<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0013" id="link2HCH0013"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER XIII. KNOWLEDGE, ERROR, AND PROBABLE OPINION </h2>
<p>The question as to what we mean by truth and falsehood, which we
considered in the preceding chapter, is of much less interest than the
question as to how we can know what is true and what is false. This
question will occupy us in the present chapter. There can be no doubt that
<i>some</i> of our beliefs are erroneous; thus we are led to inquire what
certainty we can ever have that such and such a belief is not erroneous.
In other words, can we ever <i>know</i> anything at all, or do we merely
sometimes by good luck believe what is true? Before we can attack this
question, we must, however, first decide what we mean by 'knowing', and
this question is not so easy as might be supposed.</p>
<p>At first sight we might imagine that knowledge could be defined as 'true
belief'. When what we believe is true, it might be supposed that we had
achieved a knowledge of what we believe. But this would not accord with
the way in which the word is commonly used. To take a very trivial
instance: If a man believes that the late Prime Minister's last name began
with a B, he believes what is true, since the late Prime Minister was Sir
Henry Campbell Bannerman. But if he believes that Mr. Balfour was the late
Prime Minister, he will still believe that the late Prime Minister's last
name began with a B, yet this belief, though true, would not be thought to
constitute knowledge. If a newspaper, by an intelligent anticipation,
announces the result of a battle before any telegram giving the result has
been received, it may by good fortune announce what afterwards turns out
to be the right result, and it may produce belief in some of its less
experienced readers. But in spite of the truth of their belief, they
cannot be said to have knowledge. Thus it is clear that a true belief is
not knowledge when it is deduced from a false belief.</p>
<p>In like manner, a true belief cannot be called knowledge when it is
deduced by a fallacious process of reasoning, even if the premisses from
which it is deduced are true. If I know that all Greeks are men and that
Socrates was a man, and I infer that Socrates was a Greek, I cannot be
said to <i>know</i> that Socrates was a Greek, because, although my
premisses and my conclusion are true, the conclusion does not follow from
the premisses.</p>
<p>But are we to say that nothing is knowledge except what is validly deduced
from true premisses? Obviously we cannot say this. Such a definition is at
once too wide and too narrow. In the first place, it is too wide, because
it is not enough that our premisses should be <i>true</i>, they must also
be <i>known</i>. The man who believes that Mr. Balfour was the late Prime
Minister may proceed to draw valid deductions from the true premiss that
the late Prime Minister's name began with a B, but he cannot be said to <i>know</i>
the conclusions reached by these deductions. Thus we shall have to amend
our definition by saying that knowledge is what is validly deduced from <i>known</i>
premisses. This, however, is a circular definition: it assumes that we
already know what is meant by 'known premisses'. It can, therefore, at
best define one sort of knowledge, the sort we call derivative, as opposed
to intuitive knowledge. We may say: '<i>Derivative</i> knowledge is what
is validly deduced from premisses known intuitively'. In this statement
there is no formal defect, but it leaves the definition of <i>intuitive</i>
knowledge still to seek.</p>
<p>Leaving on one side, for the moment, the question of intuitive knowledge,
let us consider the above suggested definition of derivative knowledge.
The chief objection to it is that it unduly limits knowledge. It
constantly happens that people entertain a true belief, which has grown up
in them because of some piece of intuitive knowledge from which it is
capable of being validly inferred, but from which it has not, as a matter
of fact, been inferred by any logical process.</p>
<p>Take, for example, the beliefs produced by reading. If the newspapers
announce the death of the King, we are fairly well justified in believing
that the King is dead, since this is the sort of announcement which would
not be made if it were false. And we are quite amply justified in
believing that the newspaper asserts that the King is dead. But here the
intuitive knowledge upon which our belief is based is knowledge of the
existence of sense-data derived from looking at the print which gives the
news. This knowledge scarcely rises into consciousness, except in a person
who cannot read easily. A child may be aware of the shapes of the letters,
and pass gradually and painfully to a realization of their meaning. But
anybody accustomed to reading passes at once to what the letters mean, and
is not aware, except on reflection, that he has derived this knowledge
from the sense-data called seeing the printed letters. Thus although a
valid inference from the-letters to their meaning is possible, and <i>could</i>
be performed by the reader, it is not in fact performed, since he does not
in fact perform any operation which can be called logical inference. Yet
it would be absurd to say that the reader does not <i>know</i> that the
newspaper announces the King's death.</p>
<p>We must, therefore, admit as derivative knowledge whatever is the result
of intuitive knowledge even if by mere association, provided there <i>is</i>
a valid logical connexion, and the person in question could become aware
of this connexion by reflection. There are in fact many ways, besides
logical inference, by which we pass from one belief to another: the
passage from the print to its meaning illustrates these ways. These ways
may be called 'psychological inference'. We shall, then, admit such
psychological inference as a means of obtaining derivative knowledge,
provided there is a discoverable logical inference which runs parallel to
the psychological inference. This renders our definition of derivative
knowledge less precise than we could wish, since the word 'discoverable'
is vague: it does not tell us how much reflection may be needed in order
to make the discovery. But in fact 'knowledge' is not a precise
conception: it merges into 'probable opinion', as we shall see more fully
in the course of the present chapter. A very precise definition,
therefore, should not be sought, since any such definition must be more or
less misleading.</p>
<p>The chief difficulty in regard to knowledge, however, does not arise over
derivative knowledge, but over intuitive knowledge. So long as we are
dealing with derivative knowledge, we have the test of intuitive knowledge
to fall back upon. But in regard to intuitive beliefs, it is by no means
easy to discover any criterion by which to distinguish some as true and
others as erroneous. In this question it is scarcely possible to reach any
very precise result: all our knowledge of truths is infected with some
degree of doubt, and a theory which ignored this fact would be plainly
wrong. Something may be done, however, to mitigate the difficulties of the
question.</p>
<p>Our theory of truth, to begin with, supplies the possibility of
distinguishing certain truths as <i>self-evident</i> in a sense which
ensures infallibility. When a belief is true, we said, there is a
corresponding fact, in which the several objects of the belief form a
single complex. The belief is said to constitute <i>knowledge</i> of this
fact, provided it fulfils those further somewhat vague conditions which we
have been considering in the present chapter. But in regard to any fact,
besides the knowledge constituted by belief, we may also have the kind of
knowledge constituted by <i>perception</i> (taking this word in its widest
possible sense). For example, if you know the hour of the sunset, you can
at that hour know the fact that the sun is setting: this is knowledge of
the fact by way of knowledge of <i>truths</i>; but you can also, if the
weather is fine, look to the west and actually see the setting sun: you
then know the same fact by the way of knowledge of <i>things</i>.</p>
<p>Thus in regard to any complex fact, there are, theoretically, two ways in
which it may be known: (1) by means of a judgement, in which its several
parts are judged to be related as they are in fact related; (2) by means
of <i>acquaintance</i> with the complex fact itself, which may (in a large
sense) be called perception, though it is by no means confined to objects
of the senses. Now it will be observed that the second way of knowing a
complex fact, the way of acquaintance, is only possible when there really
is such a fact, while the first way, like all judgement, is liable to
error. The second way gives us the complex whole, and is therefore only
possible when its parts do actually have that relation which makes them
combine to form such a complex. The first way, on the contrary, gives us
the parts and the relation severally, and demands only the reality of the
parts and the relation: the relation may not relate those parts in that
way, and yet the judgement may occur.</p>
<p>It will be remembered that at the end of Chapter XI we suggested that
there might be two kinds of self-evidence, one giving an absolute
guarantee of truth, the other only a partial guarantee. These two kinds
can now be distinguished.</p>
<p>We may say that a truth is self-evident, in the first and most absolute
sense, when we have acquaintance with the fact which corresponds to the
truth. When Othello believes that Desdemona loves Cassio, the
corresponding fact, if his belief were true, would be 'Desdemona's love
for Cassio'. This would be a fact with which no one could have
acquaintance except Desdemona; hence in the sense of self-evidence that we
are considering, the truth that Desdemona loves Cassio (if it were a
truth) could only be self-evident to Desdemona. All mental facts, and all
facts concerning sense-data, have this same privacy: there is only one
person to whom they can be self-evident in our present sense, since there
is only one person who can be acquainted with the mental things or the
sense-data concerned. Thus no fact about any particular existing thing can
be self-evident to more than one person. On the other hand, facts about
universals do not have this privacy. Many minds may be acquainted with the
same universals; hence a relation between universals may be known by
acquaintance to many different people. In all cases where we know by
acquaintance a complex fact consisting of certain terms in a certain
relation, we say that the truth that these terms are so related has the
first or absolute kind of self-evidence, and in these cases the judgement
that the terms are so related <i>must</i> be true. Thus this sort of
self-evidence is an absolute guarantee of truth.</p>
<p>But although this sort of self-evidence is an absolute guarantee of truth,
it does not enable us to be <i>absolutely</i> certain, in the case of any
given judgement, that the judgement in question is true. Suppose we first
perceive the sun shining, which is a complex fact, and thence proceed to
make the judgement 'the sun is shining'. In passing from the perception to
the judgement, it is necessary to analyse the given complex fact: we have
to separate out 'the sun' and 'shining' as constituents of the fact. In
this process it is possible to commit an error; hence even where a <i>fact</i>
has the first or absolute kind of self-evidence, a judgement believed to
correspond to the fact is not absolutely infallible, because it may not
really correspond to the fact. But if it does correspond (in the sense
explained in the preceding chapter), then it <i>must</i> be true.</p>
<p>The second sort of self-evidence will be that which belongs to judgements
in the first instance, and is not derived from direct perception of a fact
as a single complex whole. This second kind of self-evidence will have
degrees, from the very highest degree down to a bare inclination in favour
of the belief. Take, for example, the case of a horse trotting away from
us along a hard road. At first our certainty that we hear the hoofs is
complete; gradually, if we listen intently, there comes a moment when we
think perhaps it was imagination or the blind upstairs or our own
heartbeats; at last we become doubtful whether there was any noise at all;
then we <i>think</i> we no longer hear anything, and at last we <i>know</i>
we no longer hear anything. In this process, there is a continual
gradation of self-evidence, from the highest degree to the least, not in
the sense-data themselves, but in the judgements based on them.</p>
<p>Or again: Suppose we are comparing two shades of colour, one blue and one
green. We can be quite sure they are different shades of colour; but if
the green colour is gradually altered to be more and more like the blue,
becoming first a blue-green, then a greeny-blue, then blue, there will
come a moment when we are doubtful whether we can see any difference, and
then a moment when we know that we cannot see any difference. The same
thing happens in tuning a musical instrument, or in any other case where
there is a continuous gradation. Thus self-evidence of this sort is a
matter of degree; and it seems plain that the higher degrees are more to
be trusted than the lower degrees.</p>
<p>In derivative knowledge our ultimate premisses must have some degree of
self-evidence, and so must their connexion with the conclusions deduced
from them. Take for example a piece of reasoning in geometry. It is not
enough that the axioms from which we start should be self-evident: it is
necessary also that, at each step in the reasoning, the connexion of
premiss and conclusion should be self-evident. In difficult reasoning,
this connexion has often only a very small degree of self-evidence; hence
errors of reasoning are not improbable where the difficulty is great.</p>
<p>From what has been said it is evident that, both as regards intuitive
knowledge and as regards derivative knowledge, if we assume that intuitive
knowledge is trustworthy in proportion to the degree of its self-evidence,
there will be a gradation in trustworthiness, from the existence of
noteworthy sense-data and the simpler truths of logic and arithmetic,
which may be taken as quite certain, down to judgements which seem only
just more probable than their opposites. What we firmly believe, if it is
true, is called <i>knowledge</i>, provided it is either intuitive or
inferred (logically or psychologically) from intuitive knowledge from
which it follows logically. What we firmly believe, if it is not true, is
called <i>error</i>. What we firmly believe, if it is neither knowledge
nor error, and also what we believe hesitatingly, because it is, or is
derived from, something which has not the highest degree of self-evidence,
may be called <i>probable opinion</i>. Thus the greater part of what would
commonly pass as knowledge is more or less probable opinion.</p>
<p>In regard to probable opinion, we can derive great assistance from <i>coherence</i>,
which we rejected as the <i>definition</i> of truth, but may often use as
a <i>criterion</i>. A body of individually probable opinions, if they are
mutually coherent, become more probable than any one of them would be
individually. It is in this way that many scientific hypotheses acquire
their probability. They fit into a coherent system of probable opinions,
and thus become more probable than they would be in isolation. The same
thing applies to general philosophical hypotheses. Often in a single case
such hypotheses may seem highly doubtful, while yet, when we consider the
order and coherence which they introduce into a mass of probable opinion,
they become pretty nearly certain. This applies, in particular, to such
matters as the distinction between dreams and waking life. If our dreams,
night after night, were as coherent one with another as our days, we
should hardly know whether to believe the dreams or the waking life. As it
is, the test of coherence condemns the dreams and confirms the waking
life. But this test, though it increases probability where it is
successful, never gives absolute certainty, unless there is certainty
already at some point in the coherent system. Thus the mere organization
of probable opinion will never, by itself, transform it into indubitable
knowledge.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />