<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0007" id="link2HCH0007"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER VII. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL PRINCIPLES </h2>
<p>We saw in the preceding chapter that the principle of induction, while
necessary to the validity of all arguments based on experience, is itself
not capable of being proved by experience, and yet is unhesitatingly
believed by every one, at least in all its concrete applications. In these
characteristics the principle of induction does not stand alone. There are
a number of other principles which cannot be proved or disproved by
experience, but are used in arguments which start from what is
experienced.</p>
<p>Some of these principles have even greater evidence than the principle of
induction, and the knowledge of them has the same degree of certainty as
the knowledge of the existence of sense-data. They constitute the means of
drawing inferences from what is given in sensation; and if what we infer
is to be true, it is just as necessary that our principles of inference
should be true as it is that our data should be true. The principles of
inference are apt to be overlooked because of their very obviousness—the
assumption involved is assented to without our realizing that it is an
assumption. But it is very important to realize the use of principles of
inference, if a correct theory of knowledge is to be obtained; for our
knowledge of them raises interesting and difficult questions.</p>
<p>In all our knowledge of general principles, what actually happens is that
first of all we realize some particular application of the principle, and
then we realize that the particularity is irrelevant, and that there is a
generality which may equally truly be affirmed. This is of course familiar
in such matters as teaching arithmetic: 'two and two are four' is first
learnt in the case of some particular pair of couples, and then in some
other particular case, and so on, until at last it becomes possible to see
that it is true of any pair of couples. The same thing happens with
logical principles. Suppose two men are discussing what day of the month
it is. One of them says, 'At least you will admit that <i>if</i> yesterday
was the 15th to-day must be the 16th.' 'Yes', says the other, 'I admit
that.' 'And you know', the first continues, 'that yesterday was the 15th,
because you dined with Jones, and your diary will tell you that was on the
15th.' 'Yes', says the second; 'therefore to-day <i>is</i> the 16th.'</p>
<p>Now such an argument is not hard to follow; and if it is granted that its
premisses are true in fact, no one will deny that the conclusion must also
be true. But it depends for its truth upon an instance of a general
logical principle. The logical principle is as follows: 'Suppose it known
that <i>if</i> this is true, then that is true. Suppose it also known that
this <i>is</i> true, then it follows that that is true.' When it is the
case that if this is true, that is true, we shall say that this 'implies'
that, and that that 'follows from' this. Thus our principle states that if
this implies that, and this is true, then that is true. In other words,
'anything implied by a true proposition is true', or 'whatever follows
from a true proposition is true'.</p>
<p>This principle is really involved—at least, concrete instances of it
are involved—in all demonstrations. Whenever one thing which we
believe is used to prove something else, which we consequently believe,
this principle is relevant. If any one asks: 'Why should I accept the
results of valid arguments based on true premisses?' we can only answer by
appealing to our principle. In fact, the truth of the principle is
impossible to doubt, and its obviousness is so great that at first sight
it seems almost trivial. Such principles, however, are not trivial to the
philosopher, for they show that we may have indubitable knowledge which is
in no way derived from objects of sense.</p>
<p>The above principle is merely one of a certain number of self-evident
logical principles. Some at least of these principles must be granted
before any argument or proof becomes possible. When some of them have been
granted, others can be proved, though these others, so long as they are
simple, are just as obvious as the principles taken for granted. For no
very good reason, three of these principles have been singled out by
tradition under the name of 'Laws of Thought'.</p>
<p>They are as follows:</p>
<p>(1) <i>The law of identity</i>: 'Whatever is, is.'</p>
<p>(2) <i>The law of contradiction</i>: 'Nothing can both be and not be.'</p>
<p>(3) <i>The law of excluded middle</i>: 'Everything must either be or not
be.'</p>
<p>These three laws are samples of self-evident logical principles, but are
not really more fundamental or more self-evident than various other
similar principles: for instance, the one we considered just now, which
states that what follows from a true premiss is true. The name 'laws of
thought' is also misleading, for what is important is not the fact that we
think in accordance with these laws, but the fact that things behave in
accordance with them; in other words, the fact that when we think in
accordance with them we think <i>truly</i>. But this is a large question,
to which we must return at a later stage.</p>
<p>In addition to the logical principles which enable us to prove from a
given premiss that something is <i>certainly</i> true, there are other
logical principles which enable us to prove, from a given premiss, that
there is a greater or less probability that something is true. An example
of such principles—perhaps the most important example is the
inductive principle, which we considered in the preceding chapter.</p>
<p>One of the great historic controversies in philosophy is the controversy
between the two schools called respectively 'empiricists' and
'rationalists'. The empiricists—who are best represented by the
British philosophers, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume—maintained that all
our knowledge is derived from experience; the rationalists—who are
represented by the Continental philosophers of the seventeenth century,
especially Descartes and Leibniz—maintained that, in addition to
what we know by experience, there are certain 'innate ideas' and 'innate
principles', which we know independently of experience. It has now become
possible to decide with some confidence as to the truth or falsehood of
these opposing schools. It must be admitted, for the reasons already
stated, that logical principles are known to us, and cannot be themselves
proved by experience, since all proof presupposes them. In this,
therefore, which was the most important point of the controversy, the
rationalists were in the right.</p>
<p>On the other hand, even that part of our knowledge which is <i>logically</i>
independent of experience (in the sense that experience cannot prove it)
is yet elicited and caused by experience. It is on occasion of particular
experiences that we become aware of the general laws which their
connexions exemplify. It would certainly be absurd to suppose that there
are innate principles in the sense that babies are born with a knowledge
of everything which men know and which cannot be deduced from what is
experienced. For this reason, the word 'innate' would not now be employed
to describe our knowledge of logical principles. The phrase '<i>a priori</i>'
is less objectionable, and is more usual in modern writers. Thus, while
admitting that all knowledge is elicited and caused by experience, we
shall nevertheless hold that some knowledge is <i>a priori</i>, in the
sense that the experience which makes us think of it does not suffice to
prove it, but merely so directs our attention that we see its truth
without requiring any proof from experience.</p>
<p>There is another point of great importance, in which the empiricists were
in the right as against the rationalists. Nothing can be known to <i>exist</i>
except by the help of experience. That is to say, if we wish to prove that
something of which we have no direct experience exists, we must have among
our premisses the existence of one or more things of which we have direct
experience. Our belief that the Emperor of China exists, for example,
rests upon testimony, and testimony consists, in the last analysis, of
sense-data seen or heard in reading or being spoken to. Rationalists
believed that, from general consideration as to what must be, they could
deduce the existence of this or that in the actual world. In this belief
they seem to have been mistaken. All the knowledge that we can acquire <i>a
priori</i> concerning existence seems to be hypothetical: it tells us that
if one thing exists, another must exist, or, more generally, that if one
proposition is true, another must be true. This is exemplified by the
principles we have already dealt with, such as '<i>if</i> this is true,
and this implies that, then that is true', or '<i>if</i> this and that
have been repeatedly found connected, they will probably be connected in
the next instance in which one of them is found'. Thus the scope and power
of <i>a priori</i> principles is strictly limited. All knowledge that
something exists must be in part dependent on experience. When anything is
known immediately, its existence is known by experience alone; when
anything is proved to exist, without being known immediately, both
experience and <i>a priori</i> principles must be required in the proof.
Knowledge is called <i>empirical</i> when it rests wholly or partly upon
experience. Thus all knowledge which asserts existence is empirical, and
the only <i>a priori</i> knowledge concerning existence is hypothetical,
giving connexions among things that exist or may exist, but not giving
actual existence.</p>
<p><i>A priori</i> knowledge is not all of the logical kind we have been
hitherto considering. Perhaps the most important example of non-logical <i>a
priori</i> knowledge is knowledge as to ethical value. I am not speaking
of judgements as to what is useful or as to what is virtuous, for such
judgements do require empirical premisses; I am speaking of judgements as
to the intrinsic desirability of things. If something is useful, it must
be useful because it secures some end; the end must, if we have gone far
enough, be valuable on its own account, and not merely because it is
useful for some further end. Thus all judgements as to what is useful
depend upon judgements as to what has value on its own account.</p>
<p>We judge, for example, that happiness is more desirable than misery,
knowledge than ignorance, goodwill than hatred, and so on. Such judgements
must, in part at least, be immediate and <i>a priori</i>. Like our
previous <i>a priori</i> judgements, they may be elicited by experience,
and indeed they must be; for it seems not possible to judge whether
anything is intrinsically valuable unless we have experienced something of
the same kind. But it is fairly obvious that they cannot be proved by
experience; for the fact that a thing exists or does not exist cannot
prove either that it is good that it should exist or that it is bad. The
pursuit of this subject belongs to ethics, where the impossibility of
deducing what ought to be from what is has to be established. In the
present connexion, it is only important to realize that knowledge as to
what is intrinsically of value is <i>a priori</i> in the same sense in
which logic is <i>a priori</i>, namely in the sense that the truth of such
knowledge can be neither proved nor disproved by experience.</p>
<p>All pure mathematics is <i>a priori</i>, like logic. This was strenuously
denied by the empirical philosophers, who maintained that experience was
as much the source of our knowledge of arithmetic as of our knowledge of
geography. They maintained that by the repeated experience of seeing two
things and two other things, and finding that altogether they made four
things, we were led by induction to the conclusion that two things and two
other things would <i>always</i> make four things altogether. If, however,
this were the source of our knowledge that two and two are four, we should
proceed differently, in persuading ourselves of its truth, from the way in
which we do actually proceed. In fact, a certain number of instances are
needed to make us think of two abstractly, rather than of two coins or two
books or two people, or two of any other specified kind. But as soon as we
are able to divest our thoughts of irrelevant particularity, we become
able to see the general principle that two and two are four; any one
instance is seen to be <i>typical</i>, and the examination of other
instances becomes unnecessary.(1)</p>
<p>(1) Cf. A. N. Whitehead, <i>Introduction to Mathematics</i> (Home
University Library).</p>
<p>The same thing is exemplified in geometry. If we want to prove some
property of <i>all</i> triangles, we draw some one triangle and reason
about it; but we can avoid making use of any property which it does not
share with all other triangles, and thus, from our particular case, we
obtain a general result. We do not, in fact, feel our certainty that two
and two are four increased by fresh instances, because, as soon as we have
seen the truth of this proposition, our certainty becomes so great as to
be incapable of growing greater. Moreover, we feel some quality of
necessity about the proposition 'two and two are four', which is absent
from even the best attested empirical generalizations. Such
generalizations always remain mere facts: we feel that there might be a
world in which they were false, though in the actual world they happen to
be true. In any possible world, on the contrary, we feel that two and two
would be four: this is not a mere fact, but a necessity to which
everything actual and possible must conform.</p>
<p>The case may be made clearer by considering a genuinely-empirical
generalization, such as 'All men are mortal.' It is plain that we believe
this proposition, in the first place, because there is no known instance
of men living beyond a certain age, and in the second place because there
seem to be physiological grounds for thinking that an organism such as a
man's body must sooner or later wear out. Neglecting the second ground,
and considering merely our experience of men's mortality, it is plain that
we should not be content with one quite clearly understood instance of a
man dying, whereas, in the case of 'two and two are four', one instance
does suffice, when carefully considered, to persuade us that the same must
happen in any other instance. Also we can be forced to admit, on
reflection, that there may be some doubt, however slight, as to whether <i>all</i>
men are mortal. This may be made plain by the attempt to imagine two
different worlds, in one of which there are men who are not mortal, while
in the other two and two make five. When Swift invites us to consider the
race of Struldbugs who never die, we are able to acquiesce in imagination.
But a world where two and two make five seems quite on a different level.
We feel that such a world, if there were one, would upset the whole fabric
of our knowledge and reduce us to utter doubt.</p>
<p>The fact is that, in simple mathematical judgements such as 'two and two
are four', and also in many judgements of logic, we can know the general
proposition without inferring it from instances, although some instance is
usually necessary to make clear to us what the general proposition means.
This is why there is real utility in the process of <i>deduction</i>,
which goes from the general to the general, or from the general to the
particular, as well as in the process of <i>induction</i>, which goes from
the particular to the particular, or from the particular to the general.
It is an old debate among philosophers whether deduction ever gives <i>new</i>
knowledge. We can now see that in certain cases, at least, it does do so.
If we already know that two and two always make four, and we know that
Brown and Jones are two, and so are Robinson and Smith, we can deduce that
Brown and Jones and Robinson and Smith are four. This is new knowledge,
not contained in our premisses, because the general proposition, 'two and
two are four', never told us there were such people as Brown and Jones and
Robinson and Smith, and the particular premisses do not tell us that there
were four of them, whereas the particular proposition deduced does tell us
both these things.</p>
<p>But the newness of the knowledge is much less certain if we take the stock
instance of deduction that is always given in books on logic, namely, 'All
men are mortal; Socrates is a man, therefore Socrates is mortal.' In this
case, what we really know beyond reasonable doubt is that certain men, A,
B, C, were mortal, since, in fact, they have died. If Socrates is one of
these men, it is foolish to go the roundabout way through 'all men are
mortal' to arrive at the conclusion that <i>probably</i> Socrates is
mortal. If Socrates is not one of the men on whom our induction is based,
we shall still do better to argue straight from our A, B, C, to Socrates,
than to go round by the general proposition, 'all men are mortal'. For the
probability that Socrates is mortal is greater, on our data, than the
probability that all men are mortal. (This is obvious, because if all men
are mortal, so is Socrates; but if Socrates is mortal, it does not follow
that all men are mortal.) Hence we shall reach the conclusion that
Socrates is mortal with a greater approach to certainty if we make our
argument purely inductive than if we go by way of 'all men are mortal' and
then use deduction.</p>
<p>This illustrates the difference between general propositions known <i>a
priori</i> such as 'two and two are four', and empirical generalizations
such as 'all men are mortal'. In regard to the former, deduction is the
right mode of argument, whereas in regard to the latter, induction is
always theoretically preferable, and warrants a greater confidence in the
truth of our conclusion, because all empirical generalizations are more
uncertain than the instances of them.</p>
<p>We have now seen that there are propositions known <i>a priori</i>, and
that among them are the propositions of logic and pure mathematics, as
well as the fundamental propositions of ethics. The question which must
next occupy us is this: How is it possible that there should be such
knowledge? And more particularly, how can there be knowledge of general
propositions in cases where we have not examined all the instances, and
indeed never can examine them all, because their number is infinite? These
questions, which were first brought prominently forward by the German
philosopher Kant (1724-1804), are very difficult, and historically very
important.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />