<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0005" id="link2HCH0005"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER V. KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE AND KNOWLEDGE BY DESCRIPTION </h2>
<p>In the preceding chapter we saw that there are two sorts of knowledge:
knowledge of things, and knowledge of truths. In this chapter we shall be
concerned exclusively with knowledge of things, of which in turn we shall
have to distinguish two kinds. Knowledge of things, when it is of the kind
we call knowledge by <i>acquaintance</i>, is essentially simpler than any
knowledge of truths, and logically independent of knowledge of truths,
though it would be rash to assume that human beings ever, in fact, have
acquaintance with things without at the same time knowing some truth about
them. Knowledge of things by <i>description</i>, on the contrary, always
involves, as we shall find in the course of the present chapter, some
knowledge of truths as its source and ground. But first of all we must
make clear what we mean by 'acquaintance' and what we mean by
'description'.</p>
<p>We shall say that we have <i>acquaintance</i> with anything of which we
are directly aware, without the intermediary of any process of inference
or any knowledge of truths. Thus in the presence of my table I am
acquainted with the sense-data that make up the appearance of my table—its
colour, shape, hardness, smoothness, etc.; all these are things of which I
am immediately conscious when I am seeing and touching my table. The
particular shade of colour that I am seeing may have many things said
about it—I may say that it is brown, that it is rather dark, and so
on. But such statements, though they make me know truths about the colour,
do not make me know the colour itself any better than I did before so far
as concerns knowledge of the colour itself, as opposed to knowledge of
truths about it, I know the colour perfectly and completely when I see it,
and no further knowledge of it itself is even theoretically possible. Thus
the sense-data which make up the appearance of my table are things with
which I have acquaintance, things immediately known to me just as they
are.</p>
<p>My knowledge of the table as a physical object, on the contrary, is not
direct knowledge. Such as it is, it is obtained through acquaintance with
the sense-data that make up the appearance of the table. We have seen that
it is possible, without absurdity, to doubt whether there is a table at
all, whereas it is not possible to doubt the sense-data. My knowledge of
the table is of the kind which we shall call 'knowledge by description'.
The table is 'the physical object which causes such-and-such sense-data'.
This describes the table by means of the sense-data. In order to know
anything at all about the table, we must know truths connecting it with
things with which we have acquaintance: we must know that 'such-and-such
sense-data are caused by a physical object'. There is no state of mind in
which we are directly aware of the table; all our knowledge of the table
is really knowledge of truths, and the actual thing which is the table is
not, strictly speaking, known to us at all. We know a description, and we
know that there is just one object to which this description applies,
though the object itself is not directly known to us. In such a case, we
say that our knowledge of the object is knowledge by description.</p>
<p>All our knowledge, both knowledge of things and knowledge of truths, rests
upon acquaintance as its foundation. It is therefore important to consider
what kinds of things there are with which we have acquaintance.</p>
<p>Sense-data, as we have already seen, are among the things with which we
are acquainted; in fact, they supply the most obvious and striking example
of knowledge by acquaintance. But if they were the sole example, our
knowledge would be very much more restricted than it is. We should only
know what is now present to our senses: we could not know anything about
the past—not even that there was a past—nor could we know any
truths about our sense-data, for all knowledge of truths, as we shall
show, demands acquaintance with things which are of an essentially
different character from sense-data, the things which are sometimes called
'abstract ideas', but which we shall call 'universals'. We have therefore
to consider acquaintance with other things besides sense-data if we are to
obtain any tolerably adequate analysis of our knowledge.</p>
<p>The first extension beyond sense-data to be considered is acquaintance by
<i>memory</i>. It is obvious that we often remember what we have seen or
heard or had otherwise present to our senses, and that in such cases we
are still immediately aware of what we remember, in spite of the fact that
it appears as past and not as present. This immediate knowledge by memory
is the source of all our knowledge concerning the past: without it, there
could be no knowledge of the past by inference, since we should never know
that there was anything past to be inferred.</p>
<p>The next extension to be considered is acquaintance by <i>introspection</i>.
We are not only aware of things, but we are often aware of being aware of
them. When I see the sun, I am often aware of my seeing the sun; thus 'my
seeing the sun' is an object with which I have acquaintance. When I desire
food, I may be aware of my desire for food; thus 'my desiring food' is an
object with which I am acquainted. Similarly we may be aware of our
feeling pleasure or pain, and generally of the events which happen in our
minds. This kind of acquaintance, which may be called self-consciousness,
is the source of all our knowledge of mental things. It is obvious that it
is only what goes on in our own minds that can be thus known immediately.
What goes on in the minds of others is known to us through our perception
of their bodies, that is, through the sense-data in us which are
associated with their bodies. But for our acquaintance with the contents
of our own minds, we should be unable to imagine the minds of others, and
therefore we could never arrive at the knowledge that they have minds. It
seems natural to suppose that self-consciousness is one of the things that
distinguish men from animals: animals, we may suppose, though they have
acquaintance with sense-data, never become aware of this acquaintance. I
do not mean that they <i>doubt</i> whether they exist, but that they have
never become conscious of the fact that they have sensations and feelings,
nor therefore of the fact that they, the subjects of their sensations and
feelings, exist.</p>
<p>We have spoken of acquaintance with the contents of our minds as <i>self</i>-consciousness,
but it is not, of course, consciousness of our <i>self</i>: it is
consciousness of particular thoughts and feelings. The question whether we
are also acquainted with our bare selves, as opposed to particular
thoughts and feelings, is a very difficult one, upon which it would be
rash to speak positively. When we try to look into ourselves we always
seem to come upon some particular thought or feeling, and not upon the 'I'
which has the thought or feeling. Nevertheless there are some reasons for
thinking that we are acquainted with the 'I', though the acquaintance is
hard to disentangle from other things. To make clear what sort of reason
there is, let us consider for a moment what our acquaintance with
particular thoughts really involves.</p>
<p>When I am acquainted with 'my seeing the sun', it seems plain that I am
acquainted with two different things in relation to each other. On the one
hand there is the sense-datum which represents the sun to me, on the other
hand there is that which sees this sense-datum. All acquaintance, such as
my acquaintance with the sense-datum which represents the sun, seems
obviously a relation between the person acquainted and the object with
which the person is acquainted. When a case of acquaintance is one with
which I can be acquainted (as I am acquainted with my acquaintance with
the sense-datum representing the sun), it is plain that the person
acquainted is myself. Thus, when I am acquainted with my seeing the sun,
the whole fact with which I am acquainted is
'Self-acquainted-with-sense-datum'.</p>
<p>Further, we know the truth 'I am acquainted with this sense-datum'. It is
hard to see how we could know this truth, or even understand what is meant
by it, unless we were acquainted with something which we call 'I'. It does
not seem necessary to suppose that we are acquainted with a more or less
permanent person, the same to-day as yesterday, but it does seem as though
we must be acquainted with that thing, whatever its nature, which sees the
sun and has acquaintance with sense-data. Thus, in some sense it would
seem we must be acquainted with our Selves as opposed to our particular
experiences. But the question is difficult, and complicated arguments can
be adduced on either side. Hence, although acquaintance with ourselves
seems <i>probably</i> to occur, it is not wise to assert that it
undoubtedly does occur.</p>
<p>We may therefore sum up as follows what has been said concerning
acquaintance with things that exist. We have acquaintance in sensation
with the data of the outer senses, and in introspection with the data of
what may be called the inner sense—thoughts, feelings, desires,
etc.; we have acquaintance in memory with things which have been data
either of the outer senses or of the inner sense. Further, it is probable,
though not certain, that we have acquaintance with Self, as that which is
aware of things or has desires towards things.</p>
<p>In addition to our acquaintance with particular existing things, we also
have acquaintance with what we shall call <i>universals</i>, that is to
say, general ideas, such as <i>whiteness</i>, <i>diversity</i>, <i>brotherhood</i>,
and so on. Every complete sentence must contain at least one word which
stands for a universal, since all verbs have a meaning which is universal.
We shall return to universals later on, in Chapter IX; for the present, it
is only necessary to guard against the supposition that whatever we can be
acquainted with must be something particular and existent. Awareness of
universals is called <i>conceiving</i>, and a universal of which we are
aware is called a <i>concept</i>.</p>
<p>It will be seen that among the objects with which we are acquainted are
not included physical objects (as opposed to sense-data), nor other
people's minds. These things are known to us by what I call 'knowledge by
description', which we must now consider.</p>
<p>By a 'description' I mean any phrase of the form 'a so-and-so' or 'the
so-and-so'. A phrase of the form 'a so-and-so' I shall call an 'ambiguous'
description; a phrase of the form 'the so-and-so' (in the singular) I
shall call a 'definite' description. Thus 'a man' is an ambiguous
description, and 'the man with the iron mask' is a definite description.
There are various problems connected with ambiguous descriptions, but I
pass them by, since they do not directly concern the matter we are
discussing, which is the nature of our knowledge concerning objects in
cases where we know that there is an object answering to a definite
description, though we are not acquainted with any such object. This is a
matter which is concerned exclusively with definite descriptions. I shall
therefore, in the sequel, speak simply of 'descriptions' when I mean
'definite descriptions'. Thus a description will mean any phrase of the
form 'the so-and-so' in the singular.</p>
<p>We shall say that an object is 'known by description' when we know that it
is 'the so-and-so', i.e. when we know that there is one object, and no
more, having a certain property; and it will generally be implied that we
do not have knowledge of the same object by acquaintance. We know that the
man with the iron mask existed, and many propositions are known about him;
but we do not know who he was. We know that the candidate who gets the
most votes will be elected, and in this case we are very likely also
acquainted (in the only sense in which one can be acquainted with some one
else) with the man who is, in fact, the candidate who will get most votes;
but we do not know which of the candidates he is, i.e. we do not know any
proposition of the form 'A is the candidate who will get most votes' where
A is one of the candidates by name. We shall say that we have 'merely
descriptive knowledge' of the so-and-so when, although we know that the
so-and-so exists, and although we may possibly be acquainted with the
object which is, in fact, the so-and-so, yet we do not know any
proposition '<i>a</i> is the so-and-so', where <i>a</i> is something with
which we are acquainted.</p>
<p>When we say 'the so-and-so exists', we mean that there is just one object
which is the so-and-so. The proposition '<i>a</i> is the so-and-so' means
that <i>a</i> has the property so-and-so, and nothing else has. 'Mr. A. is
the Unionist candidate for this constituency' means 'Mr. A. is a Unionist
candidate for this constituency, and no one else is'. 'The Unionist
candidate for this constituency exists' means 'some one is a Unionist
candidate for this constituency, and no one else is'. Thus, when we are
acquainted with an object which is the so-and-so, we know that the
so-and-so exists; but we may know that the so-and-so exists when we are
not acquainted with any object which we know to be the so-and-so, and even
when we are not acquainted with any object which, in fact, is the
so-and-so.</p>
<p>Common words, even proper names, are usually really descriptions. That is
to say, the thought in the mind of a person using a proper name correctly
can generally only be expressed explicitly if we replace the proper name
by a description. Moreover, the description required to express the
thought will vary for different people, or for the same person at
different times. The only thing constant (so long as the name is rightly
used) is the object to which the name applies. But so long as this remains
constant, the particular description involved usually makes no difference
to the truth or falsehood of the proposition in which the name appears.</p>
<p>Let us take some illustrations. Suppose some statement made about
Bismarck. Assuming that there is such a thing as direct acquaintance with
oneself, Bismarck himself might have used his name directly to designate
the particular person with whom he was acquainted. In this case, if he
made a judgement about himself, he himself might be a constituent of the
judgement. Here the proper name has the direct use which it always wishes
to have, as simply standing for a certain object, and not for a
description of the object. But if a person who knew Bismarck made a
judgement about him, the case is different. What this person was
acquainted with were certain sense-data which he connected (rightly, we
will suppose) with Bismarck's body. His body, as a physical object, and
still more his mind, were only known as the body and the mind connected
with these sense-data. That is, they were known by description. It is, of
course, very much a matter af chance which characteristics of a man's
appearance will come into a friend's mind when he thinks of him; thus the
description actually in the friend's mind is accidental. The essential
point is that he knows that the various descriptions all apply to the same
entity, in spite of not being acquainted with the entity in question.</p>
<p>When we, who did not know Bismarck, make a judgement about him, the
description in our minds will probably be some more or less vague mass of
historical knowledge—far more, in most cases, than is required to
identify him. But, for the sake of illustration, let us assume that we
think of him as 'the first Chancellor of the German Empire'. Here all the
words are abstract except 'German'. The word 'German' will, again, have
different meanings for different people. To some it will recall travels in
Germany, to some the look of Germany on the map, and so on. But if we are
to obtain a description which we know to be applicable, we shall be
compelled, at some point, to bring in a reference to a particular with
which we are acquainted. Such reference is involved in any mention of
past, present, and future (as opposed to definite dates), or of here and
there, or of what others have told us. Thus it would seem that, in some
way or other, a description known to be applicable to a particular must
involve some reference to a particular with which we are acquainted, if
our knowledge about the thing described is not to be merely what follows
<i>logically</i> from the description. For example, 'the most long-lived
of men' is a description involving only universals, which must apply to
some man, but we can make no judgements concerning this man which involve
knowledge about him beyond what the description gives. If, however, we
say, 'The first Chancellor of the German Empire was an astute
diplomatist', we can only be assured of the truth of our judgement in
virtue of something with which we are acquainted—usually a testimony
heard or read. Apart from the information we convey to others, apart from
the fact about the actual Bismarck, which gives importance to our
judgement, the thought we really have contains the one or more particulars
involved, and otherwise consists wholly of concepts.</p>
<p>All names of places—London, England, Europe, the Earth, the Solar
System—similarly involve, when used, descriptions which start from
some one or more particulars with which we are acquainted. I suspect that
even the Universe, as considered by metaphysics, involves such a connexion
with particulars. In logic, on the contrary, where we are concerned not
merely with what does exist, but with whatever might or could exist or be,
no reference to actual particulars is involved.</p>
<p>It would seem that, when we make a statement about something only known by
description, we often <i>intend</i> to make our statement, not in the form
involving the description, but about the actual thing described. That is
to say, when we say anything about Bismarck, we should like, if we could,
to make the judgement which Bismarck alone can make, namely, the judgement
of which he himself is a constituent. In this we are necessarily defeated,
since the actual Bismarck is unknown to us. But we know that there is an
object B, called Bismarck, and that B was an astute diplomatist. We can
thus <i>describe</i> the proposition we should like to affirm, namely, 'B
was an astute diplomatist', where B is the object which was Bismarck. If
we are describing Bismarck as 'the first Chancellor of the German Empire',
the proposition we should like to affirm may be described as 'the
proposition asserting, concerning the actual object which was the first
Chancellor of the German Empire, that this object was an astute
diplomatist'. What enables us to communicate in spite of the varying
descriptions we employ is that we know there is a true proposition
concerning the actual Bismarck, and that however we may vary the
description (so long as the description is correct) the proposition
described is still the same. This proposition, which is described and is
known to be true, is what interests us; but we are not acquainted with the
proposition itself, and do not know it, though we know it is true.</p>
<p>It will be seen that there are various stages in the removal from
acquaintance with particulars: there is Bismarck to people who knew him;
Bismarck to those who only know of him through history; the man with the
iron mask; the longest-lived of men. These are progressively further
removed from acquaintance with particulars; the first comes as near to
acquaintance as is possible in regard to another person; in the second, we
shall still be said to know 'who Bismarck was'; in the third, we do not
know who was the man with the iron mask, though we can know many
propositions about him which are not logically deducible from the fact
that he wore an iron mask; in the fourth, finally, we know nothing beyond
what is logically deducible from the definition of the man. There is a
similar hierarchy in the region of universals. Many universals, like many
particulars, are only known to us by description. But here, as in the case
of particulars, knowledge concerning what is known by description is
ultimately reducible to knowledge concerning what is known by
acquaintance.</p>
<p>The fundamental principle in the analysis of propositions containing
descriptions is this: <i>Every proposition which we can understand must be
composed wholly of constituents with which we are acquainted</i>.</p>
<p>We shall not at this stage attempt to answer all the objections which may
be urged against this fundamental principle. For the present, we shall
merely point out that, in some way or other, it must be possible to meet
these objections, for it is scarcely conceivable that we can make a
judgement or entertain a supposition without knowing what it is that we
are judging or supposing about. We must attach <i>some</i> meaning to the
words we use, if we are to speak significantly and not utter mere noise;
and the meaning we attach to our words must be something with which we are
acquainted. Thus when, for example, we make a statement about Julius
Caesar, it is plain that Julius Caesar himself is not before our minds,
since we are not acquainted with him. We have in mind some description of
Julius Caesar: 'the man who was assassinated on the Ides of March', 'the
founder of the Roman Empire', or, perhaps, merely 'the man whose name was
<i>Julius Caesar</i>'. (In this last description, <i>Julius Caesar</i> is
a noise or shape with which we are acquainted.) Thus our statement does
not mean quite what it seems to mean, but means something involving,
instead of Julius Caesar, some description of him which is composed wholly
of particulars and universals with which we are acquainted.</p>
<p>The chief importance of knowledge by description is that it enables us to
pass beyond the limits of our private experience. In spite of the fact
that we can only know truths which are wholly composed of terms which we
have experienced in acquaintance, we can yet have knowledge by description
of things which we have never experienced. In view of the very narrow
range of our immediate experience, this result is vital, and until it is
understood, much of our knowledge must remain mysterious and therefore
doubtful.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />