthetical extensions of it?</p>
<p class="Standard">
Such a necessary agreement of the principles of possible experience with the laws of
the possibility of nature, can only proceed from one of two reasons: either these
laws are drawn from nature by means of experience, or conversely nature is derived
from the laws of the possibility of experience in general, and is quite the same as
the mere universal conformity to law of the latter. The former is self-contradictory,
for the universal laws of nature can and must be cognised <span class="T6">a
priori</span> (that is, independent of all experience), and be the foundation of all
empirical use of the understanding; the latter alternative therefore alone
remains.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn21" id="body_ftn21">21</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">But we must distinguish the empirical laws of nature, which always
presuppose particular perceptions, from the pure or universal laws of nature, which,
without being based on particular perceptions, contain merely the conditions of their
necessary union in experience. In relation to the latter, nature and possible
experience are quite the same, and as the conformity to law here depends upon the
necessary connexion of appearances in experience (without which we cannot cognise any
object whatever in the sensible world), consequently upon the original laws of the
understanding, it seems at first strange, but is not the less certain, to say:</p>
<p class="Standard"><span class="T6">The understanding does not derive its laws (a priori) from, but
prescribes them to, nature.</span></p>
<p class="Standard">§ 37. We shall illustrate this seemingly bold proposition by
an example, which will show, that laws, which we discover in objects of sensuous
intuition (especially when these laws are cognised as necessary), are commonly held by
us to be such as have been placed there by the understanding, in spite of their being
similar in all points to the laws of nature, which we ascribe to experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 38. If we consider the properties of the circle, by which
this figure combines so many arbitrary determinations of space in itself, at once in a
universal rule, we cannot avoid attributing a constitution (<span class="T6">eine
Natur</span>) to this geometrical thing. Two right lines, for example, which intersect
one another and the circle, howsoever they may be drawn, are always divided so that the
rectangle constructed with the segments of the one is equal to that constructed with
the segments of the other. The question now is: Does this law lie in the circle or in
the understanding, that is, Does this figure, independently of the understanding,
contain in itself the ground of the law, or does the understanding, having constructed
according to its concepts (according to the quality of the radii) the figure itself,
introduce into it this law of the chords cutting one another in geometrical proportion?
When we follow the proofs of this law, we soon perceive, that it can only be derived
from the condition on which the understanding founds the construction of this figure,
and which is that of the equality of the radii. But, if we enlarge this concept, to
pursue further the unity of various properties of geometrical figures under common
laws, and consider the circle as a conic section, which of course is subject to the
same fundamental conditions of construction as other conic sections, we shall find that
all the chords which intersect within the ellipse, parabola, and hyperbola, always
intersect so that the rectangles of their segments are not indeed equal, but always
bear a constant ratio to one another. If we proceed still farther, to the fundamental
laws of physical astronomy, we find a physical law of reciprocal attraction diffused
over all material nature, the rule of which is: "that it decreases inversely as the
square of the distance from each attracting point, i.e., as the spherical surfaces
increase, over which this force spreads," which law seems to be necessarily inherent in
the very nature of things, and hence is usually propounded as cognisable <span class="T6">a priori</span>. Simple as the sources of this law are, merely resting upon the
relation of spherical surfaces of different radii, its consequences are so valuable
with regard to the variety of their agreement and its regularity, that not only are all
possible orbits of the celestial bodies conic sections, but such a relation of these
orbits to each other results, that no other law of attraction, than that of the inverse
square of the distance, can be imagined as fit for a cosmical system.</p>
<p class="Standard">Here accordingly is a nature that rests upon laws which the
understanding cognises <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and chiefly from the universal
principles of the determination of space. Now I ask:</p>
<p class="Standard">Do the laws of nature lie in space, and does the understanding
learn them by merely endeavoring to find out the enormous wealth of meaning that lies
in space; or do they inhere in the understanding and in the way in which it determines
space according to the conditions of the synthetical unity in which its concepts are
all centred?</p>
<p class="Standard">Space is something so uniform and as to all particular properties
so indeterminate, that we should certainly not seek a store of laws of nature in it.
Whereas that which determines space to assume the form of a circle or the figures of a
cone and a sphere, is the understanding, so far as it contains the ground of the unity
of their constructions.</p>
<p class="Standard">
The mere universal form of intuition, called space, must therefore be the substratum
of all intuitions determinable to particular objects, and in it of course the
condition of the possibility and of the variety of these intuitions lies. But the
unity of the objects is entirely determined by the understanding, and on conditions
which lie in its own nature; and thus the understanding is the origin of the
universal order of nature, in that it comprehends all appearances under its own laws,
and thereby first constructs, <span class="T6">a priori</span>, experience (as to its
form), by means of which whatever is to be cognised only by experience, is
necessarily subjected to its laws. For we are not now concerned with the nature of
things in themselves, which is independent of the conditions both of our sensibility
and our understanding, but with nature, as an object of possible experience, and in
this case the understanding, whilst it makes experience possible, thereby insists
that the sensuous world is either not an object of experience at all, or must be
nature [viz., an existence of things, determined according to universal
laws<sup><SPAN href="#ftn22" id="body_ftn22">22</SPAN></sup>].</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">APPENDIX TO THE PURE SCIENCE OF NATURE.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">§ 39. <span class="T6">Of the System of the
Categories</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">There can be nothing more desirable to a philosopher, than to be
able to derive the scattered multiplicity of the concepts or the principles, which had
occurred to him in concrete use, from a principle <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and
to unite everything in this way in one cognition. He formerly only believed that those
things, which remained after a certain abstraction, and seemed by comparison among one
another to constitute a particular kind of cognitions, were completely collected; but
this was only an Aggregate. Now he knows, that just so many, neither more nor less, can
constitute the mode of cognition, and perceives the necessity of his division, which
constitutes comprehension; and now only he has attained a <span class="T6">System</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">To search in our daily cognition for the concepts, which do not
rest upon particular experience, and yet occur in all cognition of experience, where
they as it were constitute the mere form of connexion, presupposes neither greater
reflexion nor deeper insight, than to detect in a language the rules of the actual use
of words generally, and thus to collect elements for a grammar. In fact both researches
are very nearly related, even though we are not able to give a reason why each language
has just this and no other formal constitution, and still less why an exact number of
such formal determinations in general are found in it.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Aristotle collected ten pure elementary concepts under the name of
Categories.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn23" id="body_ftn23">23</SPAN></sup> To these, which are also called
predicaments, he found himself obliged afterwards to add five
post-predicaments,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn24" id="body_ftn24">24</SPAN></sup> some of which however (<span class="T6">prius</span>,
<span class="T6">simul</span>, and <span class="T6">motus</span>) are contained in
the former; but this random collection must be considered (and commended) as a mere
hint for future inquirers, not as a regularly developed idea, and hence it has, in
the present more advanced state of philosophy, been rejected as quite useless.</p>
<p class="Standard">After long reflexion on the pure elements of human knowledge (those
which contain nothing empirical), I at last succeeded in distinguishing with certainty
and in separating the pure elementary notions of the Sensibility (space and time) from
those of the Understanding. Thus the 7th, 8th, and 9th Categories had to be excluded
from the old list. And the others were of no service to me; because there was no
principle [in them], on which the understanding could be investigated, measured in its
completion, and all the functions, whence its pure concepts arise, determined
exhaustively and with precision.</p>
<p class="Standard">But in order to discover such a principle, I looked about for an
act of the understanding which comprises all the rest, and is distinguished only by
various modifications or phases, in reducing the multiplicity of representation to the
unity of thinking in general: I found this act of the understanding to consist in
judging. Here then the labors of the logicians were ready at hand, though not yet quite
free from defects, and with this help I was enabled to exhibit a complete table of the
pure functions of the understanding, which are however undetermined in regard to any
object. I finally referred these functions of judging to objects in general, or rather
to the condition of determining judgments as objectively valid, and so there arose the
pure concepts of the understanding, concerning which I could make certain, that these,
and this exact number only, constitute our whole cognition of things from pure
understanding. I was justified in calling them by their old name, <span class="T6">Categories</span>, while I reserved for myself the liberty of adding, under the
title of "Predicables," a complete list of all the concepts deducible from them, by
combinations whether among themselves, or with the pure form of the appearance, i.e.,
space or time, or with its matter, so far as it is not yet empirically determined
(viz., the object of sensation in general), as soon as a system of transcendental
philosophy should be completed with the construction of which I am engaged in the
<span class="T6">Critique of Pure Reason</span> itself.</p>
<p class="Standard">Now the essential point in this system of Categories, which
distinguishes it from the old rhapsodical collection without any principle, and for
which alone it deserves to be considered as philosophy, consists in this: that by means
of it the true significance of the pure concepts of the understanding and the condition
of their use could be precisely determined. For here it became obvious that they are
themselves nothing but logical functions, and as such do not produce the least concept
of an object, but require some sensuous intuition as a basis. They therefore only serve
to determine empirical judgments, which are otherwise undetermined and indifferent as
regards all functions of judging, relatively to these functions, thereby procuring them
universal validity, and by means of them making judgments of experience in general
possible.</p>
<p class="Standard">Such an insight into the nature of the categories, which limits
them at the same time to the mere use of experience, never occurred either to their
first author, or to any of his successors; but without this insight (which immediately
depends upon their derivation or deduction), they are quite useless and only a
miserable list of names, without explanation or rule for their use. Had the ancients
ever conceived such a notion, doubtless the whole study of the pure rational knowledge,
which under the name of metaphysics has for centuries spoiled many a sound mind, would
have reached us in quite another shape, and would have enlightened the human
understanding, instead of actually exhausting it in obscure and vain speculations,
thereby rendering it unfit for true science.</p>
<p class="Standard">
This system of categories makes all treatment of every object of pure reason itself
systematic, and affords a direction or clue how and through what points of inquiry
every metaphysical consideration must proceed, in order to be complete; for it
exhausts all the possible movements (<span class="T6">momenta</span>) of the
understanding, among which every concept must be classed. In like manner the table of
Principles has been formulated, the completeness of which we can only vouch for by
the system of the categories. Even in the division of the concepts,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn25" id="body_ftn25">25</SPAN></sup> which must go beyond the physical
application of the understanding, it is always the very same clue, which, as it must
always be determined <span class="T6">a priori</span> by the same fixed points of the
human understanding, always forms a closed circle. There is no doubt that the object
of a pure conception either of the understanding or of reason, so far as it is to be
estimated philosophically and on <span class="T6">a priori</span> principles, can in
this way be completely cognised. I could not therefore omit to make use of this clue
with regard to one of the most abstract ontological divisions, viz., the various
distinctions of "the notions of something and of nothing," and to construct
accordingly (<span class="T6">Critique</span>, p. 207) a regular and necessary
table of their divisions.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn26" id="body_ftn26">26</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">
And this system, like every other true one founded on a universal principle, shows
its inestimable value in this, that it excludes all foreign concepts, which might
otherwise intrude among the pure concepts of the understanding, and determines the
place of every cognition. Those concepts, which under the name of "concepts of
reflexion" have been likewise arranged in a table according to the clue of the
categories, intrude, without having any privilege or title to be among the pure
concepts of the understanding in Ontology. They are concepts of connexion, and
thereby of the objects themselves, whereas the former are only concepts of a mere
comparison of concepts already given, hence of quite another nature and use. By my
systematic division<sup><SPAN href="#ftn27" id="body_ftn27">27</SPAN></sup>
they are saved from this confusion.
But the value of my special table of the categories will be still more obvious, when
we separate the table of the transcendental concepts of Reason from the concepts of
the understanding. The latter being of quite another nature and origin, they must
have quite another form than the former. This so necessary separation has never yet
been made in any system of metaphysics for, as a rule, these rational concepts all
mixed up with the categories, like children of one family, which confusion was
unavoidable in the absence of a definite system of categories.</p>
<h1><SPAN name="__RefHeading___Toc3107" name="__RefHeading___Toc3107"></SPAN>THIRD PART OF THE MAIN TRANSCENDENTAL PROBLEM.</h1>
<h2>HOW IS METAPHYSICS IN GENERAL POSSIBLE?</h2>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">§ 40.</p>
<p class="Standard">PURE mathematics and pure science of nature had no occasion for
such a deduction, as we have made of both, for their own safety and certainty. For the
former rests upon its own evidence; and the latter (though sprung from pure sources of
the understanding) upon experience and its thorough confirmation. Physics cannot
altogether refuse and dispense with the testimony of the latter; because with all its
certainty, it can never, as philosophy, rival mathematics. Both sciences therefore
stood in need of this inquiry, not for themselves, but for the sake of another science,
metaphysics.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Metaphysics has to do not only with concepts of nature, which always find their
application in experience, but also with pure rational concepts, which never can be
given in any possible experience. Consequently the objective reality of these
concepts (viz., that they are not mere chimeras), and the truth or falsity of
metaphysical assertions, cannot be discovered or confirmed by any experience. This
part of metaphysics however is precisely what constitutes its essential end, to which
the rest is only a means, and thus this science is in need of such a deduction for
its own sake. The third question now proposed relates therefore as it were to the
root and essential difference of metaphysics, i.e., the occupation of Reason with
itself, and the supposed knowledge of objects arising immediately from this
incubation of its own concepts, without requiring, or indeed being able to reach that
knowledge through, experience.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn28" id="body_ftn28">28</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">Without solving this problem reason never is justified. The
empirical use to which reason limits the pure understanding, does not fully satisfy the
proper destination of the latter. Every single experience is only a part of the whole
sphere of its domain, but the absolute totality of all possible experience is itself
not experience. Yet it is a necessary [concrete] problem for reason, the mere
representation of which requires concepts quite different from the categories, whose
use is only immanent, or refers to experience, so far as it can be given. Whereas the
concepts of reason aim at the completeness, i.e., the collective unity of all possible
experience, and thereby transcend every given experience. Thus they become <span class="T6">transcendent</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">As the understanding stands in need of categories for experience, reason
contains in itself the source of ideas, by which I mean necessary concepts, whose
object cannot be given in any experience. The latter are inherent in the nature of
reason, as the former are in that of the understanding. While the former carry with
them an illusion likely to mislead, the illusion of the latter is inevitable, though it
certainly can be kept from misleading us.</p>
<p class="Standard">Since all illusion consists in holding the subjective ground of our
judgments to be objective, a self-knowledge of pure reason in its transcendent
(exaggerated) use is the sole preservative from the aberrations into which reason falls
when it mistakes its destination, and refers that to the object transcendently, which
only regards its own subject and its guidance in all immanent use.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 41. The distinction of ideas, that is, of pure concepts of
reason, from categories, or pure concepts of the understanding, as cognitions of a
quite distinct species, origin and use, is so important a point in founding a science
which is to contain the system of all these <span class="T6">a priori</span>
cognitions, that without this distinction metaphysics is absolutely impossible, or is
at best a random, bungling attempt to build a castle in the air without a knowledge of
the materials or of their fitness for any purpose. Had the <span class="T6">Critique of
Pure Reason</span> done nothing but first point out this distinction, it had thereby
contributed more to clear up our conception of, and to guide our inquiry in, the field
of metaphysics, than all the vain efforts which have hitherto been made to satisfy the
transcendent problems of pure reason, without ever surmising that we were in quite
another field than that of the understanding, and hence classing concepts of the
understanding and those of reason together, as if they were of the same kind.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 42. All pure cognitions of the understanding have this
feature, that their concepts present themselves in experience, and their principles can
be confirmed by it; whereas the transcendent cognitions of reason cannot, either as
ideas, appear in experience, or as propositions ever be confirmed or refuted by it.
Hence whatever errors may slip in unawares, can only be discovered by pure reason
itself—a discovery of much difficulty, because this very reason naturally becomes
dialectical by means of its ideas, and this unavoidable illusion cannot be limited by
any objective and dogmatical researches into things, but by a subjective investigation
of reason itself as a source of ideas.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 43. In the <span class="T6">Critique of Pure Reason</span>
it was always my greatest care to endeavor not only carefully to distinguish the
several species of cognition, but to derive concepts belonging to each one of them from
their common source. I did this in order that by knowing whence they originated, I
might determine their use with safety, and also have the unanticipated but invaluable
advantage of knowing the completeness of my enumeration, classification and
specification of concepts <span class="T6">a priori</span>, and therefore according to
principles. Without this, metaphysics is mere rhapsody, in which no one knows whether
he has enough, or whether and where something is still wanting. We can indeed have this
advantage only in pure philosophy, but of this philosophy it constitutes the very
essence.</p>
<p class="Standard">As I had found the origin of the categories in the four logical
functions of all the judgments of the understanding, it was quite natural to seek the
origin of the ideas in the three functions of the syllogisms of reason. For as soon as
these pure concepts of reason (the transcendental ideas) are given, they could hardly,
except they be held innate, be found anywhere else, than in the same activity of
reason, which, so far as it regards mere form, constitutes the logical element of the
syllogisms of reason; but, so far as it represents judgments of the understanding with
respect to the one or to the other form <span class="T6">a priori</span>, constitutes
transcendental concepts of pure reason.</p>
<p class="Standard">
The formal distinction of syllogisms renders their division into categorical,
hypothetical, and disjunctive necessary. The concepts of reason founded on them
contained therefore, first, the idea of the complete subject (the substantial);
secondly, the idea of the complete series of conditions; thirdly, the determination
of all concepts in the idea of a complete complex of that which is
possible.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn29" id="body_ftn29" name="body_ftn29">29</SPAN></sup>
The first idea is psychological, the
second cosmological, the third theological, and, as all three give occasion to
Dialectics, yet each in its own way, the division of the whole Dialects of pure
reason into its Paralogism, its Antinomy, and its Ideal, was arranged accordingly.
Through this deduction we may feel assured that all the claims of pure reason are
completely represented, and that none can be wanting; because the faculty of reason
itself, whence they all take their origin, is thereby completely surveyed.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 44. In these general considerations it is also remarkable
that the ideas of reason are unlike the categories, of no service to the use of our
understanding in experience, but quite dispensable, and become even an impediment to
the maxims of a rational cognition of nature. Yet in another aspect still to be
determined they are necessary. Whether the soul is or is not a simple substance, is of
no consequence to us in the explanation of its phenomena. For we cannot render the
notion of a simple being intelligible by any possible experience that is sensuous or
concrete. The notion is therefore quite void as regards all hoped-for insight into the
cause of phenomena, and cannot at all serve as a principle of the explanation of that
which internal or external experience supplies. So the cosmological ideas of the
beginning of the world or of its eternity (<span class="T6">a parte ante</span>) cannot
be of any greater service to us for the explanation of any event in the world itself.
And finally we must, according to a right maxim of the philosophy of nature, refrain
from all explanations of the design of nature, drawn from the will of a Supreme Being;
because this would not be natural philosophy, but an acknowledgment that we have come
to the end of it. The use of these ideas, therefore, is quite different from that of
those categories by which (and by the principles built upon which) experience itself
first becomes possible. But our laborious analytics of the understanding would be
superfluous if we had nothing else in view than the mere cognition of nature as it can
be given in experience; for reason does its work, both in mathematics and in the
science of nature, quite safely and well without any of this subtle deduction.
Therefore our Critique of the Understanding combines with the ideas of pure reason for
a purpose which lies beyond the empirical use of the understanding; but this we have
above declared to be in this aspect totally inadmissible, and without any object or
meaning. Yet there must be a harmony between that of the nature of reason and that of
the understanding, and the former must contribute to the perfection of the latter, and
cannot possibly upset it.</p>
<p class="Standard">The solution of this question is as follows: Pure reason does not
in its ideas point to particular objects, which lie beyond the field of experience, but
only requires completeness of the use of the understanding in the system of experience.
But this completeness can be a completeness of principles only, not of intuitions
(i.e., concrete atsights or <span class="T6">Anschauungen</span>) and of objects. In
order however to represent the ideas definitely, reason conceives them after the
fashion of the cognition of an object. The cognition is as far as these rules are
concerned completely determined, but the object is only an idea invented for the
purpose of bringing the cognition of the understanding as near as possible to the
completeness represented by that idea.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter"><span class="T6">Prefatory Remark to the Dialectics of Pure
Reason</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 45. We have above shown in §§ 33 and 34 that the purity of
the categories from all admixture of sensuous determinations may mislead reason into
extending their use, quite beyond all experience, to things in themselves; though as
these categories themselves find no intuition which can give them meaning or sense
<span class="T6">in concreto</span>, they, as mere logical functions, can represent a
thing in general, but not give by themselves alone a determinate concept of anything.
Such hyperbolical objects are distinguised by the appellation of <span class="T6">Noümena</span>, or pure beings of
the understanding (or better, beings of thought), such as, for example, "substance,"
but conceived without permanence in time, or "cause," but not acting in time, etc. Here
predicates, that only serve to make the conformity-to-law of experience possible, are
applied to these concepts, and yet they are deprived of all the conditions of
intuition, on which alone experience is possible, and so these concepts lose all
significance.</p>
<p class="Standard">There is no danger, however, of the understanding spontaneously
making an excursion so very wantonly beyond its own bounds into the field of the mere
creatures of thought, without being impelled by foreign laws. But when reason, which
cannot be fully satisfied with any empirical use of the rules of the understanding, as
being always conditioned, requires a completion of this chain of conditions, then the
understanding is forced out of its sphere. And then it partly represents objects of
experience in a series so extended that no experience can grasp, partly even (with a
view to complete the series) it seeks entirely beyond it noumena, to which it can
attach that chain, and so, having at last escaped from the conditions of experience,
make its attitude as it were final. These are then the transcendental ideas, which,
though according to the true but hidden ends of the natural determination of our
reason, they may aim not at extravagant concepts, but at an unbounded extension of
their empirical use, yet seduce the understanding by an unavoidable illusion to a
transcendent use, which, though deceitful, cannot be restrained within the bounds of
experience by any resolution, but only by scientific instruction and with much
difficulty.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">
I. <span class="T6">The Psychological Idea</span>.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn30" id="body_ftn30">30</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">§ 46. People have long since observed, that in all substances
the proper subject, that which remains after all the accidents (as predicates) are
abstracted, consequently that which forms the substance of things remains unknown, and
various complaints have been made concerning these limits to our knowledge. But it will
be well to consider that the human understanding is not to be blamed for its inability
to know the substance of things, that is, to determine it by itself, but rather for
requiring to cognise it which is a mere idea definitely as though it were a given
object. Pure reason requires us to seek for every predicate of a thing its proper
subject, and for this subject, which is itself necessarily nothing but a predicate, its
subject, and so on indefinitely (or as far as we can reach). But hence it follows, that
we must not hold anything, at which we can arrive, to be an ultimate subject, and that
substance itself never can be thought by our understanding, however deep we may
penetrate, even if all nature were unveiled to us. For the specific nature of our
understanding consists in thinking everything discursively, that is, representing it by
concepts, and so by mere predicates, to which therefore the absolute subject must
always be wanting. Hence all the real properties, by which we cognise bodies, are mere
accidents, not excepting impenetrability, which we can only represent to ourselves as
the effect of a power of which the subject is unknown to us.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Now we appear to have this substance in the consciousness of ourselves (in the
thinking subject), and indeed in an immediate intuition; for all the predicates of an
internal sense refer to the ego, as a subject, and I cannot conceive myself as the
predicate of any other subject. Hence completeness in the reference of the given
concepts as predicates to a subject—not merely an idea, but an object—that is, the
absolute subject itself, seems to be given in experience. But this expectation is
disappointed. For the ego is not a concept,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn31" id="body_ftn31">31</SPAN></sup>
but only the indication of the object
of the internal sense, so far as we cognise it by no further predicate. Consequently
it cannot be in itself a predicate of any other thing; but just as little can it be a
determinate concept of an absolute subject, but is, as in all other cases, only the
reference of the internal phenomena to their unknown subject. Yet this idea (which
serves very well, as a regulative principle, totally to destroy all materialistic
explanations of the internal phenomena of the soul) occasions by a very natural
misunderstanding a very specious argument, which, from this supposed cognition of the
substance of our thinking being, infers its nature, so far as the knowledge of it
falls quite without the complex of experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 47. But though we may call this thinking self (the soul)
substance, as being the ultimate subject of thinking which cannot be further
represented as the predicate of another thing; it remains quite empty and without
significance, if permanence—the quality which renders the concept of substances in
experience fruitful—cannot be proved of it.</p>
<p class="Standard">
But permanence can never be proved of the concept of a substance, as a thing in
itself, but for the purposes of experience only. This is sufficiently shown by the
first Analogy of Experience,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn32" id="body_ftn32">32</SPAN></sup> and who ever will not yield to this
proof may try for himself whether he can succeed in proving, from the concept of a
subject which does not exist itself as the predicate of another thing, that its
existence is thoroughly permanent, and that it cannot either in itself or by any
natural cause originate or be annihilated. These synthetical <span class="T6">a
priori</span> propositions can never be proved in themselves, but only in reference
to things as objects of possible experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">
§ 48. If therefore from the concept of the soul as a substance, we would infer
its permanence, this can hold good as regards possible experience only, not [of the
soul] as a thing in itself and beyond all possible experience. But life is the
subjective condition of all our possible experience, consequently we can only infer
the permanence of the soul in life; for the death of man is the end of all experience
which concerns the soul as an object of experience, except the contrary be proved,
which is the very question in hand. The permanence of the soul can therefore only be
proved (and no one cares for that) during the life of man, but not, as we desire to
do, after death; and for this general reason, that the concept of substance, so far
as it is to be considered necessarily combined with the concept of permanence, can be
so combined only according to the principles of possible experience, and therefore
for the purposes of experience only.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn33" id="body_ftn33">33</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">§ 49. That there is something real without us which not
only corresponds, but must correspond, to our external perceptions, can likewise be
proved to be not a connexion of things in themselves, but for the sake of experience.
This means that there is something empirical, i.e., some phenomenon in space without
us, that admits of a satisfactory proof, for we have nothing to do with other objects
than those which belong to possible experience; because objects which cannot be given
us in any experience, do not exist for us. Empirically without me is that which appears
in space, and space, together with all the phenomena which it contains, belongs to the
representations, whose connexion according to laws of experience proves their objective
truth, just as the connexion of the phenomena of the internal sense proves the
actuality of my soul (as an object of the internal sense). By means of external
experience I am conscious of the actuality of bodies, as external phenomena in space,
in the same manner as by means of the internal experience I am conscious of the
existence of my soul in time, but this soul is only cognised as an object of the
internal sense by phenomena that constitute an internal state, and of which the essence
in itself, which forms the basis of these phenomena, is unknown. Cartesian idealism
therefore does nothing but distinguish external experience from dreaming; and the
conformity to law (as a criterion of its truth) of the former, from the irregularity
and the false illusion of the latter. In both it presupposes space and time as
conditions of the existence of objects, and it only inquires whether the objects of the
external senses, which we when awake put in space, are as actually to be found in it,
as the object of the internal sense, the soul, is in time; that is, whether experience
carries with it sure criteria to distinguish it from imagination. This doubt, however,
may be easily disposed of, and we always do so in common life by investigating the
connexion of phenomena in both space and time according to universal laws of
experience, and we cannot doubt, when the representation of external things throughout
agrees therewith, that they constitute truthful experience. Material idealism, in which
phenomena are considered as such only according to their connexion in experience, may
accordingly be very easily refuted; and it is just as sure an experience, that bodies
exist without us (in space), as that I myself exist according to the representation of
the internal sense (in time): for the notion without us, only signifies existence in
space. However as the Ego in the proposition, "I am," means not only the object of
internal intuition (in time), but the subject of consciousness, just as body means not
only external intuition (in space), but the thing-in-itself, which is the basis of this
phenomenon; [as this is the case] the question, whether bodies (as phenomena of the
external sense) exist as bodies apart from my thoughts, may without any hesitation be
denied in nature. But the question, whether I myself as a phenomenon of the internal
sense (the soul according to empirical psychology) exist apart from my faculty of
representation in time, is an exactly similar inquiry, and must likewise be answered in
the negative. And in this manner everything, when it is reduced to its true meaning, is
decided and certain. The formal (which I have also called transcendental) actually
abolishes the material, or Cartesian, idealism. For if space be nothing but a form of
my sensibility, it is as a representation in me just as actual as I myself am, and
nothing but the empirical truth of the representations in it remains for consideration.
But, if this is not the case, if space and the phenomena in it are something existing
without us, then all the criteria of experience beyond our perception can never prove
the actuality of these objects without us.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">
II. <span class="T6">The Cosmological Idea</span>.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn34" id="body_ftn34">34</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">§ 50. This product of pure reason in its transcendent use is
its most remarkable curiosity. It serves as a very powerful agent to rouse philosophy
from its dogmatic slumber, and to stimulate it to the arduous task of undertaking a
<span class="T6">Critique of Reason</span> itself.</p>
<p class="Standard">I term this idea cosmological, because it always takes its object
only from the sensible world, and does not use any other than those whose object is
given to sense, consequently it remains in this respect in its native home, it does not
become transcendent, and is therefore so far not mere idea; whereas, to conceive the
soul as a simple substance, already means to conceive such an object (the simple) as
cannot be presented to the senses. Yet the cosmological idea extends the connexion of
the conditioned with its condition (whether the connexion is mathematical or dynamical)
so far, that experience never can keep up with it. It is therefore with regard to this
point always an idea, whose object never can be adequately given in any experience.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 51. In the first place, the use of a system of categories
becomes here so obvious and unmistakable, that even if there were not several other
proofs of it, this alone would sufficiently prove it indispensable in the system of
pure reason. There are only four such transcendent ideas, as there are so many classes
of categories; in each of which, however, they refer only to the absolute completeness
of the series of the conditions for a given conditioned. In analogy to these
cosmological ideas there are only four kinds of dialectical assertions of pure reason,
which, as they are dialectical, thereby prove, that to each of them, on equally
specious principles of pure reason, a contradictory assertion stands opposed. As all
the metaphysical art of the most subtile distinction cannot prevent this opposition, it
compels the philosopher to recur to the first sources of pure reason itself. This
Antinomy, not arbitrarily invented, but founded in the nature of human reason, and
hence unavoidable and never ceasing, contains the following four theses together with
their antitheses:</p>
<p class="P8">1.</p>
<p class="NormCent"><span class="T6">Thesis</span>.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">The World has, as to Time and Space, a Beginning (limit).</p>
<p class="NormCent"><span class="T6">Antithesis</span>.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">The World is, as to Time and Space, infinite.</p>
<p class="NormCent">2.</p>
<p class="NormCent"><span class="T6">Thesis</span>.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">Everything in the World consists of [elements that are] simple.</p>
<p class="NormCent"><span class="T6">Antithesis</span>.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">There is nothing simple, but everything is composite.</p>
<p class="NormCent">3.</p>
<p class="NormCent"><span class="T6">Thesis</span>.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">There are in the World Causes through Freedom.</p>
<p class="NormCent"><span class="T6">Antithesis</span>.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">There is no Liberty, but all is Nature.</p>
<p class="NormCent">4.</p>
<p class="NormCent"><span class="T6">Thesis</span>.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">In the Series of the World-Causes there is some necessary Being.</p>
<p class="NormCent"><span class="T6">Antithesis</span>.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceAfter">There is Nothing necessary in the World, but in this Series All is
incidental.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 52.<span class="T6">a</span>. Here is the most singular
phenomenon of human reason, no other instance of which can be shown in any other use.
If we, as is commonly done, represent to ourselves the appearances of the sensible
world as things in themselves, if we assume the principles of their combination as
principles universally valid of things in themselves and not merely of experience, as
is usually, nay without our <span class="T6">Critique</span>, unavoidably done, there
arises an unexpected conflict, which never can be removed in the common dogmatical way;
because the thesis, as well as the antithesis, can be shown by equally clear, evident,
and irresistible proofs—for I pledge myself as to the correctness of all these
proofs—and reason therefore perceives that it is divided with itself, a state at which
the sceptic rejoices, but which must make the critical philosopher pause and feel ill
at ease.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 52.<span class="T6">b</span>. We may blunder in various
ways in metaphysics without any fear of being detected in falsehood. For we never can
be refuted by experience if we but avoid self-contradiction, which in synthetical,
though purely fictitious propositions, may be done whenever the concepts, which we
connect, are mere ideas, that cannot be given (in their whole content) in experience.
For how can we make out by experience, whether the world is from eternity or had a
beginning, whether matter is infinitely divisible or consists of simple parts? Such
concept cannot be given in any experience, be it ever so extensive, and consequently
the falsehood either of the positive or the negative proposition cannot be discovered
by this touch-stone.</p>
<p class="Standard">The only possible way in which reason could have revealed
unintentionally its secret Dialectics, falsely announced as Dogmatics, would be when it
were made to ground an assertion upon a universally admitted principle, and to deduce
the exact contrary with the greatest accuracy of inference from another which is
equally granted. This is actually here the case with regard to four natural ideas of
reason, whence four assertions on the one side, and as many counter-assertions on the
other arise, each consistently following from universally-acknowledged principles. Thus
they reveal by the use of these principles the dialectical illusion of pure reason
which would otherwise forever remain concealed.</p>
<p class="Standard">
This is therefore a decisive experiment, which must necessarily expose any error
lying hidden in the assumptions of reason.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn35" id="body_ftn35">35</SPAN></sup> Contradictory propositions cannot
both be false, except the concept, which is the subject of both, is
self-contradictory; for example, the propositions, "a square circle is round, and a
square circle is not round," are both false. For, as to the former it is false, that
the circle is round, because it is quadrangular; and it is likewise false, that it is
not round, that is, angular, because it is a circle. For the logical criterion of the
impossibility of a concept consists in this, that if we presuppose it, two
contradictory propositions both become false; consequently, as no middle between them
is conceivable, nothing at all is thought by that concept.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 52.<span class="T6">c</span>. The first two antinomies, which I
call mathematical, because they are concerned with the addition or division of the
homogeneous, are founded on such a self-contradictory concept; and hence I explain how
it happens, that both the Thesis and Antithesis of the two are false.</p>
<p class="Standard">When I speak of objects in time and in space, it is not of things
in themselves, of which I know nothing, but of things in appearance, that is, of
experience, as the particular way of cognising objects which is afforded to man. I must
not say of what I think in time or in space, that in itself, and independent of these
my thoughts, it exists in space and in time; for in that case I should contradict
myself; because space and time, together with the appearances in them, are nothing
existing in themselves and outside of my representations, but are themselves only modes
of representation, and it is palpably contradictory to say, that a mere mode of
representation exists without our representation. Objects of the senses therefore exist
only in experience; whereas to give them a self-subsisting existence apart from
experience or before it, is merely to represent to ourselves that experience actually
exists apart from experience or before it.</p>
<p class="Standard">Now if I inquire after the quantity of the world, as to space and
time, it is equally impossible, as regards all my notions, to declare it infinite or to
declare it finite. For neither assertion can be contained in experience, because
experience either of an infinite space, or of an infinite time elapsed, or again, of
the boundary of the world by a void space, or by an antecedent void time, is
impossible; these are mere ideas. This quantity of the world, which is determined in
either way, should therefore exist in the world itself apart from all experience. This
contradicts the notion of a world of sense, which is merely a complex of the
appearances whose existence and connexion occur only in our representations, that is,
in experience, since this latter is not an object in itself, but a mere mode of
representation. Hence it follows, that as the concept of an absolutely existing world
of sense is self-contradictory, the solution of the problem concerning its quantity,
whether attempted affirmatively or negatively, is always false.</p>
<p class="Standard">The same holds good of the second antinomy, which relates to the
division of phenomena. For these are mere representations, and the parts exist merely
in their representation, consequently in the division, or in a possible experience
where they are given, and the division reaches only as far as this latter reaches. To
assume that an appearance, e.g., that of body, contains in itself before all experience
all the parts, which any possible experience can ever reach, is to impute to a mere
appearance, which can exist only in experience, an existence previous to experience. In
other words, it would mean that mere representations exist before they can be found in
our faculty of representation. Such an assertion is self-contradictory, as also every
solution of our misunderstood problem, whether we maintain, that bodies in themselves
consist of an infinite number of parts, or of a finite number of simple parts.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 53. In the first (the mathematical) class of antinomies the
falsehood of the assumption consists in representing in one concept something
self-contradictory as if it were compatible (i.e., an appearance as an object in
itself). But, as to the second (the dynamical) class of antinomies, the falsehood of
the representation consists in representing as contradictory what is compatible; so
that, as in the former case, the opposed assertions are both false, in this case, on
the other hand, where they are opposed to one another by mere misunderstanding, they
may both be true.</p>
<p class="Standard">Any mathematical connexion necessarily presupposes homogeneity of
what is connected (in the concept of magnitude), while the dynamical one by no means
requires the same. When we have to deal with extended magnitudes, all the parts must be
homogeneous with one another and with the whole; whereas, in the connexion of cause and
effect, homogeneity may indeed likewise be found, but is not necessary; for the concept
of causality (by means of which something is posited through something else quite
different from it), at all events, does not require it.</p>
<p class="Standard">If the objects of the world of sense are taken for things in
themselves, and the above laws of nature for the laws of things in themselves, the
contradiction would be unavoidable. So also, if the subject of freedom were, like other
objects, represented as mere appearance, the contradiction would be just as
unavoidable, for the same predicate would at once be affirmed and denied of the same
kind of object in the same sense. But if natural necessity is referred merely to
appearances, and freedom merely to things in themselves, no contradiction arises, if we
at once assume, or admit both kinds of causality, however difficult or impossible it
may be to make the latter kind conceivable.</p>
<p class="Standard">
As appearance every effect is an event, or something that happens in time; it must,
according to the universal law of nature, be preceded by a determination of the
causality of its cause (a state), which follows according to a constant law. But this
determination of the cause as causality must likewise be something that takes place
or happens; the cause must have begun to act, otherwise no succession between it and
the effect could be conceived. Otherwise the effect, as well as the causality of the
cause, would have always existed. Therefore the determination of the cause to act
must also have originated among appearances, and must consequently, as well as its
effect, be an event, which must again have its cause, and so on; hence natural
necessity must be the condition, on which effective causes are determined. Whereas if
freedom is to be a property of certain causes of appearances, it must, as regards
these, which are events, be a faculty of starting them spontaneously, that is,
without the causality of the cause itself, and hence without requiring any other
ground to determine its start. But then the cause, as to its causality, must not rank
under time-determinations of its state, that is, it cannot be an appearance, and must
be considered a thing in itself, while its effects would be only
appearances.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn36" id="body_ftn36">36</SPAN></sup> If without contradiction we can think
of the beings of understanding [<span class="T6">Verstandeswesen</span>] as
exercising such an influence on appearances, then natural necessity will attach to
all connexions of cause and effect in the sensuous world, though on the other hand,
freedom can be granted to such cause, as is itself not an appearance (but the
foundation of appearance). Nature therefore and freedom can without contradiction be
attributed to the very same thing, but in different relations—on one side as a
phenomenon, on the other as a thing in itself.</p>
<p class="Standard">We have in us a faculty, which not only stands in connexion with
its subjective determining grounds that are the natural causes of its actions, and is
so far the faculty of a being that itself belongs to appearances, but is also referred
to objective grounds, that are only ideas, so far as they can determine this faculty, a
connexion which is expressed by the word <span class="T6">ought</span>. This faculty is
called <span class="T6">reason</span>, and, so far as we consider a being (man)
entirely according to this objectively determinable reason, he cannot be considered as
a being of sense, but this property is that of a thing in itself, of which we cannot
comprehend the possibility—I mean how the <span class="T6">ought</span> (which however
has never yet taken place) should determine its activity, and can become the cause of
actions, whose effect is an appearance in the sensible world. Yet the causality of
reason would be freedom with regard to the effects in the sensuous world, so far as we
can consider objective grounds, which are themselves ideas, as their determinants. For
its action in that case would not depend upon subjective conditions, consequently not
upon those of time, and of course not upon the law of nature, which serves to determine
them, because grounds of reason give to actions the rule universally, according to
principles, without the influence of the circumstances of either time or place.</p>
<p class="Standard">What I adduce here is merely meant as an example to make the thing
intelligible, and does not necessarily belong to our problem, which must be decided
from mere concepts, independently of the properties which we meet in the actual
world.</p>
<p class="Standard">Now I may say without contradiction: that all the actions of
rational beings, so far as they are appearances (occurring in any experience), are
subject to the necessity of nature; but the same actions, as regards merely the
rational subject and its faculty of acting according to mere reason, are free. For what
is required for the necessity of nature? Nothing more than the determinability of every
event in the world of sense according to constant laws, that is, a reference to cause
in the appearance; in this process the thing in itself at its foundation and its
causality remain unknown. But I say, that the law of nature remains, whether the
rational being is the cause of the effects in the sensuous world from reason, that is,
through freedom, or whether it does not determine them on grounds of reason. For, if
the former is the case, the action is performed according to maxims, the effect of
which as appearance is always conform able to constant laws; if the latter is the case,
and the action not performed on principles of reason, it is subjected to the empirical
laws of the sensibility, and in both cases the effects are connected according to
constant laws; more than this we do not require or know concerning natural necessity.
But in the former case reason is the cause of these laws of nature, and therefore free;
in the latter the effects follow according to mere natural laws of sensibility, because
reason does not influence it; but reason itself is not determined on that account by
the sensibility, and is therefore free in this case too. Freedom is therefore no
hindrance to natural law in appearance, neither does this law abrogate the freedom of
the practical use of reason, which is connected with things in themselves, as
determining grounds.</p>
<p class="Standard">Thus practical freedom, viz., the freedom in which reason possesses
causality according to objectively determining grounds, is rescued and yet natural
necessity is not in the least curtailed with regard to the very same effects, as
appearances. The same remarks will serve to explain what we had to say concerning
transcendental freedom and its compatibility with natural necessity (in the same
subject, but not taken in the same reference). For, as to this, every beginning of the
action of a being from objective causes regarded as determining grounds, is always a
first start, though the same action is in the series of appearances only a subordinate
start, which must be preceded by a state of the cause, which determines it, and is
itself determined in the same manner by another immediately preceding. Thus we are
able, in rational beings, or in beings generally, so far as their causality is
determined in them as things in themselves, to imagine a faculty of beginning from
itself a series of states, without falling into contradiction with the laws of nature.
For the relation of the action to objective grounds of reason is not a time-relation;
in this case that which determines the causality does not precede in time the action,
because such determining grounds represent not a reference to objects of sense, e.g.,
to causes in the appearances, but to determining causes, as things in themselves, which
do not rank under conditions of time. And in this way the action, with regard to the
causality of reason, can be considered as a first start in respect to the series of
appearances, and yet also as a merely subordinate beginning. We may therefore without
contradiction consider it in the former aspect as free, but in the latter (in so far as
it is merely appearance) as subject to natural necessity.</p>
<p class="Standard">As to the fourth Antinomy, it is solved in the same way as the
conflict of reason with itself in the third. For, provided the cause <span class="T6">in</span> the appearance is distinguished from the cause <span class="T6">of</span> the appearance (so far as it can be thought as a thing in itself), both
propositions are perfectly reconcilable: the one, that there is nowhere in the sensuous
world a cause (according to similar laws of causality), whose existence is absolutely
necessary; the other, that this world is nevertheless connected with a Necessary Being
as its cause (but of another kind and according to another law). The incompatibility of
these propositions entirely rests upon the mistake of extending what is valid merely of
appearances to things in themselves, and in general confusing both in one concept.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 54. This then is the proposition and this the solution of
the whole antinomy, in which reason finds itself involved in the application of its
principles to the sensible world. The former alone (the mere proposition) would be a
considerable service in the cause of our knowledge of human reason, even though the
solution might fail to fully satisfy the reader, who has here to combat a natural
illusion, which has been but recently exposed to him, and which he had hitherto always
regarded as genuine. For one result at least is unavoidable. As it is quite impossible
to prevent this conflict of reason with itself—so long as the objects of the sensible
world are taken for things in themselves, and not for mere appearances, which they are
in fact—the reader is thereby compelled to examine over again the deduction of all our
<span class="T6">a priori</span> cognition and the proof which I have given of my
deduction in order to come to a decision on the question. This is all I require at
present; for when in this occupation he shall have thought himself deep enough into the
nature of pure reason, those concepts by which alone the solution of the conflict of
reason is possible, will become sufficiently familiar to him. Without this preparation
I cannot expect an unreserved assent even from the most attentive reader.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">
III. <span class="T6">The Theological Idea</span>.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn37" id="body_ftn37">37</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">§ 55. The third transcendental Idea, which affords matter for
the most important, but, if pursued only speculatively, transcendent and thereby
dialectical use of reason, is the ideal of pure reason. Reason in this case does not,
as with the psychological and the cosmological Ideas, begin from experience, and err by
exaggerating its grounds, in striving to attain, if possible, the absolute completeness
of their series. It rather totally breaks with experience, and from mere concepts of
what constitutes the absolute completeness of a thing in general, consequently by means
of the idea of a most perfect primal Being, it proceeds to determine the possibility
and therefore the actuality of all other things. And so the mere presupposition of a
Being, who is conceived not in the series of experience, yet for the purposes of
experience—for the sake of comprehending its connexion, order, and unity—i.e., the idea
[the notion of it], is more easily distinguished from the concept of the understanding
here, than in the former cases. Hence we can easily expose the dialectical illusion
which arises from our making the subjective conditions of our thinking objective
conditions of objects themselves, and an hypothesis necessary for the satisfaction of
our reason, a dogma. As the observations of the Critique on the pretensions of
transcendental theology are intelligible, clear, and decisive, I have nothing more to
add on the subject.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter"><span class="T6">General Remark on the
Transcendental Ideas</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">
§ 56. The objects, which are given us by experience, are in many respects
incomprehensible, and many questions, to which the law of nature leads us, when
carried beyond a certain point (though quite conformably to the laws of nature),
admit of no answer; as for example the question: why substances attract one another?
But if we entirely quit nature, or in pursuing its combinations, exceed all possible
experience, and so enter the realm of mere ideas, we cannot then say that the object
is incomprehensible, and that the nature of things proposes to us insoluble problems.
For we are not then concerned with nature or in general with given objects, but with
concepts, which have their origin merely in our reason, and with mere creations of
thought; and all the problems that arise from our notions of them must be solved,
because of course reason can and must give a full account of its own
procedure.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn38" id="body_ftn38">38</SPAN></sup> As the psychological, cosmological,
and theological Ideas are nothing but pure concepts of reason, which cannot be given
in any experience, the questions which reason asks us about them are put to us not by
the objects, but by mere maxims of our reason for the sake of its own satisfaction.
They must all be capable of satisfactory answers, which is done by showing that they
are principles which bring our use of the understanding into thorough agreement,
completeness, and synthetical unity, and that they so far hold good of experience
only, but of experience as a whole.</p>
<p class="Standard">Although an absolute whole of experience is impossible, the idea of
a whole of cognition according to principles must impart to our knowledge a peculiar
kind of unity, that of a system, without which it is nothing but piecework, and cannot
be used for proving the existence of a highest purpose (which can only be the general
system of all purposes), I do not here refer only to the practical, but also to the
highest purpose of the speculative use of reason.</p>
<p class="Standard">The transcendental Ideas therefore express the peculiar application
of reason as a principle of systematic unity in the use of the understanding. Yet if we
assume this unity of the mode of cognition to be attached to the object of cognition,
if we regard that which is merely regulative to be constitutive, and if we persuade
ourselves that we can by means of these Ideas enlarge our cognition transcendently, or
far beyond all possible experience, while it only serves to render experience within
itself as nearly complete as possible, i.e., to limit its progress by nothing that
cannot belong to experience: we suffer from a mere misunderstanding in our estimate of
the proper application of our reason and of its principles, and from a Dialectic, which
both confuses the empirical use of reason, and also sets reason at variance with
itself.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">Conclusion.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter"><span class="T6">On the Determination of the Bounds of Pure
Reason</span>.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 57. Having adduced the clearest arguments, it would be
absurd for us to hope that we can know more of any object, than belongs to the possible
experience of it, or lay claim to the least atom of knowledge about anything not
assumed to be an object of possible experience, which would determine it according to
the constitution it has in itself. For how could we determine anything in this way,
since time, space, and the categories, and still more all the concepts formed by
empirical experience or perception in the sensible world (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>), have and can have no other use, than to make experience
possible. And if this condition is omitted from the pure concepts of the understanding,
they do not determine any object, and have no meaning whatever.</p>
<p class="Standard">But it would be on the other hand a still greater absurdity if we
conceded no things in themselves, or set up our experience for the only possible mode
of knowing things, our way of beholding (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>) them in
space and in time for the only possible way, and our discursive understanding for the
archetype of every possible understanding; in fact if we wished to have the principles
of the possibility of experience considered universal conditions of things in
themselves.</p>
<p class="Standard">Our principles, which limit the use of reason to possible
experience, might in this way become transcendent, and the limits of our reason be set
up as limits of the possibility of things in themselves (as Hume's dialogues may
illustrate), if a careful critique did not guard the bounds of our reason with respect
to its empirical use, and set a limit to its pretensions. Scepticism originally arose
from metaphysics and its licentious dialectics. At first it might, merely to favor the
empirical use of reason, announce everything that transcends this use as worthless and
deceitful; but by and by, when it was perceived that the very same principles that are
used in experience, insensibly, and apparently with the same right, led still further
than experience extends, then men began to doubt even the propositions of experience.
But here there is no danger; for common sense will doubtless always assert its rights.
A certain confusion, however, arose in science which cannot determine how far reason is
to be trusted, and why only so far and no further, and this confusion can only be
cleared up and all future relapses obviated by a formal determination, on principle, of
the boundary of the use of our reason.</p>
<p class="Standard">We cannot indeed, beyond all possible experience, form a definite
notion of what things in themselves may be. Yet we are not at liberty to abstain
entirely from inquiring into them; for experience never satisfies reason fully, but in
answering questions, refers us further and further back, and leaves us dissatisfied
with regard to their complete solution. This any one may gather from the Dialectics of
pure reason, which therefore has its good subjective grounds. Having acquired, as
regards the nature of our soul, a clear conception of the subject, and having come to
the conviction, that its manifestations cannot be explained materialistically, who can
refrain from asking what the soul really is, and, if no concept of experience suffices
for the purpose, from accounting for it by a concept of reason (that of a simple
immaterial being), though we cannot by any means prove its objective reality? Who can
satisfy himself with mere empirical knowledge in all the cosmological questions of the
duration and of the quantity of the world, of freedom or of natural necessity, since
every answer given on principles of experience begets a fresh question, which likewise
requires its answer and thereby clearly shows the insufficiency of all physical modes
of explanation to satisfy reason? Finally, who does not see in the thorough-going
contingency and dependence of all his thoughts and assumptions on mere principles of
experience, the impossibility of stopping there? And who does not feel himself
compelled, notwithstanding all interdictions against losing himself in transcendent
ideas, to seek rest and contentment beyond all the concepts which he can vindicate by
experience, in the concept of a Being, the possibility of which we cannot conceive, but
at the same time cannot be refuted, because it relates to a mere being of the
understanding, and without it reason must needs remain forever dissatisfied?</p>
<p class="Standard">Bounds (in extended beings) always presuppose a space existing
outside a certain definite place, and in closing it; limits do not require this, but
are mere negations, which affect a quantity, so far as it is not absolutely complete.
But our reason, as it were, sees in its surroundings a space for the cognition of
things in themselves, though we can never have definite notions of them, and are
limited to appearances only.</p>
<p class="Standard">As long as the cognition of reason is homogeneous, definite bounds
to it are inconceivable. In mathematics and in natural philosophy human reason admits
of limits, but not of bounds, viz., that something indeed lies without it, at which it
can never arrive, but not that it will at any point find completion in its internal
progress. The enlarging of our views in mathematics, and the possibility of new
discoveries, are infinite; and the same is the case with the discovery of new
properties of nature, of new powers and laws, by continued experience and its rational
combination. But limits cannot be mistaken here, for mathematics refers to appearances
only, and what cannot be an object of sensuous contemplation, such as the concepts of
metaphysics and of morals, lies entirely without its sphere, and it can never lead to
them; neither does it require them. It is therefore not a continual progress and an
approximation towards these sciences, and there is not, as it were, any point or line
of contact. Natural science will never reveal to us the internal constitution of
things, which though not appearance, yet can serve as the ultimate ground of explaining
appearance. Nor does that science require this for its physical explanations. Nay even
if such grounds should be offered from other sources (for instance, the influence of
immaterial beings), they must be rejected and not used in the progress of its
explanations. For these explanations must only be grounded upon that which as an object
of sense can belong to experience, and be brought into connexion with our actual
perceptions and empirical laws.</p>
<p class="Standard">But metaphysics leads us towards bounds in the dialectical attempts
of pure reason (not undertaken arbitrarily or wantonly, but stimulated thereto by the
nature of reason itself). And the transcendental Ideas, as they do not admit of
evasion, and are never capable of realisation, serve to point out to us actually not
only the bounds of the pure use of reason, but also the way to determine them. Such is
the end and the use of this natural predisposition of our reason, which has brought
forth metaphysics as its favorite child, whose generation, like every other in the
world, is not to be ascribed to blind chance, but to an original germ, wisely organised
for great ends. For metaphysics, in its fundamental features, perhaps more than any
other science, is placed in us by nature itself, and cannot be considered the
production of an arbitrary choice or a casual enlargement in the progress of experience
from which it is quite disparate.</p>
<p class="Standard">Reason with all its concepts and laws of the understanding, which
suffice for empirical use, i.e., within the sensible world, finds in itself no
satisfaction because ever-recurring questions deprive us of all hope of their complete
solution. The transcendental ideas, which have that completion in view, are such
problems of reason. But it sees clearly, that the sensuous world cannot contain this
completion, neither consequently can all the concepts, which serve merely for
understanding the world of sense, such as space and time, and whatever we have adduced
under the name of pure concepts of the understanding. The sensuous world is nothing but
a chain of appearances connected according to universal laws; it has therefore no
subsistence by itself; it is not the thing in itself, and consequently must point to
that which contains the basis of this experience, to beings which cannot be cognised
merely as phenomena, but as things in themselves. In the cognition of them alone reason
can hope to satisfy its desire of completeness in proceeding from the conditioned to
its conditions.</p>
<p class="Standard">We have above (§§ 33, 34) indicated the limits of reason with
regard to all cognition of mere creations of thought. Now, since the transcendental
ideas have urged us to approach them, and thus have led us, as it were, to the spot
where the occupied space (viz., experience) touches the void (that of which we can know
nothing, viz., noumena), we can determine the bounds of pure reason. For in all bounds
there is something positive (e.g., a surface is the boundary of corporeal space, and is
therefore itself a space, a line is a space, which is the boundary of the surface, a
point the boundary of the line, but yet always a place in space), whereas limits
contain mere negations. The limits pointed out in those paragraphs are not enough after
we have discovered that beyond them there still lies something (though we can never
cognise what it is in itself). For the question now is, What is the attitude of our
reason in this connexion of what we know with what we do not, and never shall, know?
This is an actual connexion of a known thing with one quite unknown (and which will
always remain so), and though what is unknown should not become the least more
known—which we cannot even hope—yet the notion of this connexion must be definite, and
capable of being rendered distinct.</p>
<p class="Standard">We must therefore accept an immaterial being, a world of
understanding, and a Supreme Being (all mere noumena), because in them only, as things
in themselves, reason finds that completion and satisfaction, which it can never hope
for in the derivation of appearances from their homogeneous grounds, and because these
actually have reference to something distinct from them (and totally heterogeneous), as
appearances always presuppose an object in itself, and therefore suggest its existence
whether we can know more of it or not.</p>
<p class="Standard">But as we can never cognise these beings of understanding as they
are in themselves, that is, definitely, yet must assume them as regards the sensible
world, and connect them with it by reason, we are at least able to think this connexion
by means of such concepts as express their relation to the world of sense. Yet if we
represent to ourselves a being of the understanding by nothing but pure concepts of the
understanding, we then indeed represent nothing definite to ourselves, consequently our
concept has no significance; but if we think it by properties borrowed from the
sensuous world, it is no longer a being of understanding, but is conceived as an
appearance, and belongs to the sensible world. Let us take an instance from the notion
of the Supreme Being.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Our deistic conception is quite a pure concept of reason, but represents only a thing
containing all realities, without being able to determine any one of them; because
for that purpose an example must be taken from the world of sense, in which case we
should have an object of sense only, not something quite heterogeneous, which can
never be an object of sense. Suppose I attribute to the Supreme Being understanding,
for instance; I have no concept of an understanding other than my own, one that must
receive its perceptions (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>) by the senses, and which
is occupied in bringing them under rules of the unity of consciousness. Then the
elements of my concept would always lie in the appearance; I should however by the
insufficiency of the appearance be necessitated to go beyond them to the concept of a
being which neither depends upon appearance, nor is bound up with them as conditions
of its determination. But if I separate understanding from sensibility to obtain a
pure understanding, then nothing remains but the mere form of thinking without
perception (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>), by which form alone I can cognise
nothing definite, and consequently no object. For that purpose I should conceive
another understanding, such as would directly perceive its objects,<sup><SPAN href="#ftn39" id="body_ftn39">39</SPAN></sup> but of which I have not the least
notion; because the human understanding is discursive, and can [not directly
perceive, it can] only cognise by means of general concepts. And the very same
difficulties arise if we attribute a will to the Supreme Being; for we have this
concept only by drawing it from our internal experience, and therefore from our
dependence for satisfaction upon objects whose existence we require; and so the
notion rests upon sensibility, which is absolutely incompatible with the pure concept
of the Supreme Being.</p>
<p class="Standard">Hume's objections to deism are weak, and affect only the proofs,
and not the deistic assertion itself. But as regards theism, which depends on a
stricter determination of the concept of the Supreme Being which in deism is merely
transcendent, they are very strong, and as this concept is formed, in certain (in fact
in all common) cases irrefutable. Hume always insists, that by the mere concept of an
original being, to which we apply only ontological predicates (eternity, omnipresence,
omnipotence), we think nothing definite, and that properties which can yield a concept
<span class="T6">in concreto</span> must be superadded; that it is not enough to say,
it is Cause, but we must explain the nature of its causality, for example, that of an
understanding and of a will. He then begins his attacks on the essential point itself,
i.e., theism, as he had previously directed his battery only against the proofs of
deism, an attack which is not very dangerous to it in its consequences. All his
dangerous arguments refer to anthropomorphism, which he holds to be inseparable from
theism, and to make it absurd in itself; but if the former be abandoned, the latter
must vanish with it, and nothing remain but deism, of which nothing can come, which is
of no value, and which cannot serve as any foundation to religion or morals. If this
anthropomorphism were really unavoidable, no proofs whatever of the existence of a
Supreme Being, even were they all granted, could determine for us the concept of this
Being without involving us in contradictions.</p>
<p class="Standard">
If we connect with the command to avoid all transcendent judgments of pure reason,
the command (which apparently conflicts with it) to proceed to concepts that lie
beyond the field of its immanent (empirical) use, we discover that both can subsist
together, but only at the boundary of all lawful use of reason. For this boundary
belongs as well to the field of experience, as to that of the creations of thought,
and we are thereby taught, as well, how these so remarkable ideas serve merely for
marking the bounds of human reason. On the one hand they give warning not boundlessly
to extend cognition of experience, as if nothing but
world<sup><SPAN href="#ftn40" id="body_ftn40">40</SPAN></sup> remained for us to cognise, and yet,
on the other hand, not to transgress the bounds of experience, and to think of
judging about things beyond them, as things in themselves.</p>
<p class="Standard">But we stop at this boundary if we limit our judgment merely to the
relation which the world may have to a Being whose very concept lies beyond all the
knowledge which we can attain within the world. For we then do not attribute to the
Supreme Being any of the properties in themselves, by which we represent objects of
experience, and thereby avoid dogmatic anthropomorphism; but we attribute them to his
relation to the world, and allow ourselves a symbolical anthropomorphism, which in fact
concerns language only, and not the object itself.</p>
<p class="Standard">If I say that we are compelled to consider the world, as if it were
the work of a Supreme Understanding and Will, I really say nothing more, than that a
watch, a ship, a regiment, bears the same relation to the watchmaker, the shipbuilder,
the commanding officer, as the world of sense (or whatever constitutes the substratum
of this complex of appearances) does to the Unknown, which I do not hereby cognise as
it is in itself, but as it is for me or in relation to the world, of which I am a
part.</p>
<p class="Standard">
§ 58. Such a cognition is one of analogy, and does not signify (as is commonly
understood) an imperfect similarity of two things, but a perfect similarity of
relations between two quite dissimilar things.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn41" id="body_ftn41">41</SPAN></sup> By means of this
analogy, however, there remains a concept of the Supreme Being sufficiently determined
<span class="T6">for us</span>, though we have left out everything that could deter mine it
absolutely or in itself; for we determine it as regards the world and as regards
ourselves, and more do we not require. The attacks which Hume makes upon those who
would determine this concept absolutely, by taking the materials for so doing from
themselves and the world, do not affect us; and he cannot object to us, that we have
nothing left if we give up the objective anthropomorphism of the concept of the
Supreme Being.</p>
<p class="Standard">
For let us assume at the outset (as Hume in his dialogues makes Philo grant
Cleanthes), as a necessary hypothesis, the deistical concept of the First Being, in
which this Being is thought by the mere ontological predicates of substance, of
cause, etc. This must be done, because reason, actuated in the sensible world by mere
conditions, which are themselves always conditional, cannot otherwise have any
satisfaction, and it therefore can be done without falling into anthropomorphism
(which transfers predicates from the world of sense to a Being quite distinct from
the world), because those predicates are mere categories, which, though they do not
give a determinate concept of God, yet give a concept not limited to any conditions
of sensibility. Thus nothing can prevent our predicating of this Being a causality
through reason with regard to the world, and thus passing to theism, without being
obliged to attribute to God in himself this kind of reason, as a property inhering in
him. For as to the former, the only possible way of prosecuting the use of reason (as
regards all possible experience, in complete harmony with itself) in the world of
sense to the highest point, is to assume a supreme reason as a cause of all the
connexions in the world. Such a principle must be quite advantageous to reason and
can hurt it nowhere in its application to nature. As to the latter, reason is thereby
not transferred as a property to the First Being in himself, but only to his relation
to the world of sense, and so anthropomorphism is entirely avoided. For nothing is
considered here but the cause of the form of reason which is perceived everywhere in
the world, and reason is attributed to the Supreme Being, so far as it contains the
ground of this form of reason in the world, but according to analogy only, that is,
so far as this expression shows merely the relation, which the Supreme Cause unknown
to us has to the world, in order to determine everything in it conformably to reason
in the highest degree. We are thereby kept from using reason as an attribute for the
purpose of conceiving God, but instead of conceiving the world in such a manner as is
necessary to have the greatest possible use of reason according to principle. We
thereby acknowledge that the Supreme Being is quite inscrutable and even unthinkable
in any definite way as to what he is in himself. We are thereby kept, on the one
hand, from making a transcendent use of the concepts which we have of reason as an
efficient cause (by means of the will), in order to determine the Divine Nature by
properties, which are only borrowed from human nature, and from losing ourselves in
gross and extravagant notions, and on the other hand from deluging the contemplation
of the world with hyperphysical modes of explanation according to our notions of
human reason, which we transfer to God, and so losing for this contemplation its
proper application, according to which it should be a rational study of mere nature,
and not a presumptuous derivation of its appearances from a Supreme Reason. The
expression suited to our feeble notions is, that we conceive the world as if it came,
as to its existence and internal plan, from a Supreme Reason, by which notion we both
cognise the constitution, which belongs to the world itself, yet without pretending
to determine the nature of its cause in itself, and on the other hand, we transfer
the ground of this constitution (of the form of reason in the world) upon the
relation of the Supreme Cause to the world, without finding the world sufficient by
itself for that purpose.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn42" id="body_ftn42">42</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">Thus the difficulties which seem to oppose theism disappear by
combining with Hume's principle—"not to carry the use of reason dogmatically beyond the
field of all possible experience"—this other principle, which he quite overlooked: "not
to consider the field of experience as one which bounds itself in the eye of our
reason." The <span class="T6">Critique of Pure Reason</span> here points out the true
mean between dogmatism, which Hume combats, and skepticism, which he would substitute
for it—a mean which is not like other means that we find advisable to determine for
ourselves as it were mechanically (by adopting something from one side and something
from the other), and by which nobody is taught a better way, but such a one as can be
accurately determined on principles.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 59. At the beginning of this annotation I made use of the
metaphor of a boundary, in order to establish the limits of reason in regard to its
suitable use. The world of sense contains merely appearances, which are not things in
themselves, but the understanding must assume these latter ones, viz., noumena. In our
reason both are comprised, and the question is, How does reason proceed to set
boundaries to the understanding as regards both these fields? Experience, which
contains all that belongs to the sensuous world, does not bound itself; it only
proceeds in every case from the conditioned to some other equally conditioned object.
Its boundary must lie quite without it, and this field is that of the pure beings of
the understanding. But this field, so far as the determination of the nature of these
beings is concerned, is an empty space for us, and if dogmatically-determined concepts
alone are in question, we cannot pass out of the field of possible experience. But as a
boundary itself is something positive, which belongs as well to that which lies within,
as to the space that lies without the given complex, it is still an actual positive
cognition, which reason only acquires by enlarging itself to this boundary, yet without
attempting to pass it; because it there finds itself in the presence of an empty space,
in which it can conceive forms of things, but not things themselves. But the setting of
a boundary to the field of the understanding by something, which is otherwise unknown
to it, is still a cognition which belongs to reason even at this standpoint, and by
which it is neither confined within the sensible, nor straying without it, but only
refers, as befits the knowledge of a boundary, to the relation between that which lies
without it, and that which is contained within it.</p>
<p class="Standard">Natural theology is such a concept at the boundary of human reason,
being constrained to look beyond this boundary to the Idea of a Supreme Being (and, for
practical purposes to that of an intelligible world also), not in order to determine
anything relatively to this pure creation of the understanding, which lies beyond the
world of sense, but in order to guide the use of reason within it according to
principles of the greatest possible (theoretical as well as practical) unity. For this
purpose we make use of the reference of the world of sense to an independent reason, as
the cause of all its connexions. Thereby we do not purely invent a being, but, as
beyond the sensible world there must be something that can only be thought by the pure
understanding, we determine that something in this particular way, though only of
course according to analogy.</p>
<p class="Standard">And thus there remains our original proposition, which is the
<span class="T6">résumé</span> of the whole <span class="T6">Critique</span>: "that reason by all its <span class="T6">a priori</span>
principles never teaches us anything more than objects of possible experience, and even
of these nothing more than can be cognised in experience." But this limitation does not
prevent reason leading us to the objective boundary of experience, viz., to the
reference to something which is not itself an object of experience, but is the ground
of all experience. Reason does not however teach us anything concerning the thing in
itself: it only instructs us as regards its own complete and highest use in the field
of possible experience. But this is all that can be reasonably desired in the present
case, and with which we have cause to be satisfied.</p>
<p class="Standard">§ 60. Thus we have fully exhibited metaphysics as it is actually
given in the natural predisposition of human reason, and in that which constitutes the
essential end of its pursuit, according to its subjective possibility. Though we have
found, that this merely natural use of such a predisposition of our reason, if no
discipline arising only from a scientific critique bridles and sets limits to it,
involves us in transcendent, either apparently or really conflicting, dialectical
syllogisms; and this fallacious metaphysics is not only unnecessary as regards the
promotion of our knowledge of nature, but even disadvantageous to it: there yet remains
a problem worthy of solution, which is to find out the natural ends intended by this
disposition to transcendent concepts in our reason, because everything that lies in
nature must be originally intended for some useful purpose.</p>
<p class="Standard">Such an inquiry is of a doubtful nature; and I acknowledge, that
what I can say about it is conjecture only, like every speculation about the first ends
of nature. The question does not concern the objective validity of metaphysical
judgments, but our natural predisposition to them, and therefore does not belong to the
system of metaphysics but to anthropology.</p>
<p class="Standard">When I compare all the transcendental Ideas, the totality of which
constitutes the particular problem of natural pure reason, compelling it to quit the
mere contemplation of nature, to transcend all possible experience, and in this
endeavor to produce the thing (be it knowledge or fiction) called metaphysics, I think
I perceive that the aim of this natural tendency is, to free our notions from the
fetters of experience and from the limits of the mere contemplation of nature so far as
at least to open to us a field containing mere objects for the pure understanding,
which no sensibility can reach, not indeed for the purpose of speculatively occupying
ourselves with them (for there we can find no ground to stand on), but because
practical principles, which, without finding some such scope for their necessary
expectation and hope, could not expand to the universality which reason unavoidably
requires from a moral point of view.</p>
<p class="Standard">So I find that the Psychological Idea (however little it may reveal
to me the nature of the human soul, which is higher than all concepts of experience),
shows the insufficiency of these concepts plainly enough, and thereby deters me from
materialism, the psychological notion of which is unfit for any explanation of nature,
and besides confines reason in practical respects. The Cosmological Ideas, by the
obvious insufficiency of all possible cognition of nature to satisfy reason in its
lawful inquiry, serve in the same manner to keep us from naturalism, which asserts
nature to be sufficient for itself. Finally, all natural necessity in the sensible
world is conditional, as it always presupposes the dependence of things upon others,
and unconditional necessity must be sought only in the unity of a cause different from
the world of sense. But as the causality of this cause, in its turn, were it merely
nature, could never render the existence of the contingent (as its consequent)
comprehensible, reason frees itself by means of the Theological Idea from fatalism,
(both as a blind natural necessity in the coherence of nature itself, without a first
principle, and as a blind causality of this principle itself), and leads to the concept
of a cause possessing freedom, or of a Supreme Intelligence. Thus the transcendental
Ideas serve, if not to instruct us positively, at least to destroy the rash assertions
of Materialism, of Naturalism, and of Fatalism, and thus to afford scope for the moral
Ideas beyond the field of speculation. These considerations, I should think, explain in
some measure the natural predisposition of which I spoke.</p>
<p class="Standard">The practical value, which a merely speculative science may have,
lies without the bounds of this science, and can therefore be considered as a scholion
merely, and like all scholia does not form part of the science itself. This application
however surely lies within the bounds of philosophy, especially of philosophy drawn
from the pure sources of reason, where its speculative use in metaphysics must
necessarily be at unity with its practical use in morals. Hence the unavoidable
dialectics of pure reason, considered in metaphysics, as a natural tendency, deserves
to be explained not as an illusion merely, which is to be removed, but also, if
possible, as a natural provision as regards its end, though this duty, a work of
supererogation, cannot justly be assigned to metaphysics proper.</p>
<p class="Standard">
The solutions of these questions which are treated in the chapter on the Regulative
Use of the Ideas of Pure Reason<sup><SPAN href="#ftn43" id="body_ftn43">43</SPAN></sup> should
be considered a second scholion
which however has a greater affinity with the subject of metaphysics. For there
certain rational principles are expounded which determine <span class="T6">a
priori</span> the order of nature or rather of the understanding, which seeks
nature's laws through experience. They seem to be constitutive and legislative with
regard to experience, though they spring from pure reason, which cannot be
considered, like the understanding, as a principle of possible experience. Now
whether or not this harmony rests upon the fact, that just as nature does not inhere
in appearances or in their source (the sensibility) itself, but only in so far as the
latter is in relation to the understanding, as also a systematic unity in applying
the understanding to bring about an entirety of all possible experience can only
belong to the understanding when in relation to reason; and whether or not experience
is in this way mediately subordinate to the legislation of reason: may be discussed
by those who desire to trace the nature of reason even beyond its use in metaphysics,
into the general principles of a history of nature; I have represented this task as
important, but not attempted its solution, in the book itself.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn44" id="body_ftn44">44</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">And thus I conclude the analytical solution of the main question
which I had proposed: How is metaphysics in general possible? by ascending from the
data of its actual use in its consequences, to the grounds of its possibility.</p>
<h1><SPAN name="__RefHeading___Toc3109" name="__RefHeading___Toc3109"></SPAN>SCHOLIA.</h1>
<h2>SOLUTION OF THE GENERAL QUESTION OF THE PROLEGOMENA, "HOW IS METAPHYSICS POSSIBLE AS A SCIENCE?"</h2>
<p class="Standard">METAPHYSICS, as a natural disposition of reason, is actual, but if
considered by itself alone (as the analytical solution of the third principal question
showed), dialectical and illusory. If we think of taking principles from it, and in
using them follow the natural, but on that account not less false, illusion, we can
never produce science, but only a vain dialectical art, in which one school may outdo
another, but none can ever acquire a just and lasting approbation.</p>
<p class="Standard">In order that as a science metaphysics may be entitled to claim not
mere fallacious plausibility, but in sight and conviction, a <span class="T6">Critique
of Reason</span> must itself exhibit the whole stock of <span class="T6">a
priori</span> concepts, their division according to their various sources (Sensibility,
Understanding, and Reason), together with a complete table of them, the analysis of all
these concepts, with all their consequences, especially by means of the deduction of
these concepts, the possibility of synthetical cognition <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, the principles of its application and finally its bounds, all in a
complete system. Critique, therefore, and critique alone, contains in itself the whole
well-proved and well-tested plan, and even all the means required to accomplish
metaphysics, as a science; by other ways and means it is impossible. The question here
therefore is not so much how this performance is possible, as how to set it going, and
induce men of clear heads to quit their hitherto perverted and fruitless cultivation
for one that will not deceive, and how such a union for the common end may best be
directed.</p>
<p class="Standard">This much is certain, that whoever has once tasted Critique will be
ever after disgusted with all dogmatical twaddle which he formerly put up with, because
his reason must have something, and could find nothing better for its support.</p>
<p class="Standard">Critique stands in the same relation to the common metaphysics of
the schools, as chemistry does to alchemy, or as astronomy to the astrology of the
fortune-teller. I pledge myself that nobody who has read through and through, and
grasped the principles of, the Critique even in these Prolegomena only, will ever
return to that old and sophistical pseudo-science; but will rather with a certain
delight look forward to metaphysics which is now indeed in his power, requiring no more
preparatory discoveries, and now at last affording permanent satisfaction to reason.
For here is an advantage upon which, of all possible sciences, metaphysics alone can
with certainty reckon: that it can be brought to such completion and fixity as to be
incapable of further change, or of any augmentation by new discoveries; because here
reason has the sources of its knowledge in itself, not in objects and their observation
(<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>), by which latter its stock of knowledge cannot be
further increased. When therefore it has exhibited the fundamental laws of its faculty
completely and so definitely as to avoid all misunderstanding, there remains nothing
for pure reason to cognise <span class="T6">a priori</span>, nay, there is even no
ground to raise further questions. The sure prospect of knowledge so definite and so
compact has a peculiar charm, even though we should set aside all its advantages, of
which I shall hereafter speak.</p>
<p class="Standard">All false art, all vain wisdom, lasts its time, but finally
destroys itself, and its highest culture is also the epoch of its decay. That this time
is come for metaphysics appears from the state into which it has fallen among all
learned nations, despite of all the zeal with which other sciences of every kind are
prosecuted. The old arrangement of our university studies still preserves its shadow;
now and then an Academy of Science tempts men by offering prizes to write essays on it,
but it is no longer numbered among thorough sciences; and let any one judge for himself
how a man of genius, if he were called a great metaphysician, would receive the
compliment, which may be well-meant, but is scarce envied by anybody.</p>
<p class="Standard">Yet, though the period of the downfall of all dogmatical
metaphysics has undoubtedly arrived, we are yet far from being able to say that the
period of its regeneration is come by means of a thorough and
complete <span class="T6">Critique of Reason</span>. All transitions from
a tendency to its contrary pass
through the stage of indifference, and this moment is the most dangerous for an author,
but, in my opinion, the most favorable for the science. For, when party spirit has died
out by a total dissolution of former connexions, minds are in the best state to listen
to several proposals for an organisation according to a new plan.</p>
<p class="Standard">When I say, that I hope these <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span>
will excite investigation in the field of critique and afford a new and promising
object to sustain the general spirit of philosophy, which seems on its speculative side
to want sustenance, I can imagine beforehand, that every one, whom the thorny paths of
my <span class="T6">Critique</span> have tired and put out of humor, will ask me, upon
what I found this hope. My answer is, upon the irresistible law of necessity.</p>
<p class="Standard">That the human mind will ever give up metaphysical researches is as
little to be expected as that we should prefer to give up breathing altogether, to
avoid inhaling impure air. There will therefore always be metaphysics in the world;
nay, every one, especially every man of reflexion, will have it, and for want of a
recognised standard, will shape it for himself after his own pattern. What has hitherto
been called metaphysics, cannot satisfy any critical mind, but to forego it entirely is
impossible; therefore a <span class="T6">Critique of Pure Reason</span> itself must now
be attempted or, if one exists, investigated, and brought to the full test, because
there is no other means of supplying this pressing want, which is something more than
mere thirst for knowledge.</p>
<p class="Standard">Ever since I have come to know critique, whenever I finish reading
a book of metaphysical contents, which, by the preciseness of its notions, by variety,
order, and an easy style, was not only entertaining but also helpful, I cannot help
asking, "Has this author indeed advanced metaphysics a single step?" The learned men,
whose works have been useful to me in other respects and always contributed to the
culture of my mental powers, will, I hope, forgive me for saying, that I have never
been able to find either their essays or my own less important ones (though self-love
may recommend them to me) to have advanced the science of metaphysics in the least, and
why?</p>
<p class="Standard">Here is the very obvious reason: metaphysics did not then exist as
a science, nor can it be gathered piecemeal, but its germ must be fully preformed in
the <span class="T6">Critique</span>. But in order to prevent all misconception, we
must remember what has been already said, that by the analytical treatment of our
concepts the understanding gains indeed a great deal, but the science (of metaphysics)
is thereby not in the least advanced, because these dissections of concepts are nothing
but the materials from which the intention is to carpenter our science. Let the
concepts of substance and of accident be ever so well dissected and determined, all
this is very well as a preparation for some future use. But if we cannot prove, that in
all which exists the substance endures, and only the accidents vary, our science is not
the least advanced by all our analyses.</p>
<p class="Standard">Metaphysics has hitherto never been able to
prove <span class="T6">a priori</span> either this proposition,
or that of sufficient reason, still, less
any more complex theorem, such as belongs to psychology or cosmology, or indeed any
synthetical proposition. By all its analysing therefore nothing is affected, nothing
obtained or forwarded, and the science, after all this bustle and noise, still remains
as it was in the days of Aristotle, though far better preparations were made for it
than of old, if the clue to synthetical cognitions had only been discovered.</p>
<p class="Standard">If any one thinks himself offended, he is at liberty to refute my
charge by producing a single synthetical proposition belonging to metaphysics, which he
would prove dogmatically <span class="T6">a priori</span>, for until he has actually
performed this feat, I shall not grant that he has truly advanced the science; even
should this proposition be sufficiently confirmed by common experience. No demand can
be more moderate or more equitable, and in the (inevitably certain) event of its
non-performance, no assertion more just, than that hitherto metaphysics has never
existed as a science.</p>
<p class="Standard">But there are two things which, in case the challenge be accepted,
I must deprecate: first, trifling about probability and conjecture, which are suited as
little to metaphysics, as to geometry; and secondly, a decision by means of the magic
wand of common sense, which does not convince every one, but which accommodates itself
to personal peculiarities.</p>
<p class="Standard">For as to the former, nothing can be more absurd, than in
metaphysics, a philosophy from pure reason to think of grounding our judgments upon
probability and conjecture. Everything that is to be cognised <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, is thereby announced as apodeictically certain, and must therefore be
proved in this way. We might as well think of grounding geometry or arithmetic upon
conjectures. As to the doctrine of chances in the latter, it does not contain probable,
but perfectly certain, judgments concerning the degree of the probability of certain
cases, under given uniform conditions, which, in the sum of all possible cases,
infallibly happen according to the rule, though it is not sufficiently determined in
respect to every single chance. Conjectures (by means of induction and of analogy) can
be suffered in an empirical science of nature only, yet even there the possibility at
least of what we assume must be quite certain.</p>
<p class="Standard">The appeal to common sense is even more absurd, when concept and
principles are announced as valid, not in so far as they hold with regard to
experience, but even beyond the conditions of experience. For what is common sense? It
is normal good sense, so far it judges right. But what is normal good sense? It is the
faculty of the knowledge and use of rules <span class="T6">in concreto</span>, as
distinguished from the speculative understanding, which is a faculty of knowing rules
<span class="T6">in abstracto</span>. Common sense can hardly understand the rule,
"that every event is determined by means of its cause," and can never comprehend it
thus generally. It therefore demands an example from experience, and when it hears that
this rule means nothing but what it always thought when a pane was broken or a
kitchen-utensil missing, it then understands the principle and grants it. Common sense
therefore is only of use so far as it can see its rules (though they actually are
<span class="T6">a priori</span>) confirmed by experience; consequently to comprehend
them <span class="T6">a priori</span>, or independently of experience, belongs to the
speculative understanding, and lies quite beyond the horizon of common sense. But the
province of metaphysics is entirely confined to the latter kind of knowledge, and it is
certainly a bad index of common sense to appeal to it as a witness, for it cannot here
form any opinion whatever, and men look down upon it with contempt until they are in
difficulties, and can find in their speculation neither in nor out.</p>
<p class="Standard">It is a common subterfuge of those false friends of common sense
(who occasionally prize it highly, but usually despise it) to say, that there must
surely be at all events some propositions which are immediately certain, and of which
there is no occasion to give any proof, or even any account at all, because we
otherwise could never stop inquiring into the grounds of our judgments. But if we
except the principle of contradiction, which is not sufficient to show the truth of
synthetical judgments, they can never adduce, in proof of this privilege, anything else
indubitable, which they can immediately ascribe to common sense, except mathematical
propositions, such as twice two make four, between two points there is but one straight
line, etc. But these judgments are radically different from those of metaphysics. For
in mathematics I myself can by thinking construct whatever I represent to myself as
possible by a concept: I add to the first two the other two, one by one, and myself
make the number four, or I draw in thought from one point to another all manner of
lines, equal as well as unequal; yet I can draw one only, which is like itself in all
its parts. But I cannot, by all my power of thinking, extract from the concept of a
thing the concept of something else, whose existence is necessarily connected with the
former, but I must call in experience. And though my understanding furnishes me
<span class="T6">a priori</span> (yet only in reference to possible experience) with
the concept of such a connexion (i.e., causation), I cannot exhibit it, like the
concepts of mathematics, by (<span class="T6">Anschauung</span>) visualising them,
<span class="T6">a priori</span>, and so show its possibility <span class="T6">a
priori</span>. This concept, together with the principles of its application, always
requires, if it shall hold <span class="T6">a priori</span>—as is requisite in
metaphysics—a justification and deduction of its possibility, because we cannot
otherwise know how far it holds good, and whether it can be used in experience only or
beyond it also.</p>
<p class="Standard">Therefore in metaphysics, as a speculative science of pure reason,
we can never appeal to common sense, but may do so only when we are forced to surrender
it, and to renounce all purely speculative cognition, which must always be knowledge,
and consequently when we forego metaphysics itself and its instruction, for the sake of
adopting a rational faith which alone may be possible for us, and sufficient to our
wants, perhaps even more salutary than knowledge itself. For in this case the attitude
of the question is quite altered. Metaphysics must be science, not only as a whole, but
in all its parts, otherwise it is nothing; because, as a speculation of pure reason, it
finds a hold only on general opinions. Beyond its field, however, probability and
common sense may be used with advantage and justly, but on quite special principles, of
which the importance always depends on the reference to practical life.</p>
<p class="Standard">This is what I hold myself justified in requiring for the
possibility of metaphysics as a science.</p>
<h1><SPAN name="__RefHeading___Toc3111" name="__RefHeading___Toc3111"></SPAN>APPENDIX.</h1>
<h2>ON WHAT CAN BE DONE TO MAKE METAPHYSICS ACTUAL AS A SCIENCE.</h2>
<p class="Standard">SINCE all the ways heretofore taken have failed to attain the goal,
and since without a preceding critique of pure reason it is not likely ever to be
attained, the present essay now before the public has a fair title to an accurate and
careful investigation, except it be thought more advisable to give up all pretensions
to metaphysics, to which, if men but would consistently adhere to their purpose, no
objection can be made.</p>
<p class="Standard">If we take the course of things as it is, not as it ought to be,
there are two sorts of judgments: (1) one a judgment which precedes investigation (in
our case one in which the reader from his own metaphysics pronounces judgment on the
<span class="T6">Critique of Pure Reason</span> which was intended to discuss the very
possibility of metaphysics); (2) the other a judgment subsequent to investigation. In
the latter the reader is enabled to waive for awhile the consequences of the critical
researches that may be repugnant to his formerly adopted metaphysics, and first
examines the grounds whence those consequences are derived. If what common metaphysics
propounds were demonstrably certain, as for instance the theorems of geometry, the
former way of judging would hold good. For if the consequences of certain principles
are repugnant to established truths, these principles are false and without further
inquiry to be repudiated. But if metaphysics does not possess a stock of indisputably
certain (synthetical) propositions, and should it even be the case that there are a
number of them, which, though among the most specious, are by their consequences in
mutual collision, and if no sure criterion of the truth of peculiarly metaphysical
(synthetical) propositions is to be met with in it, then the former way of judging is
not admissible, but the investigation of the principles of the critique must precede
all judgments as to its value.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">ON A SPECIMEN OF A JUDGMENT OF THE
CRITIQUE PRIOR TO ITS EXAMINATION.</p>
<p class="Standard">This judgment is to be found in the <span class="T6">Göttingischen gelehrten
Anzeigen</span>, in the supplement to the third division, of January 19, 1782,
pages 40 et seq.</p>
<p class="Standard">When an author who is familiar with the subject of his work and
endeavors to present his independent reflexions in its elaboration, falls into the
hands of a reviewer who, in his turn, is keen enough to discern the points on which the
worth or worthlessness of the book rests, who does not cling to words, but goes to the
heart of the subject, sifting and testing more than the mere principles which the
author takes as his point of departure, the severity of the judgment may indeed
displease the latter, but the public does not care, as it gains thereby; and the author
himself may be contented, as an opportunity of correcting or explaining his positions
is afforded to him at an early date by the examination of a competent judge, in such a
manner, that if he believes himself fundamentally right, he can remove in time any
stone of offence that might hurt the success of his work.</p>
<p class="Standard">I find myself, with my reviewer, in quite another position. He
seems not to see at all the real matter of the investigation with which (successfully
or unsuccessfully) I have been occupied. It is either impatience at thinking out a
lengthy work, or vexation at a threatened reform of a science in which he believed he
had brought everything to perfection long ago, or, what I am unwilling to imagine, real
narrowmindedness, that prevents him from ever carrying his thoughts beyond his
school-metaphysics. In short, he passes impatiently in review a long series of
propositions, by which, without knowing their premises, we can think nothing,
intersperses here and there his censure, the reason of which the reader understands
just as little as the propositions against which it is directed; and hence [his report]
can neither serve the public nor damage me, in the judgment of experts. I should, for
these reasons, have passed over this judgment altogether, were it not that it may
afford me occasion for some explanations which may in some cases save the readers of
these <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span> from a misconception.</p>
<p class="Standard">In order to take a position from which my reviewer could most
easily set the whole work in a most unfavorable light, without venturing to trouble
himself with any special investigation, he begins and ends by saying:</p>
<p class="Standard">
"This work is a system of transcendent (or, as he translates it, of higher)
Idealism."<sup><SPAN href="#ftn45" id="body_ftn45" name="body_ftn45">45</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">A glance at this line soon showed me the sort of criticism that I
had to expect, much as though the reviewer were one who had never seen or heard of
geometry, having found a Euclid, and coming upon various figures in turning over its
leaves, were to say, on being asked his opinion of it: "The work is a text-book of
drawing; the author introduces a peculiar terminology, in order to give dark,
incomprehensible directions, which in the end teach nothing more than what every one
can effect by a fair natural accuracy of eye, etc."</p>
<p class="Standard">Let us see, in the meantime, what sort of an idealism it is that
goes through my whole work, although it does not by a long way constitute the soul of
the system.</p>
<p class="Standard">The dictum of all genuine idealists from the Eleatic school to
Bishop Berkeley, is contained in this formula: "All cognition through the senses and
experience is nothing but sheer illusion, and only, in the ideas of the pure
understanding and reason there is truth."</p>
<p class="Standard">The principle that throughout dominates and determines my Idealism,
is on the contrary: "All cognition of things merely from pure understanding or pure
reason is nothing but sheer illusion, and only in experience is there truth."</p>
<p class="Standard">But this is directly contrary to idealism proper. How came I then
to use this expression for quite an opposite purpose, and how came my reviewer to see
it everywhere?</p>
<p class="Standard">
The solution of this difficulty rests on something that could have been very easily
understood from the general bearing of the work, if the reader had only desired to do
so. Space and time, together with all that they contain, are not things nor qualities
in themselves, but belong merely to the appearances of the latter: up to this point I
am one in confession with the above idealists. But these, and amongst them more
particularly Berkeley, regarded space as a mere empirical presentation that, like the
phenomenon it contains, is only known to us by means of experience or perception,
together with its determinations. I, on the contrary, prove in the first place, that
space (and also time, which Berkeley did not consider) and all its determinations
<span class="T6">a priori</span>, can be cognised by us, because, no less than time,
it inheres in our sensibility as a pure form before all perception or experience and
makes all intuition of the same, and therefore all its phenomena, possible. It
follows from this, that as truth rests on universal and necessary laws as its
criteria, experience, according to Berkeley, can have no criteria of truth, because
its phenomena (according to him) have nothing <span class="T6">a priori</span> at
their foundation; whence it follows, that they are nothing but sheer illusion;
whereas with us, space and time (in conjunction with the pure conceptions of the
understanding) prescribe their law to all possible experience <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, and at the same time afford the <span class="T17">certain</span>
criterion for distinguishing truth from illusion therein.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn46" id="body_ftn46">46</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">My so-called (properly critical) Idealism is of quite a special
character, in that it subverts the ordinary idealism, and that through it all cognition
<span class="T6">a priori</span>, even that of geometry, first receives objective
reality, which, without my demonstrated ideality of space and time, could not be
maintained by the most zealous realists. This being the state of the case, I could have
wished, in order to avoid all misunderstanding, to have named this conception of mine
otherwise, but to alter it altogether was impossible. It may be permitted me however,
in future, as has been above intimated, to term it the formal, or better still, the
critical Idealism, to distinguish it from the dogmatic Idealism of Berkeley, and from
the sceptical Idealism of Descartes.</p>
<p class="Standard">
Beyond this, I find nothing further remarkable in the judgment of my book. The
reviewer criticises here and there, makes sweeping criticisms, a mode prudently
chosen, since it does not betray one's own knowledge or ignorance; a single thorough
criticism in detail, had it touched the main question, as is only fair, would have
exposed, it may be my error, or it may be my reviewer's measure of insight into this
species of research. It was, moreover, not a badly conceived plan, in order at once
to take from readers (who are accustomed to form their conceptions of books from
newspaper reports) the desire to read the book itself, to pour out in one breath a
number of passages in succession, torn from their connexion, and their grounds of
proof and explanations, and which must necessarily sound senseless, especially
considering how antipathetic they are to all school-metaphysics; to exhaust the
reader's patience <span class="T6">ad nauseam</span>, and then, after having made me
acquainted with the sensible proposition that persistent illusion is truth, to
conclude with the crude paternal moralisation: to what end, then, the quarrel with
accepted language, to what end, and whence, the idealistic distinction? A judgment
which seeks all that is characteristic of my book, first supposed to be
metaphysically heterodox, in a mere innovation of the nomenclature, proves clearly
that my would-be judge has understood nothing of the subject, and in addition, has
not understood himself.<sup><SPAN href="#ftn47" id="body_ftn47">47</SPAN></sup></p>
<p class="Standard">My reviewer speaks like a man who is conscious of important and
superior insight which he keeps hidden; for I am aware of nothing recent with respect
to metaphysics that could justify his tone. But he should not withhold his discoveries
from the world, for there are doubtless many who, like myself, have not been able to
find in all the fine things that have for long past been written in this department,
anything that has advanced the science by so much as a fingerbreadth; we find indeed
the giving a new point to definitions, the supplying of lame proofs with new crutches,
the adding to the crazy-quilt of metaphysics fresh patches or changing its pattern; but
all this is not what the world requires. The world is tired of metaphysical assertions;
it wants the possibility of the science, the sources from which certainty therein can
be derived, and certain criteria by which it may distinguish the dialectical illusion
of pure reason from truth. To this the critic seems to possess a key, otherwise he
would never have spoken out in such a high tone.</p>
<p class="Standard">But I am inclined to suspect that no such requirement of the
science has ever entered his thoughts, for in that case he would have directed his
judgment to this point, and even a mistaken attempt in such an important matter, would
have won his respect. If that be the case, we are once more good friends. He may
penetrate as deeply as he likes into metaphysics, without any one hindering him; only
as concerns that which lies outside metaphysics, its sources, which are to be found in
reason, he cannot form a judgment. That my suspicion is not without foundation, is
proved by the fact that he does not mention a word about the possibility of synthetic
knowledge <span class="T6">a priori</span>, the special problem upon the solution of
which the fate of metaphysics wholly rests, and upon which my <span class="T6">Critique</span> (as well
as the present <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span>)
entirely hinges. The Idealism he encountered, and which he hung upon, was only taken up
in the doctrine as the sole means of solving the above problem (although it received
its confirmation on other grounds), and hence he must have shown either that the above
problem does not possess the importance I attribute to it (even in these <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span>), or
that by my conception of appearances, it is either not
solved at all, or can be better solved in another way; but I do not find a word of this
in the criticism. The reviewer, then, understands nothing of my work, and possibly also
nothing of the spirit and essential nature of metaphysics itself; and it is not, what I
would rather assume, the hurry of a man incensed at the labor of plodding through so
many obstacles, that threw an unfavorable shadow over the work lying before him, and
made its fundamental features unrecognisable.</p>
<p class="Standard">There is a good deal to be done before a learned journal, it
matters not with what care its writers may be selected, can maintain its otherwise
well-merited reputation, in the field of metaphysics as elsewhere. Other sciences and
branches of knowledge have their standard. Mathematics has it, in itself; history and
theology, in profane or sacred books; natural science and the art of medicine, in
mathematics and experience; jurisprudence, in law books; and even matters of taste in
the examples of the ancients. But for the judgment of the thing called metaphysics, the
standard has yet to be found. I have made an attempt to determine it, as well as its
use. What is to be done, then, until it be found, when works of this kind have to be
judged of? If they are of a dogmatic character, one may do what one likes; no one will
play the master over others here for long, before someone else appears to deal with him
in the same manner. If, however, they are critical in their character, not indeed with
reference to other works, but to reason itself, so that the standard of judgment cannot
be assumed but has first of all to be sought for, then, though objection and blame may
indeed be permitted, yet a certain degree of leniency is indispensable, since the need
is common to us all, and the lack of the necessary insight makes the high-handed
attitude of judge unwarranted.</p>
<p class="Standard">In order, however, to connect my defence with the interest of the
philosophical commonwealth, I propose a test, which must be decisive as to the mode,
whereby all metaphysical investigations may be directed to their common purpose. This
is nothing more than what formerly mathematicians have done, in establishing the
advantage of their methods by competition. I challenge my critic to demonstrate, as is
only just, on <span class="T6">a priori</span> grounds, in his way, a single really
metaphysical principle asserted by him. Being metaphysical it must be synthetic and
cognised <span class="T6">a priori</span> from conceptions, but it may also be any one
of the most indispensable principles, as for instance, the principle of the persistence
of substance, or of the necessary determination of events in the world by their causes.
If he cannot do this (silence however is confession), he must admit, that as
metaphysics without apodeictic certainty of propositions of this kind is nothing at
all, its possibility or impossibility must before all things be established in a
critique of the pure reason. Thus he is bound either to confess that my principles in
the <span class="T6">Critique</span> are correct, or he must prove their invalidity.
But as I can already foresee, that, confidently as he has hitherto relied on the
certainty of his principles, when it comes to a strict test he will not find a single
one in the whole range of metaphysics he can bring forward, I will concede to him an
advantageous condition, which can only be expected in such a competition, and will
relieve him of the <span class="T6">onus probandi</span> by laying it on myself.</p>
<p class="Standard">He finds in these <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span> and in my
<span class="T6">Critique</span> (chapter on the "Theses and Antitheses of the Four
Antinomies") eight propositions, of which two and two contradict one another, but each
of which necessarily belongs to metaphysics, by which it must either be accepted or
rejected (although there is not one that has not in this time been held by some
philosopher). Now he has the liberty of selecting any one of these eight propositions
at his pleasure, and accepting it without any proof, of which I shall make him a
present, but only one (for waste of time will be just as little serviceable to him as
to me), and then of attacking my proof of the opposite proposition. If I can save this
one, and at the same time show, that according to principles which every dogmatic
metaphysics must necessarily recognise, the opposite of the proposition adopted by him
can be just as clearly proved, it is thereby established that metaphysics has an
hereditary failing, not to be explained, much less set aside, until we ascend to its
birth-place, pure reason itself, and thus my <span class="T6">Critique</span> must
either be accepted or a better one take its place; it must at least be studied, which
is the only thing I now require. If, on the other hand, I cannot save my demonstration,
then a synthetic proposition <span class="T6">a priori</span> from dogmatic principles
is to be reckoned to the score of my opponent, then also I will deem my impeachment of
ordinary metaphysics as unjust, and pledge myself to recognise his stricture on my
<span class="T6">Critique</span> as justified (although this would not be the
consequence by a long way). To this end it would be necessary, it seems to me, that he
should step out of his incognito. Otherwise I do not see how it could be avoided, that
instead of dealing with one, I should be honored by several problems coming from
anonymous and unqualified opponents.</p>
<p class="NormCentSpaceBeforeAfter">PROPOSALS AS TO AN INVESTIGATION OF THE CRITIQUE UPON WHICH A
JUDGMENT MAY FOLLOW.</p>
<p class="Standard">I feel obliged to the honored public even for the silence with
which it for a long time favored my <span class="T6">Critique</span>, for this proves
at least a postponement of judgment, and some supposition that in a work, leaving all
beaten tracks and striking out on a new path, in which one cannot at once perhaps so
easily find one's way, something may perchance lie, from which an important but at
present dead branch of human knowledge may derive new life and productiveness. Hence
may have originated a solicitude for the as yet tender shoot, lest it be destroyed by a
hasty judgment. A test of a judgment, delayed for the above reasons, is now before my
eye in the <span class="T6">Gothaischen gelehrten Zeitung</span>, the thoroughness of
which every reader will himself perceive, from the clear and unperverted presentation
of a fragment of one of the first principles of my work, without taking into
consideration my own suspicious praise.</p>
<p class="Standard">And now I propose, since an extensive structure cannot be judged of
as a whole from a hurried glance, to test it piece by piece from its foundations, so
thereby the present <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span> may fitly be used as a general
outline with which the work itself may occasionally be compared. This notion, if it
were founded on nothing more than my conceit of importance, such as vanity commonly
attributes to one's own productions, would be immodest and would deserve to be
repudiated with disgust. But now, the interests of speculative philosophy have arrived
at the point of total extinction, while human reason hangs upon them with
inextinguishable affection, and only after having been ceaselessly deceived does it
vainly attempt to change this into indifference.</p>
<p class="Standard">In our thinking age it is not to be supposed but that many
deserving men would use any good opportunity of working for the common interest of the
more and more enlightened reason, if there were only some hope of attaining the goal.
Mathematics, natural science, laws, arts, even morality, etc., do not completely fill
the soul; there is always a space left over, reserved for pure and speculative reason,
the vacuity of which prompts us to seek in vagaries, buffooneries, and myticism for
what seems to be employment and entertainment, but what actually is mere pastime; in
order to deaden the troublesome voice of reason, which in accordance with its nature
requires something that can satisfy it, and not merely subserve other ends or the
interests of our inclinations. A consideration, therefore, which is concerned only with
reason as it exists for it itself, has as I may reasonably suppose a great fascination
for every one who has attempted thus to extend his conceptions, and I may even say a
greater than any other theoretical branch of knowledge, for which he would not
willingly exchange it, because here all other cognitions, and even purposes, must meet
and unite themselves in a whole.</p>
<p class="Standard">I offer, therefore, these <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span> as a
sketch and text-book for this investigation, and not the work itself. Although I am
even now perfectly satisfied with the latter as far as contents, order, and mode of
presentation, and the care that I have expended in weighing and testing every sentence
before writing it down, are concerned (for it has taken me years to satisfy myself
fully, not only as regards the whole, but in some cases even as to the sources of one
particular proposition); yet I am not quite satisfied with my exposition in some
sections of the doctrine of elements, as for instance in the deduction of the
conceptions of the Understanding, or in that on the paralogisms of pure reason, because
a certain diffuseness takes away from their clearness, and in place of them, what is
here said in the <span class="T6">Prolegomena</span> respecting these sections, may be
made the basis of the test.</p>
<p class="Standard">It is the boast of the Germans that where steady and continuous
industry are requisite, they can carry things farther than other nations. If this
opinion be well founded, an opportunity, a business, presents itself, the successful
issue of which we can scarcely doubt, and in which all thinking men can equally take
part, though they have hitherto been unsuccessful in accomplishing it and in thus
confirming the above good opinion. But this is chiefly because the science in question
is of so peculiar a kind, that it can be at once brought to completion and to that
enduring state that it will never be able to be brought in the least degree farther or
increased by later discoveries, or even changed (leaving here out of account adornment
by greater clearness in some places, or additional uses), and this is an advantage no
other science has or can have, because there is none so fully isolated and independent
of others, and which is concerned with the faculty of cognition pure and simple. And
the present moment seems, moreover, not to be unfavorable to my expectation, for just
now, in Germany, no one seems to know wherewith to occupy himself, apart from the
so-called useful sciences, so as to pursue not mere play, but a business possessing an
enduring purpose.</p>
<p class="Standard">To discover the means how the endeavors of the learned may be
united in such a purpose, I must leave to others. In the meantime, it is my intention
to persuade any one merely to follow my propositions, or even to flatter me with the
hope that he will do so; but attacks, repetitions, limitations, or confirmation,
completion, and extension, as the case may be, should be appended. If the matter be but
investigated from its foundation, it cannot fail that a system, albeit not my own,
shall be erected, that shall be a possession for future generations for which they may
have reason to be grateful.</p>
<p class="Standard">It would lead us too far here to show what kind of metaphysics may
be expected, when only the principles of criticism have been perfected, and how,
because the old false feathers have been pulled out, she need by no means appear poor
and reduced to an insignificant figure, but may be in other respects richly and
respectably adorned. But other and great uses which would result from such a reform,
strike one immediately. The ordinary metaphysics had its uses, in that it sought out
the elementary conceptions of the pure understanding in order to make them clear
through analysis, and definite by explanation. In this way it was a training for
reason, in whatever direction it might be turned; but this was all the good it did;
service was subsequently effaced when it favored conceit by venturesome assertions,
sophistry by subtle distinctions and adornment, and shallowness by the ease with which
it decided the most difficult problems by means of a little school-wisdom, which is
only the more seductive the more it has the choice, on the one hand, of taking
something from the language of science, and on the other from that of popular
discourse, thus being everything to everybody, but in reality nothing at all. By
criticism, however, a standard is given to our judgment, whereby knowledge may be with
certainty distinguished from pseudo-science, and firmly founded, being brought into
full operation in metaphysics; a mode of thought extending by degrees its beneficial
influence over every other use of reason, at once infusing into it the true
philosophical spirit. But the service also that metaphysics performs for theology, by
making it independent of the judgment of dogmatic speculation, thereby assuring it
completely against the attacks of all such opponents, is certainly not to be valued
lightly. For ordinary metaphysics, although it promised the latter much advantage,
could not keep this promise, and moreover, by summoning speculative dogmatics to its
assistance, did nothing but arm enemies against itself. Mysticism, which can prosper in
a rationalistic age only when it hides itself behind a system of school-metaphysics,
under the protection of which it may venture to rave with a semblance of rationality,
is driven from this, its last hiding-place, by critical philosophy. Last, but not
least, it cannot be otherwise than important to a teacher of metaphysics, to be able to
say with universal assent, that what he expounds is Science, and that thereby genuine
services will be rendered to the commonweal.</p>
<hr>
<p id="ftn1" class="Standard"><sup>1</sup> Prolegomena means literally prefatory
or introductory remarks. It is the neuter plural of the present passive participle
of προλέγειν, to speak before, i.e., to make introductory remarks before beginning one's regular
discourse. <SPAN href="#body_ftn1">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn2" class="Standard"><sup>2</sup> Mahaffy not incorrectly translates
"spirals winding opposite ways," and Mr. Bax follows him verbatim even to the
repetition of the footnote. <SPAN href="#body_ftn2">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn3" class="Standard"><sup>3</sup> The French <span class="T6">cento</span> is still
in use. <SPAN href="#body_ftn3">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn4" class="Standard"><sup>4</sup> κέντρων, (1)
one that bears the marks of the κέντρο, goad; a rogue, (2) a
patched cloth; (3) any kind of patchwork, especially verses made up of scraps from
other authors. <SPAN href="#body_ftn4">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn5" class="StandardFullEmBelow"><sup>5</sup> Says Horace:</p>
<p class="StandardIndentFlushNoSpace">"Rusticus expectat, dum defluat amnis, at ille</p>
<p class="StandardIndentFlushNoSpace">Labitur et labetur in omne volubilis aevum;"</p>
<p class="StandardIndentFlushNoSpace">"A rustic fellow waiteth on the shore</p>
<p class="StandardIndentFlushNoSpace">For the river to flow away,</p>
<p class="StandardIndentFlushNoSpace">But the river flows, and flows on as before,</p>
<p class="StandardIndentFlushSpaceBelow">And it flows forever and aye." <SPAN href="#body_ftn5">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn6" class="Standard"><sup>6</sup> Nevertheless Hume
called this very destructive science metaphysics and attached to it great value.
Metaphysics and morals [he declares in the fourth part of his Essays] are the most
important branches of science; mathematics and physics are not nearly so
important. But the acute man merely
regarded the negative use arising from the moderation of extravagant claims of
speculative reason, and the complete settlement of the many endless and troublesome
controversies that mislead mankind. He overlooked the positive injury which results, if
reason be deprived of its most important prospects, which can alone supply to the will
the highest aim for all its endeavor. <SPAN href="#body_ftn6">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn7" class="Standard"><sup>7</sup> The term <span class="T6">Anschauung</span> here
used means sense-perception. It is that which is given to the senses and apprehended
immediately, as an object is seen by merely looking at it. The translation <span class="T6">intuition</span>,
though etymologically correct, is misleading. In the present
passage the term is not used in its technical significance but means "practical
experience."—<span class="T6">Ed</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn7">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn8" class="Standard"><sup>8</sup> The term <span class="T6">apodeictic</span> is
borrowed by Kant from Aristotle who uses it in the sense of "certain beyond dispute."
The word is derived from ἀποδείκνυμι (= <span class="T6">I
show</span>) and is contrasted to dialectic propositions, i.e., such statements as
admit of controversy.—<span class="T6">Ed</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn8">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn9" class="Standard"><sup>9</sup> It is unavoidable that as knowledge
advances, certain expressions which have become classical, after having been used since
the infancy of science, will be found inadequate and unsuitable, and a newer and more
appropriate application of the terms will give rise to confusion. [This is the case
with the term "analytical."] The analytical method, so far as it is opposed to the
synthetical, is very different from that which constitutes the essence of analytical
propositions: it signifies only that we start from what is sought, as if it were given,
and ascend to the only conditions under which it is possible. In this method we often
use nothing but synthetical propositions, as in mathematical analysis, and it were
better to term it the regressive method, in contradistinction to the synthetic or
progressive. A principal part of Logic too is distinguished by the name of Analytics,
which here signifies the logic of truth in contrast to Dialectics, without considering
whether the cognitions belonging to it are analytical or synthetical. <SPAN href="#body_ftn9">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn10" class="Standard"><sup>10</sup> This whole paragraph (§ 9)
will be better understood when compared with <SPAN href="#Page40">Remark I.</SPAN>, following
this section, appearing in the present edition on page 40.—<span class="T6">Ed</span>.
<SPAN href="#body_ftn10">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn11" class="Standard"><sup>11</sup> Empirical judgments (<span class="T6">empirische Urtheile</span>)
are either mere statements of fact, viz., records of a
perception, or statements of a natural law, implying a causal connexion between two
facts. The former Kant calls "judgments of perception" (<span class="T6">Wahrnehmungsurtheile</span>) the latter "judgments of experience" (<span class="T6">Erhfahrungsurtheile</span>).—<span class="T6">Ed.</span> <SPAN href="#body_ftn11">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn12" class="Standard"><sup>12</sup> I freely grant that these examples
do not represent such judgments of perception as ever could become judgments of
experience, even though a concept of the understanding were superadded, because they
refer merely to feeling, which everybody knows to be merely subjective, and which of
course can never be attributed to the object, and consequently never become objective.
I only wished to give here an example of a judgment that is merely subjectively valid,
containing no ground for universal validity, and thereby for a relation to the object.
An example of the judgments of perception, which become judgments of experience by
superadded concepts of the understanding, will be given in the next note. <SPAN href="#body_ftn12">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn13" class="Standard"><sup>13</sup> As an easier example, we may take
the following: "When the sun shines on the stone, it grows warm." This judgment,
however often I and others may have perceived it, is a mere judgment of perception, and
contains no necessity; perceptions are only usually conjoined in this manner. But if I
say, "The sun warms the stone," I add to the perception a concept of the understanding,
viz., that of cause, which connects with the concept of sunshine that of heat as a
necessary consequence, and the synthetical judgment becomes of necessity universally
valid, viz., objective, and is converted from a perception into experience. <SPAN href="#body_ftn13">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn14" class="Standard"><sup>14</sup> This name seems preferable to the
term <span class="T6">particularia</span>, which is used for these judgments in logic.
For the latter implies the idea that they are not universal. But when I start from
unity (in single judgments) and so proceed to universality, I must not [even indirectly
and negatively] imply any reference to universality. I think plurality merely without
universality, and not the exception from universality. This is necessary, if logical
considerations shall form the basis of the pure concepts of the understanding. However,
there is no need of making changes in logic. <SPAN href="#body_ftn14">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn15" class="Standard"><sup>15</sup> But how does this proposition,
"that judgments of experience contain necessity in the synthesis of perceptions," agree
with my statement so often before inculcated, that "experience as cognition
<span class="T6">a posteriori</span> can afford contingent judgments only?" When I say
that experience teaches me something, I mean only the perception that lies in
experience,—for example, that heat always follows the shining of the sun on a stone;
consequently the proposition of experience is always so far accidental. That this heat
necessarily follows the shining of the sun is contained indeed in the judgment of
experience (by means of the concept of cause), yet is a fact not learned by experience;
for conversely, experience is first of all generated by this addition of the concept of
the understanding (of cause) to perception. How perception attains this addition may be
seen by referring in the <span class="T6">Critique</span> itself to the section on the
Transcendental faculty of Judgment [viz., in the first edition, <span class="T6">Von
dem Schematismus der reinen Verstandsbegriffe</span>]. <SPAN href="#body_ftn15">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn16" class="Standard"><sup>16</sup> [Kant uses the term physiological
in its etymological meaning as "pertaining to the science of physics," i.e., nature in
general, not as we use the term now as "pertaining to the functions of the living
body." Accordingly it has been translated "physical."—<span class="T6">Ed.</span>] <SPAN href="#body_ftn16">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn17" class="Standard"><sup>17</sup> The three following paragraphs will
hardly be understood unless reference be made to what the <span class="T6">Critique</span> itself
says on the subject of the Principles; they will, however,
be of service in giving a general view of the Principles, and in fixing the attention
on the main points. <SPAN href="#body_ftn17">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn18" class="Standard"><sup>18</sup> [Kant uses here the equivocal term
<span class="T6">Wechselwirkung</span>.—<span class="T6">Ed</span>.] <SPAN href="#body_ftn18">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn19" class="Standard"><sup>19</sup> Heat and light are in a small space
just as large as to degree as in a large one; in like manner the internal
representations, pain, consciousness in general, whether they last a short or a long
time, need not vary as to the degree. Hence the quantity is here in a point and in a
moment just as great as in any space or time however great. Degrees are therefore
capable of increase, but not in intuition, rather in mere sensation (or the quantity of
the degree of an intuition). Hence they can only be estimated quantitatively by the
relation of 1 to 0, viz., by their capability of decreasing by infinite intermediate
degrees to disappearance, or of increasing from naught through infinite gradations to a
determinate sensation in a certain time. <span class="T6">Quantitas qualitatis est
gradus</span> [i.e., the degrees of quality must be measured by equality]. <SPAN href="#body_ftn19">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn20" class="Standard"><sup>20</sup> We speak of the "intelligible
world," not (as the usual expression is) "intellectual world." For cognitions are
intellectual through the understanding, and refer to our world of sense also; but
objects, so far as they can be represented merely by the understanding, and to which
none of our sensible intuitions can refer, are termed "intelligible." But as some
possible intuition must correspond to every object, we would have to assume an
understanding that intuites things immediately; but of such we have not the least
notion, nor have we of the <span class="T6">things of the understanding</span>
[Verstandeswesen], to which it should be applied. <SPAN href="#body_ftn20">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn21" class="Standard"><sup>21</sup> Crusius alone thought of a
compromise: that a Spirit, who can neither err nor deceive, implanted these laws in us
originally. But since false principles often intrude themselves, as indeed the very
system of this man shows in not a few examples, we are involved in difficulties as to
the use of such a principle in the absence of sure criteria to distinguish the genuine
origin from the spurious, as we never can know certainly what the Spirit of truth or
the father of lies may have instilled into us. <SPAN href="#body_ftn21">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn22" class="Standard"><sup>22</sup> The definition of nature is given
in the beginning of the Second Part of the "Transcendental Problem," in § 14. <SPAN href="#body_ftn22">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn23" class="Standard"><sup>23</sup> 1. <span class="T6">Substantia</span>. 2. <span class="T6">Qualitas</span>. 3. <span class="T6">Quantitas</span>. 4. <span class="T6">Relatio</span>, 5. <span class="T6">Actio</span>. 6. <span class="T6">Passio</span>. 7. <span class="T6">Quando</span>, 8. <span class="T6">Ubi</span>. 9. <span class="T6">Situs</span>.
10. <span class="T6">Habitus</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn23">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn24" class="Standard"><sup>24</sup> <span class="T6">Oppositum</span>.
<span class="T6">Prius</span>. <span class="T6">Simul</span>. <span class="T6">Motus</span>. <span class="T6">Habere</span>.
<SPAN href="#body_ftn24">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn25" class="Standard"><sup>25</sup> See the two tables in the chapters
<span class="T6">Von den Paralogismen der reinen Vernuuft</span> and the first division
of the Antinomy of Pure Reason, <span class="T6">System der kosmologischen
Ideen</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn25">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn26" class="Standard"><sup>26</sup> On the table of the categories many
neat observations may be made, for instance: (1) that the third arises from the first
and the second joined in one concept; (2) that in those of Quantity and of Quality
there is merely a progress from unity to totality or from something to nothing (for
this purpose the categories of Quality must stand thus: reality, limitation, total
negation), without <span class="T6">correlata</span> or <span class="T6">opposita</span>, whereas
those of Relation and of Modality have them; (3) that, as
in <span class="T6">Logic</span> categorical judgments are the basis of all others, so
the category of Substance is the basis of all concepts of actual things; (4) that as
Modality in the judgment is not a particular predicate, so by the modal concepts a
determination is not superadded to things, etc., etc. Such observations are of great
use. If we besides enumerate all the predicables, which we can find pretty completely
in any good ontology (for example, Baumgarten's), and arrange them in classes under the
categories, in which operation we must not neglect to add as complete a dissection of
all these concepts as possible, there will then arise a merely analytical part of
metaphysics, which does not contain a single synthetical proposition, which might
precede the second (the synthetical), and would by its precision and completeness be
not only useful, but, in virtue of its system, be even to some extent elegant. <SPAN href="#body_ftn26">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn27" class="Standard"><sup>27</sup> See <span class="T6">Critique of
Pure Reason, Von der Amphibolie der Reflexbegriffe</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn27">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn28" class="Standard"><sup>28</sup> If we can say, that a science is
actual at least in the ideas of all men, as soon as it appears that the problems which
lead to it are proposed to everybody by the nature of human reason, and that therefore
many (though faulty) endeavors are unavoidably made in its behalf, then we are bound to
say that metaphysics is subjectively (and indeed necessarily) actual, and therefore we
justly ask, how is it (objectively) possible. <SPAN href="#body_ftn28">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn29" class="Standard"><sup>29</sup> In disjunctive judgments we
consider all possibility as divided in respect to a particular concept. By the
ontological principle of the universal determination of a thing in general, I
understand the principle that either the one or the other of all possible contradictory
predicates must be assigned to any object. This is at the same time the principle of
all disjunctive judgments, constituting the foundation of our conception of
possibility, and in it the possibility of every object in general is considered as
determined. This may serve as a slight explanation of the above proposition: that the
activity of reason in disjunctive syllogisms is formally the same as that by which it
fashions the idea of a universal conception of all reality, containing in itself that
which is positive in all contradictory predicates. <SPAN href="#body_ftn29">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn30" class="Standard"><sup>30</sup> See <span class="T6">Critique of
Pure Reason, Von den Paralogismen der reinen Vernunft.</span> <SPAN href="#body_ftn30">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn31" class="Standard"><sup>31</sup> Were the representation of the
apperception (the Ego) a concept, by which anything could be thought, it could be used
as a predicate of other things or contain predicates in itself. But it is nothing more
than the feeling of an existence without the least definite conception and is only the
representation of that to which all thinking stands in relation (<span class="T6">relatione accidentis</span>).
<SPAN href="#body_ftn31">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn32" class="Standard"><sup>32</sup> Cf. <span class="T6">Critique, Von den
Analogien der Erfahrung</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn32">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn33" class="Standard"><sup>33</sup> It is indeed very remarkable how
carelessly metaphysicians have always passed over the principle of the permanence of
substances without ever attempting a proof of it; doubtless because they found
themselves abandoned by all proofs as soon as they began to deal with the concept of
substance. Common sense, which felt distinctly that without this presupposition do
union of perceptions in experience is possible, supplied the want by a postulate. From
experience itself it never could derive such a principle, partly because substances
cannot be so traced in all their alterations and dissolutions, that the matter can
always be found undiminished, partly because the principle contains
<span class="T6">necessity</span>, which is always the sign of an <span class="T6">a priori</span>
principle. People then boldly applied this postulate to the concept of soul as a
<span class="T6">substance</span>, and concluded a necessary continuance of the soul
after the death of man (especially as the simplicity of this substance, which is
inferred from the indivisibility of consciousness, secured it from destruction by
dissolution). Had they found the genuine source of this principle—a discovery which
requires deeper researches than they were ever inclined to make—they would have seen,
that the law of the permanence of substances has place for the purposes of experience
only, and hence can hold good of things so far as they are to be cognised and conjoined
with others in experience, but never independently of all possible experience, and
consequently cannot hold good of the soul after death. <SPAN href="#body_ftn33">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn34" class="Standard"><sup>34</sup> Cf. <span class="T6">Critique, Die
Antinomie der reinen Vernunft</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn34">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn35" class="Standard"><sup>35</sup> I therefore would be pleased to
have the critical reader to devote to this antinomy of pure reason his chief attention,
because nature itself seems to have established it with a view to stagger reason in its
daring pretentions, and to force it to self-examination. For every proof, which I have
given, as well of the thesis as of the antithesis, I undertake to be responsible, and
thereby to show the certainty of the inevitable antinomy of reason. When the reader is
brought by this curious phenomenon to fall back upon the proof of the presumption upon
which it rests, he will feel himself obliged to investigate the ultimate foundation of
all the cognition of pure reason with me more thoroughly. <SPAN href="#body_ftn35">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn36" class="Standard"><sup>36</sup> The idea of freedom occurs only in
the relation of the intellectual, as cause, to the appearance, as effect. Hence we
cannot attribute freedom to matter in regard to the incessant action by which it fills
its space, though this action takes place from an internal principle. We can likewise
find no notion of freedom suitable to purely rational beings, for instance, to God, so
far as his action is immanent. For his action, though independent of external
determining causes, is determined in his eternal reason, that is, in the divine
<span class="T6">nature</span>. It is only, if <span class="T6">something is to
start</span> by an action, and so the effect occurs in the sequence of time, or in the
world of sense (e.g., the beginning of the world), that we can put the question,
whether the causality of the cause must in its turn have been started, or whether the
cause can originate an effect without its causality itself beginning. In the former
case the concept of this causality is a concept of natural necessity, in the latter,
that of freedom. From this the reader will see, that, as I explained freedom to be the
faculty of starting an event spontaneously, I have exactly hit the notion which is the
problem of metaphysics. <SPAN href="#body_ftn36">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn37" class="Standard"><sup>37</sup> Cf. <span class="T6">Critique</span>, the chapter on "Transcendental Ideals."
<SPAN href="#body_ftn37">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn38" class="Standard"><sup>38</sup> Herr Platner in his Aphorisms
acutely says (§§ 728, 729), "If reason be a criterion, no concept, which is
incomprehensible to human reason, can be possible. Incomprehensibility has place in
what is actual only. Here in comprehensibility arises from the insufficiency of the
acquired ideas." It sounds paradoxical, but is otherwise not strange to say, that in
nature there is much incomprehensible (e.g., the faculty of generation) but if we mount
still higher, and even go beyond nature, everything again becomes comprehensible; for
we then quit entirely the objects, which can be given us, and occupy ourselves merely
about ideas, in which occupation we can easily comprehend the law that reason
prescribes by them to the understanding for its use in experience, because the law is
the reason's own production. <SPAN href="#body_ftn38">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn39" class="Standard"><sup>39</sup> <span class="T6">Der die
Gegenstände anschaute</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn39">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn40" class="Standard"><sup>40</sup> The use of the word "world" without
article, though odd, seems to be the correct reading, but it may be a mere misprint.—
<span class="T6">Ed</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn40">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn41" class="Standard"><sup>41</sup> There is, e.g., an analogy between
the juridical relation of human actions and the mechanical relation of motive powers. I
never can do anything to another man without giving him a right to do the same to me on
the same conditions; just as no mass can act with its motive power on another mass
without thereby occasioning the other to react equally against it. Here right and
motive power are quite dissimilar things, but in their relation there is complete
similarity. By means of such an analogy I can obtain a notion of the relation of things
which absolutely are unknown to me. For instance, as the promotion of the welfare of
children (= a) is to the love of parents (= b), so the welfare of the human species (=
c) is to that unknown [quantity which is] in God (= x), which we call love; not as if
it had the least similarity to any human inclination, but because we can suppose its
relation to the world to be similar to that which things of the world bear one another.
But the concept of relation in this case is a mere category, viz., the concept of
cause, which has nothing to do with sensibility. <SPAN href="#body_ftn41">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn42" class="Standard"><sup>42</sup> I may say, that the causality of
the Supreme Cause holds the same place with regard to the world that human reason does
with regard to its works of art. Here the nature of the Supreme Cause itself remains
unknown to me: I only compare its effects (the order of the world) which I know, and
their conformity to reason, to the effects of human reason which I also know; and hence
I term the former reason, without attributing to it on that account what I understand
in man by this term, or attaching to it anything else known to me, as its property.
<SPAN href="#body_ftn42">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn43" class="Standard"><sup>43</sup> <span class="T6">Critique of Pure
Reason</span>, II., chap. III., section 7. <SPAN href="#body_ftn43">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn44" class="Standard"><sup>44</sup> Throughout in the <span class="T6">Critique</span>
I never lost sight of the plan not to neglect anything, were it
ever so recondite, that could render the inquiry into the nature of pure reason
complete. Everybody may afterwards carry his researches as far as he pleases, when he
has been merely shown what yet remains to be done. It is this a duty which must
reasonably be expected of him who has made it his business to survey the whole field,
in order to consign it to others for future cultivation and allotment. And to this
branch both the scholia belong, which will hardly recommend themselves by their dryness
to amateurs, and hence are added here for connoisseurs only. <SPAN href="#body_ftn44">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn45" class="Standard"><sup>45</sup> By no means "<span class="T6">higher</span>."
High towers, and metaphysically-great men resembling them, round
both of which there is commonly much wind, are not for me. My place is the fruitful
<span class="T6">bathos</span>, the bottom-land, of experience; and the word
transcendental, the meaning of which is so often explained by me, but not once grasped
by my reviewer (so carelessly has he regarded everything), does not signify something
passing beyond all experience, but something that indeed precedes it <span class="T6">a
priori</span>, but that is intended simply to make cognition of experience possible. If
these conceptions overstep experience, their employment is termed transcendent, a word
which must be distinguished from transcendental, the latter being limited to the
immanent use, that is, to experience. All misunderstandings of this kind have been
sufficiently guarded against in the work itself, but my reviewer found his advantage in
misunderstanding me. <SPAN href="#body_ftn45">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn46" class="Standard"><sup>46</sup> Idealism proper always has a
mystical tendency, and can have no other, but mine is solely designed for the purpose
of comprehending the possibility of our cognition <span class="T6">a priori</span> as
to objects of experience, which is a problem never hitherto solved or even suggested.
In this way all mystical idealism falls to the ground, for (as may be seen already in
Plato) it inferred from our cognitions <span class="T6">a priori</span> (even from
those of geometry) another intuition different from that of the senses (namely, an
intellectual intuition), because it never occurred to any one that the senses
themselves might intuite <span class="T6">a priori</span>. <SPAN href="#body_ftn46">↩</SPAN></p>
<p id="ftn47" class="Standard"><sup>47</sup> The reviewer often fights with his
own shadow. When I oppose the truth of experience to dream, he never thinks that I am
here speaking simply of the well-known <span class="T6">somnio objective sumto</span>
of the Wolffian philosophy, which is merely formal, and with which the distinction
between sleeping and waking is in no way concerned, and in a transcendental philosophy
indeed can have no place. For the rest, he calls my deduction of the categories and
table of the principles of the understanding, "common well-known axioms of logic and
ontology, expressed in an idealistic manner." The reader need only consult these
<span class="T6">Prolegomena</span> upon this point, to convince himself that a more
miserable and historically incorrect, judgment, could hardly be made.
<SPAN href="#body_ftn47">↩</SPAN></p>
<SPAN name="endofbook"></SPAN>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />