<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0010" id="link2HCH0010"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER X. ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS </h2>
<p>In regard to one man's knowledge at a given time, universals, like
particulars, may be divided into those known by acquaintance, those known
only by description, and those not known either by acquaintance or by
description.</p>
<p>Let us consider first the knowledge of universals by acquaintance. It is
obvious, to begin with, that we are acquainted with such universals as
white, red, black, sweet, sour, loud, hard, etc., i.e. with qualities
which are exemplified in sense-data. When we see a white patch, we are
acquainted, in the first instance, with the particular patch; but by
seeing many white patches, we easily learn to abstract the whiteness which
they all have in common, and in learning to do this we are learning to be
acquainted with whiteness. A similar process will make us acquainted with
any other universal of the same sort. Universals of this sort may be
called 'sensible qualities'. They can be apprehended with less effort of
abstraction than any others, and they seem less removed from particulars
than other universals are.</p>
<p>We come next to relations. The easiest relations to apprehend are those
which hold between the different parts of a single complex sense-datum.
For example, I can see at a glance the whole of the page on which I am
writing; thus the whole page is included in one sense-datum. But I
perceive that some parts of the page are to the left of other parts, and
some parts are above other parts. The process of abstraction in this case
seems to proceed somewhat as follows: I see successively a number of
sense-data in which one part is to the left of another; I perceive, as in
the case of different white patches, that all these sense-data have
something in common, and by abstraction I find that what they have in
common is a certain relation between their parts, namely the relation
which I call 'being to the left of'. In this way I become acquainted with
the universal relation.</p>
<p>In like manner I become aware of the relation of before and after in time.
Suppose I hear a chime of bells: when the last bell of the chime sounds, I
can retain the whole chime before my mind, and I can perceive that the
earlier bells came before the later ones. Also in memory I perceive that
what I am remembering came before the present time. From either of these
sources I can abstract the universal relation of before and after, just as
I abstracted the universal relation 'being to the left of'. Thus
time-relations, like space-relations, are among those with which we are
acquainted.</p>
<p>Another relation with which we become acquainted in much the same way is
resemblance. If I see simultaneously two shades of green, I can see that
they resemble each other; if I also see a shade of red: at the same time,
I can see that the two greens have more resemblance to each other than
either has to the red. In this way I become acquainted with the universal
<i>resemblance</i> or <i>similarity</i>.</p>
<p>Between universals, as between particulars, there are relations of which
we may be immediately aware. We have just seen that we can perceive that
the resemblance between two shades of green is greater than the
resemblance between a shade of red and a shade of green. Here we are
dealing with a relation, namely 'greater than', between two relations. Our
knowledge of such relations, though it requires more power of abstraction
than is required for perceiving the qualities of sense-data, appears to be
equally immediate, and (at least in some cases) equally indubitable. Thus
there is immediate knowledge concerning universals as well as concerning
sense-data.</p>
<p>Returning now to the problem of <i>a priori</i> knowledge, which we left
unsolved when we began the consideration of universals, we find ourselves
in a position to deal with it in a much more satisfactory manner than was
possible before. Let us revert to the proposition 'two and two are four'.
It is fairly obvious, in view of what has been said, that this proposition
states a relation between the universal 'two' and the universal 'four'.
This suggests a proposition which we shall now endeavour to establish:
namely, <i>All </i>a priori<i> knowledge deals exclusively with the
relations of universals</i>. This proposition is of great importance, and
goes a long way towards solving our previous difficulties concerning <i>a
priori</i> knowledge.</p>
<p>The only case in which it might seem, at first sight, as if our
proposition were untrue, is the case in which an <i>a priori</i>
proposition states that <i>all</i> of one class of particulars belong to
some other class, or (what comes to the same thing) that <i>all</i>
particulars having some one property also have some other. In this case it
might seem as though we were dealing with the particulars that have the
property rather than with the property. The proposition 'two and two are
four' is really a case in point, for this may be stated in the form 'any
two and any other two are four', or 'any collection formed of two twos is
a collection of four'. If we can show that such statements as this really
deal only with universals, our proposition may be regarded as proved.</p>
<p>One way of discovering what a proposition deals with is to ask ourselves
what words we must understand—in other words, what objects we must
be acquainted with—in order to see what the proposition means. As
soon as we see what the proposition means, even if we do not yet know
whether it is true or false, it is evident that we must have acquaintance
with whatever is really dealt with by the proposition. By applying this
test, it appears that many propositions which might seem to be concerned
with particulars are really concerned only with universals. In the special
case of 'two and two are four', even when we interpret it as meaning 'any
collection formed of two twos is a collection of four', it is plain that
we can understand the proposition, i.e. we can see what it is that it
asserts, as soon as we know what is meant by 'collection' and 'two' and
'four'. It is quite unnecessary to know all the couples in the world: if
it were necessary, obviously we could never understand the proposition,
since the couples are infinitely numerous and therefore cannot all be
known to us. Thus although our general statement <i>implies</i> statements
about particular couples, <i>as soon as we know that there are such
particular couples</i>, yet it does not itself assert or imply that there
are such particular couples, and thus fails to make any statement whatever
about any actual particular couple. The statement made is about 'couple',
the universal, and not about this or that couple.</p>
<p>Thus the statement 'two and two are four' deals exclusively with
universals, and therefore may be known by anybody who is acquainted with
the universals concerned and can perceive the relation between them which
the statement asserts. It must be taken as a fact, discovered by
reflecting upon our knowledge, that we have the power of sometimes
perceiving such relations between universals, and therefore of sometimes
knowing general <i>a priori</i> propositions such as those of arithmetic
and logic. The thing that seemed mysterious, when we formerly considered
such knowledge, was that it seemed to anticipate and control experience.
This, however, we can now see to have been an error. <i>No</i> fact
concerning anything capable of being experienced can be known
independently of experience. We know <i>a priori</i> that two things and
two other things together make four things, but we do <i>not</i> know <i>a
priori</i> that if Brown and Jones are two, and Robinson and Smith are
two, then Brown and Jones and Robinson and Smith are four. The reason is
that this proposition cannot be understood at all unless we know that
there are such people as Brown and Jones and Robinson and Smith, and this
we can only know by experience. Hence, although our general proposition is
<i>a priori</i>, all its applications to actual particulars involve
experience and therefore contain an empirical element. In this way what
seemed mysterious in our <i>a priori</i> knowledge is seen to have been
based upon an error.</p>
<p>It will serve to make the point clearer if we contrast our genuine <i>a
priori</i> judgement with an empirical generalization, such as 'all men
are mortals'. Here as before, we can <i>understand</i> what the
proposition means as soon as we understand the universals involved, namely
<i>man</i> and <i>mortal</i>. It is obviously unnecessary to have an
individual acquaintance with the whole human race in order to understand
what our proposition means. Thus the difference between an <i>a priori</i>
general proposition and an empirical generalization does not come in the
<i>meaning</i> of the proposition; it comes in the nature of the <i>evidence</i>
for it. In the empirical case, the evidence consists in the particular
instances. We believe that all men are mortal because we know that there
are innumerable instances of men dying, and no instances of their living
beyond a certain age. We do not believe it because we see a connexion
between the universal <i>man</i> and the universal <i>mortal</i>. It is
true that if physiology can prove, assuming the general laws that govern
living bodies, that no living organism can last for ever, that gives a
connexion between <i>man</i> and <i>mortality</i> which would enable us to
assert our proposition without appealing to the special evidence of <i>men</i>
dying. But that only means that our generalization has been subsumed under
a wider generalization, for which the evidence is still of the same kind,
though more extensive. The progress of science is constantly producing
such subsumptions, and therefore giving a constantly wider inductive basis
for scientific generalizations. But although this gives a greater <i>degree</i>
of certainty, it does not give a different <i>kind</i>: the ultimate
ground remains inductive, i.e. derived from instances, and not an <i>a
priori</i> connexion of universals such as we have in logic and
arithmetic.</p>
<p>Two opposite points are to be observed concerning <i>a priori</i> general
propositions. The first is that, if many particular instances are known,
our general proposition may be arrived at in the first instance by
induction, and the connexion of universals may be only subsequently
perceived. For example, it is known that if we draw perpendiculars to the
sides of a triangle from the opposite angles, all three perpendiculars
meet in a point. It would be quite possible to be first led to this
proposition by actually drawing perpendiculars in many cases, and finding
that they always met in a point; this experience might lead us to look for
the general proof and find it. Such cases are common in the experience of
every mathematician.</p>
<p>The other point is more interesting, and of more philosophical importance.
It is, that we may sometimes know a general proposition in cases where we
do not know a single instance of it. Take such a case as the following: We
know that any two numbers can be multiplied together, and will give a
third called their <i>product</i>. We know that all pairs of integers the
product of which is less than 100 have been actually multiplied together,
and the value of the product recorded in the multiplication table. But we
also know that the number of integers is infinite, and that only a finite
number of pairs of integers ever have been or ever will be thought of by
human beings. Hence it follows that there are pairs of integers which
never have been and never will be thought of by human beings, and that all
of them deal with integers the product of which is over 100. Hence we
arrive at the proposition: 'All products of two integers, which never have
been and never will be thought of by any human being, are over 100.' Here
is a general proposition of which the truth is undeniable, and yet, from
the very nature of the case, we can never give an instance; because any
two numbers we may think of are excluded by the terms of the proposition.</p>
<p>This possibility, of knowledge of general propositions of which no
instance can be given, is often denied, because it is not perceived that
the knowledge of such propositions only requires a knowledge of the
relations of universals, and does not require any knowledge of instances
of the universals in question. Yet the knowledge of such general
propositions is quite vital to a great deal of what is generally admitted
to be known. For example, we saw, in our early chapters, that knowledge of
physical objects, as opposed to sense-data, is only obtained by an
inference, and that they are not things with which we are acquainted.
Hence we can never know any proposition of the form 'this is a physical
object', where 'this' is something immediately known. It follows that all
our knowledge concerning physical objects is such that no actual instance
can be given. We can give instances of the associated sense-data, but we
cannot give instances of the actual physical objects. Hence our knowledge
as to physical objects depends throughout upon this possibility of general
knowledge where no instance can be given. And the same applies to our
knowledge of other people's minds, or of any other class of things of
which no instance is known to us by acquaintance.</p>
<p>We may now take a survey of the sources of our knowledge, as they have
appeared in the course of our analysis. We have first to distinguish
knowledge of things and knowledge of truths. In each there are two kinds,
one immediate and one derivative. Our immediate knowledge of things, which
we called <i>acquaintance</i>, consists of two sorts, according as the
things known are particulars or universals. Among particulars, we have
acquaintance with sense-data and (probably) with ourselves. Among
universals, there seems to be no principle by which we can decide which
can be known by acquaintance, but it is clear that among those that can be
so known are sensible qualities, relations of space and time, similarity,
and certain abstract logical universals. Our derivative knowledge of
things, which we call knowledge by <i>description</i>, always involves
both acquaintance with something and knowledge of truths. Our immediate
knowledge of <i>truths</i> may be called <i>intuitive</i> knowledge, and
the truths so known may be called <i>self-evident</i> truths. Among such
truths are included those which merely state what is given in sense, and
also certain abstract logical and arithmetical principles, and (though
with less certainty) some ethical propositions. Our <i>derivative</i>
knowledge of truths consists of everything that we can deduce from
self-evident truths by the use of self-evident principles of deduction.</p>
<p>If the above account is correct, all our knowledge of truths depends upon
our intuitive knowledge. It therefore becomes important to consider the
nature and scope of intuitive knowledge, in much the same way as, at an
earlier stage, we considered the nature and scope of knowledge by
acquaintance. But knowledge of truths raises a further problem, which does
not arise in regard to knowledge of things, namely the problem of <i>error</i>.
Some of our beliefs turn out to be erroneous, and therefore it becomes
necessary to consider how, if at all, we can distinguish knowledge from
error. This problem does not arise with regard to knowledge by
acquaintance, for, whatever may be the object of acquaintance, even in
dreams and hallucinations, there is no error involved so long as we do not
go beyond the immediate object: error can only arise when we regard the
immediate object, i.e. the sense-datum, as the mark of some physical
object. Thus the problems connected with knowledge of truths are more
difficult than those connected with knowledge of things. As the first of
the problems connected with knowledge of truths, let us examine the nature
and scope of our intuitive judgements.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />