<SPAN name="startofbook"></SPAN>
<p class="center"><big>TRANSCRIBER'S NOTE:</big></p>
<p>All corrections are underlined with a <ins class="corr" title="original text">dotted line.</ins> The original text appears
when hovering the cursor over the marked text. Inconsistencies in hyphenation have not been corrected; inconsistencies in
spelling have been corrected (both phantasy and fantasy were used in the original text, phantasy has been changed to
fantasy for consistency). A list of corrections to the text can be found at the <SPAN href="#Corrections">end
of the document</SPAN>.</p>
<hr />
<div class="figcenter"> <ANTIMG src="images/cover.jpg" width-obs="450" height-obs="678" id="coverpage" alt="" title="Human Nature and Conduct, by John Dewey" /></div>
<hr/>
<h1 id="Pgi">HUMAN NATURE<br/> AND CONDUCT<br/> <span class="spaced"><small>An Introduction to Social Psychology</small></span></h1>
<p class="center spaced"><small>BY</small><br/>
<big>JOHN DEWEY</big></p>
<div class="figcenter"> <ANTIMG src="images/printdevice.jpg" class="plain" width-obs="150" height-obs="202" alt="" title="logo" /></div>
<p class="center spaced">NEW YORK<br/>
<big>HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY</big><br/>
1922</p>
<hr />
<p class="center spaced" id="Pgii"><span class="smcap">Copyright</span>, 1922,<br/>
<small>BY</small><br/>
HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY</p>
<p><span style="margin-left: 20%;">First Printing, Jan., 1922</span><br/>
<span style="margin-left: 20%;">Second Printing, Mar., 1922</span><br/>
<span style="margin-left: 20%;">Third Printing, June, 1922</span><br/>
<span style="margin-left: 20%;">Fourth Printing, Aug., 1922</span><br/>
<span style="margin-left: 20%;">Fifth Printing, Nov., 1922</span><br/>
<span style="margin-left: 20%;">Sixth Printing, April, 1923</span></p>
<p class="center">PRINTED IN THE U. S. A. BY<br/>
The Quinn & Boden Company<br/>
BOOK MANUFACTURERS<br/>
RAHWAY NEW JERSEY</p>
<hr />
<p class="center"><span class="pb" id="Pgiii">[pg iii]</span><big>PREFACE</big></p>
<p>In the spring of 1918 I was invited by Leland Stanford
Junior University to give a series of three lectures
upon the West Memorial Foundation. One of
the topics included within the scope of the Foundation
is Human Conduct and Destiny. This volume is
the result, as, according to the terms of the Foundation,
the lectures are to be published. The lectures as
given have, however, been rewritten and considerably
expanded. An Introduction and Conclusion have been
added. The lectures should have been published within
two years from delivery. Absence from the country
rendered strict compliance difficult; and I am indebted
to the authorities of the University for their indulgence
in allowing an extension of time, as well as for so many
courtesies received during the time when the lectures
were given.</p>
<p>Perhaps the sub-title requires a word of explanation.
The book does not purport to be a treatment of social
psychology. But it seriously sets forth a belief that
an understanding of habit and of different types of
habit is the key to social psychology, while the operation
of impulse and intelligence gives the key to individualized
mental activity. But they are secondary to
habit so that mind can be understood in the concrete
only as a system of beliefs, desires and purposes which
are formed in the interaction of biological aptitudes
with a social environment.<span style="margin-left: 25em;">J. D.</span></p>
<p>February, 1921</p>
<hr />
<p class="center"><span class="pb" id="Pgv">[pg v]</span><big>CONTENTS</big></p>
<ul class="TOC">
<li> <span class="ralign">PAGE</span></li>
<li>INTRODUCTION <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg001">1</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Contempt for human nature; pathology of goodness; freedom; value of science.</li>
</ul>
<p class="center"><i>PART ONE</i></p>
<p class="center">THE PLACE OF HABIT IN CONDUCT</p>
<ul class="TOC">
<li><span class="smcap">Section I: Habits as Social Functions</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg014"><ins class="corr" title="13" id="Corr_v_">14</ins></SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Habits as functions and arts; social complicity; subjective factor.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section II: Habits and Will</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg024">24</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Active means; ideas of ends; means and ends; nature of character.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section III: Character and Conduct</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg043">43</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Good will and consequences; virtues and natural goods; objective and subjective morals.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section IV: Custom and Habit</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg058">58</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Human psychology is social; habit as conservative; mind and body.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section V: Custom and Morality</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg075">75</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Customs as standards; authority of standards; class conflicts.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section VI: Habit and Social Psychology</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg084">84</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Isolation of individuality; newer movements.</li>
</ul>
<p class="center"><i>PART TWO</i></p>
<p class="center">THE PLACE OF IMPULSE IN CONDUCT</p>
<ul class="TOC">
<li><span class="smcap">Section I: Impulses and Change of Habits</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg089">89</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Present interest in instincts; impulses as re-organizing.</li>
<li><span class="pb" id="Pgvi">[pg vi]</span><span class="smcap">Section II: Plasticity of Impulse</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg095">95</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Impulse and education; uprush of impulse; fixed codes.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section III: Changing Human Nature</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg106">106</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Habits the inert factor; modification of impulses; war a social function; economic regimes as social products; nature of motives.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section IV: Impulse and Conflict of Habits</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg125">125</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Possibility of social betterment; conservatism.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section V: Classification of Instincts</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg131">131</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">False simplifications; "self-love"; will to power; acquisitive and creative.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section VI: No Separate Instincts</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg149">149</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Uniqueness of acts; possibilities of operation; necessity of play and art; rebelliousness.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section VII: Impulse and Thought</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg169">169</SPAN></span></li>
</ul>
<p class="center"><i>PART THREE</i></p>
<p class="center">THE PLACE OF INTELLIGENCE IN CONDUCT</p>
<ul class="TOC">
<li><span class="smcap">Section I: Habit and Intelligence</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg172">172</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Habits and intellect; mind, habit and impulse.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section II: The Psychology of Thinking</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg181">181</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">The trinity of intellect; conscience and its alleged separate subject-matter.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section III: The Nature of Deliberation</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg189">189</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Deliberation as imaginative rehearsal; preference and choice; strife of reason and passion; nature of reason.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section IV: Deliberation and Calculation</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg199">199</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Error in utilitarian theory; place of the pleasant; hedonistic calculus; deliberation and prediction.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section V: The Uniqueness of Good</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg210">210</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Fallacy of a single good; applied to utilitarianism; profit and personality; means and ends.</li>
<li><span class="pb" id="Pgvii">[pg vii]</span><span class="smcap">Section VI: The Nature of Aims</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg223">223</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Theory of final ends; aims as directive means; ends as justifying means; meaning well as an aim; wishes and aims.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section VII: The Nature of Principles</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg238">238</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Desire for certainty; morals and probabilities; importance of generalizations.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section VIII: Desire and Intelligence</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg248">248</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Object and consequence of desire; desire and quiescence; self-deception in desire; desire needs intelligence; nature of idealism; living in the ideal.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section IX: The Present and Future</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg265">265</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Subordination of activity to result; control of future; production and consummation; idealism and distant goals.</li>
</ul>
<p class="center"><i>PART FOUR</i></p>
<p class="center">CONCLUSION</p>
<ul class="TOC">
<li><span class="smcap">Section I: The Good of Activity</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg278">278</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Better and worse; morality a process; evolution and progress; optimism; Epicureanism; making others happy.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section II: Morals are Human</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg295">295</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Humane morals; natural law and morals; place of science.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section III: What is Freedom?</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg303">303</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Elements in freedom; capacity in action; novel possibilities; force of desire.</li>
<li><span class="smcap">Section IV: Morality Is Social</span> <span class="ralign"><SPAN href="#Pg314">314</SPAN></span></li>
<li class="sub1">Conscience and responsibility; social pressure and opportunity; exaggeration of blame; importance of social psychology; category of right; the community as religious symbol.</li>
</ul>
<hr />
<h2><span class="pb" id="Pg001"></span>INTRODUCTION</h2>
<p>"Give a dog a bad name and hang him." Human
nature has been the dog of professional moralists, and
consequences accord with the proverb. Man's nature
has been regarded with suspicion, with fear, with sour
looks, sometimes with enthusiasm for its possibilities
but only when these were placed in contrast with its
actualities. It has appeared to be so evilly disposed
that the business of morality was to prune and curb
it; it would be thought better of if it could be replaced
by something else. It has been supposed that morality
would be quite superfluous were it not for the inherent
weakness, bordering on depravity, of human nature.
Some writers with a more genial conception have attributed
the current blackening to theologians who have
thought to honor the divine by disparaging the human.
Theologians have doubtless taken a gloomier view of
man than have pagans and secularists. But this explanation
doesn't take us far. For after all these theologians
are themselves human, and they would have
been without influence if the human audience had not
somehow responded to them.</p>
<p>Morality is largely concerned with controlling human
nature. When we are attempting to control anything
we are acutely aware of what resists us. So moralists
were led, perhaps, to think of human nature as evil
<span class="pb" id="Pg002"></span>
because of its reluctance to yield to control, its rebelliousness
under the yoke. But this explanation only
raises another question. Why did morality set up
rules so foreign to human nature? The ends it insisted
upon, the regulations it imposed, were after all outgrowths
of human nature. Why then was human nature
so averse to them? Moreover rules can be obeyed and
ideals realized only as they appeal to something in human
nature and awaken in it an active response. Moral
principles that exalt themselves by degrading human
nature are in effect committing suicide. Or else they
involve human nature in unending civil war, and treat
it as a hopeless mess of contradictory forces.</p>
<p>We are forced therefore to consider the nature and
origin of that control of human nature with which
morals has been occupied. And the fact which is forced
upon us when we raise this question is the existence
of classes. Control has been vested in an oligarchy.
Indifference to regulation has grown in the gap which
separates the ruled from the rulers. Parents, priests,
chiefs, social censors have supplied aims, aims which
were foreign to those upon whom they were imposed,
to the young, laymen, ordinary folk; a few have given
and administered rule, and the mass have in a passable
fashion and with reluctance obeyed. Everybody knows
that good children are those who make as little trouble
as possible for their elders, and since most of them
cause a good deal of annoyance they must be naughty
by nature. Generally speaking, good people have been
those who did what they were told to do, and lack of
<span class="pb" id="Pg003"></span>
eager compliance is a sign of something wrong in their
nature.</p>
<p>But no matter how much men in authority have
turned moral rules into an agency of class supremacy,
any theory which attributes the origin of rule to deliberate
design is false. To take advantage of conditions
after they have come into existence is one thing;
to create them for the sake of an advantage to accrue
is quite another thing. We must go back <ins class="corr" title="of" id="Corr_003_">to</ins> the bare
fact of social division into superior and inferior. To
say that accident produced social conditions is to perceive
they were not produced by intelligence. Lack of
understanding of human nature is the primary cause
of disregard for it. Lack of insight always ends in
despising or else unreasoned admiration. When men
had no scientific knowledge of physical nature they
either passively submitted to it or sought to control it
magically. What cannot be understood cannot be
managed intelligently. It has to be forced into subjection
from without. The opaqueness of human nature
to reason is equivalent to a belief in its intrinsic irregularity.
Hence a decline in the authority of social
oligarchy was accompanied by a rise of scientific interest
in human nature. This means that the make-up and
working of human forces afford a basis for moral ideas
and ideals. Our science of human nature in comparison
with physical sciences is rudimentary, and morals
which are concerned with the health, efficiency and
happiness of a development of human nature are
correspondingly elementary. These pages are a discussion
<span class="pb" id="Pg004"></span>
of some phases of the ethical change involved
in positive respect for human nature when the
latter is associated with scientific knowledge. We
may anticipate the general nature of this change
through considering the evils which have resulted from
severing morals from the actualities of human physiology
and psychology. There is a pathology of goodness
as well as of evil; that is, of that sort of goodness
which is nurtured by this separation. The badness of
good people, for the most part recorded only in fiction,
is the revenge taken by human nature for the injuries
heaped upon it in the name of morality. In the first
place, morals cut off from positive roots in man's nature
is bound to be mainly negative. Practical emphasis
falls upon avoidance, escape of evil, upon not doing
things, observing prohibitions. Negative morals assume
as many forms as there are types of temperament subject
to it. Its commonest form is the protective coloration
of a neutral respectability, an insipidity of character.
For one man who thanks God that he is not
as other men there are a thousand to offer thanks
that they are as other men, sufficiently as others are
to escape attention. Absence of social blame is the
usual mark of goodness for it shows that evil has been
avoided. Blame is most readily averted by being so
much like everybody else that one passes unnoticed.
Conventional morality is a drab morality, in which the
only fatal thing is to be conspicuous. If there be flavor
left in it, then some natural traits have somehow escaped
being subdued. To be so good as to attract notice is
<span class="pb" id="Pg005"></span>
to be priggish, too good for this world. The same
psychology that brands the convicted criminal as forever
a social outcast makes it the part of a gentleman
not to obtrude virtues noticeably upon others.</p>
<p>The Puritan is never popular, not even in a society
of Puritans. In case of a pinch, the mass prefer to be
good fellows rather than to be good men. Polite vice
is preferable to eccentricity and ceases to be vice.
Morals that professedly neglect human nature end by
emphasizing those qualities of human nature that are
most commonplace and average; they exaggerate the
herd instinct to conformity. Professional guardians of
morality who have been exacting with respect to themselves
have accepted avoidance of conspicuous evil as
enough for the masses. One of the most instructive
things in all human history is the system of concessions,
tolerances, mitigations and reprieves which the Catholic
Church with its official supernatural morality has devised
for the multitude. Elevation of the spirit above
everything natural is tempered by organized leniency
for the frailties of flesh. To uphold an aloof realm of
strictly ideal realities is admitted to be possible only
for a few. Protestantism, except in its most zealous
forms, has accomplished the same result by a sharp
separation between religion and morality in which a
higher justification by faith disposes at one stroke of
daily lapses into the gregarious morals of average
conduct.</p>
<p>There are always ruder forceful natures who cannot
tame themselves to the required level of colorless
<span class="pb" id="Pg006"></span>
conformity. To them conventional morality appears
as an organized futility; though they are usually unconscious
of their own attitude since they are heartily
in favor of morality for the mass as making it easier
to manage them. Their only standard is success, putting
things over, getting things done. Being good is
to them practically synonymous with ineffectuality;
and accomplishment, achievement is its own justification.
They know by experience that much is forgiven
to those who succeed, and they leave goodness to the
stupid, to those whom they qualify as boobs. Their
gregarious nature finds sufficient outlet in the conspicuous
tribute they pay to all established institutions
as guardians of ideal interests, and in their
denunciations of all who openly defy conventionalized
ideals. Or they discover that they are the chosen
agents of a higher morality and walk subject to specially
ordained laws. Hypocrisy in the sense of a
deliberate covering up of a will to evil by loud-voiced
protestations of virtue is one of the rarest of occurrences.
But the combination in the same person of
an intensely executive nature with a love of popular
approval is bound, in the face of conventional morality,
to produce what the critical term hypocrisy.</p>
<p>Another reaction to the separation of morals from
human nature is a romantic glorification of natural impulse
as something superior to all moral claims. There
are those who lack the persistent force of the executive
will to break through conventions and to use them for
their own purposes, but who unite sensitiveness with
<span class="pb" id="Pg007"></span>
intensity of desire. Fastening upon the conventional
element in morality, they hold that all morality is a
conventionality hampering to the development of individuality.
Although appetites are the commonest things
in human nature, the least distinctive or individualized,
they identify unrestraint in satisfaction of appetite
with free realization of individuality. They treat subjection
to passion as a manifestation of freedom in the
degree in which it shocks the bourgeois. The urgent
need for a transvaluation of morals is caricatured by
the notion that an avoidance of the avoidances of conventional
morals constitutes positive achievement.
While the executive type keeps its eyes on actual conditions
so as to manipulate them, this school abrogates
objective intelligence in behalf of sentiment, and withdraws
into little coteries of emancipated souls.</p>
<p>There are others who take seriously the idea of
morals separated from the ordinary actualities of humanity
and who attempt to live up to it. Some become
engrossed in spiritual egotism. They are preoccupied
with the state of their character, concerned for the
purity of their motives and the goodness of their souls.
The exaltation of conceit which sometimes accompanies
this absorption can produce a corrosive inhumanity
which exceeds the possibilities of any other known form
of selfishness. In other cases, persistent preoccupation
with the thought of an ideal realm breeds morbid discontent
with surroundings, or induces a futile withdrawal
into an inner world where all facts are fair to
the eye. The needs of actual conditions are neglected,
<span class="pb" id="Pg008"></span>
or dealt with in a half-hearted way, because in the light
of the ideal they are so mean and sordid. To speak of
evils, to strive seriously for change, shows a low mind.
Or, again, the ideal becomes a refuge, an asylum, a way
of escape from tiresome responsibilities. In varied ways
men come to live in two worlds, one the actual, the other
the ideal. Some are tortured by the sense of their
irreconcilability. Others alternate between the two,
compensating for the strains of renunciation involved
in membership in the ideal realm by <ins class="corr" title="pleasureable" id="Corr_008_">pleasurable</ins> excursions
into the delights of the actual.</p>
<p>If we turn from concrete effects upon character to
theoretical issues, we single out the discussion regarding
freedom of will as typical of the consequences that come
from separating morals from human nature. Men are
wearied with bootless discussion, and anxious to dismiss
it as a metaphysical subtlety. But nevertheless
it contains within itself the most practical of all moral
questions, the nature of freedom and the means of its
achieving. The separation of morals from human
nature leads to a separation of human nature in its
moral aspects from the rest of nature, and from ordinary
social habits and endeavors which are found in
business, civic life, the run of companionships and recreations.
These things are thought of at most as places
where moral notions need to be applied, not as places
where moral ideas are to be studied and moral energies
generated. In short, the severance of morals from
human nature ends by driving morals inwards from the
public open out-of-doors air and light of day into the
<span class="pb" id="Pg009"></span>
obscurities and privacies of an inner life. The significance
of the traditional discussion of free will is that
it reflects precisely a separation of moral activity from
nature and the public life of men.</p>
<p>One has to turn from moral theories to the general
human struggle for political, economic and religious
liberty, for freedom of thought, speech, assemblage and
creed, to find significant reality in the conception of
freedom of will. Then one finds himself out of the
stiflingly close atmosphere of an inner consciousness and
in the open-air world. The cost of confining moral
freedom to an inner region is the almost complete severance
of ethics from politics and economics. The former
is regarded as summed up in edifying exhortations,
and the latter as connected with arts of expediency
separated from larger issues of good.</p>
<p>In short, there are two schools of social reform. One
bases itself upon the notion of a morality which springs
from an inner freedom, something mysteriously cooped
up within personality. It asserts that the only way
to change institutions is for men to purify their own
hearts, and that when this has been accomplished,
change of institutions will follow of itself. The other
school denies the existence of any such inner power, and
in so doing conceives that it has denied all moral freedom.
It says that men are made what they are by the
forces of the environment, that human nature is purely
malleable, and that till institutions are changed, nothing
can be done. Clearly this leaves the outcome as hopeless
as does an appeal to an inner rectitude and benevolence.
<span class="pb" id="Pg010"></span>
For it provides no leverage for change of environment.
It throws us back upon accident, usually
disguised as a necessary law of history or evolution, and
trusts to some violent change, symbolized by civil war,
to usher in an abrupt millennium. There is an alternative
to being penned in between these two theories. We
can recognize that all conduct is <em>interaction</em> between elements
of human nature and the environment, natural
and social. Then we shall see that progress proceeds
in two ways, and that freedom is found in that kind of
interaction which maintains an environment in which
human desire and choice count for something. There
are in truth forces in man as well as without him.
While they are infinitely frail in comparison with exterior
forces, yet they may have the support of a foreseeing
and contriving intelligence. When we look at the
problem as one of an adjustment to be intelligently
attained, the issue shifts from within personality to an
engineering issue, the establishment of arts of education
and social guidance.</p>
<p>The idea persists that there is something materialistic
about natural science and that morals are degraded by
having anything seriously to do with material things.
If a sect should arise proclaiming that men ought to
purify their lungs completely before they ever drew
a breath it ought to win many adherents from professed
moralists. For the neglect of sciences that deal specifically
with facts of the natural and social environment
leads to a side-tracking of moral forces into an
unreal privacy of an unreal self. It is impossible to
<span class="pb" id="Pg011"></span>
say how much of the remediable suffering of the world
is due to the fact that physical science is looked upon
as merely physical. It is impossible to say how much
of the unnecessary slavery of the world is due to the
conception that moral issues can be settled within conscience
or human sentiment apart from consistent
study of facts and application of specific knowledge
in industry, law and politics. Outside of manufacturing
and transportation, science gets its chance
in war. These facts perpetuate war and the hardest,
most brutal side of modern industry. Each sign of
disregard for the moral potentialities of physical
science drafts the conscience of mankind away from
concern with the interactions of man and nature which
must be mastered if freedom is to be a reality. It diverts
intelligence to anxious preoccupation with the unrealities
of a purely inner life, or strengthens reliance
upon outbursts of sentimental affection. The masses
swarm to the occult for assistance. The cultivated
smile contemptuously. They might smile, as the saying
goes, out of the other side of their mouths if they
realized how recourse to the occult exhibits the practical
logic of their own beliefs. For both rest upon a
separation of moral ideas and feelings from knowable
facts of life, man and the world.</p>
<p>It is not pretended that a moral theory based upon
realities of human nature and a study of the specific
connections of these realities with those of physical
science would do away with moral struggle and defeat.
It would not make the moral life as simple a matter as
<span class="pb" id="Pg012"></span>
wending one's way along a well-lighted boulevard. All
action is an invasion of the future, of the unknown.
Conflict and uncertainty are ultimate traits. But
morals based upon concern with facts and deriving
guidance from knowledge of them would at least locate
the points of effective endeavor and would focus available
resources upon them. It would put an end to the
impossible attempt to live in two unrelated worlds. It
would destroy fixed distinction between the human
and the physical, as well as that between the moral and
the industrial and political. A morals based on study
of human nature instead of upon disregard for it
would find the facts of man continuous with those of
the rest of nature and would thereby ally ethics with
physics and biology. It would find the nature and
activities of one person coterminous with those of other
human beings, and therefore link ethics with the study
of history, sociology, law and economics.</p>
<p>Such a morals would not automatically solve moral
problems, nor resolve perplexities. But it would enable
us to state problems in such forms that action could
be courageously and intelligently directed to their solution.
It would not assure us against failure, but it
would render failure a source of instruction. It would
not protect us against the future emergence of equally
serious moral difficulties, but it would enable us to approach
the always recurring troubles with a fund of
growing knowledge which would add significant values
to our conduct even when we overtly failed—as we
should continue to do. Until the integrity of morals
<span class="pb" id="Pg013"></span>
with human nature and of both with the environment is
recognized, we shall be deprived of the aid of past
experience to cope with the most acute and deep problems
of life. Accurate and extensive knowledge will
continue to operate only in dealing with purely technical
problems. The intelligent acknowledgment of
the continuity of nature, man and society will alone
secure a growth of morals which will be serious without
being fanatical, aspiring without sentimentality,
adapted to reality without conventionality, sensible
without taking the form of calculation of profits, idealistic
without being romantic.</p>
<hr />
<h2 class="spaced"><span class="pb" id="Pg014"></span>PART ONE<br/> <small>THE PLACE OF HABIT IN CONDUCT</small></h2>
<h3>I</h3>
<p>Habits may be profitably compared to physiological
functions, like breathing, digesting. The latter are, to
be sure, involuntary, while habits are acquired. But
important as is this difference for many purposes it
should not conceal the fact that habits are like functions
in many respects, and especially in requiring the
cooperation of organism and environment. Breathing
is an affair of the air as truly as of the lungs; digesting
an affair of food as truly as of tissues of stomach.
Seeing involves light just as certainly as it does the
eye and optic nerve. Walking implicates the ground
as well as the legs; speech demands physical air and
human companionship and audience as well as vocal
organs. We may shift from the biological to the mathematical
use of the word function, and say that natural
operations like breathing and digesting, acquired ones
like speech and honesty, are functions of the surroundings
as truly as of a person. They are things done <em>by</em>
the environment by means of organic structures or
acquired dispositions. The same air that under certain
conditions ruffles the pool or wrecks buildings,
<span class="pb" id="Pg015"></span>
under other conditions purifies the blood and conveys
thought. The outcome depends upon what air acts
upon. The social environment acts through native impulses
and speech and moral habitudes manifest themselves.
There are specific good reasons for the usual
attribution of acts to the person from whom they immediately
proceed. But to convert this special reference
into a belief of exclusive ownership is as misleading
as to suppose that breathing and digesting are
complete within the human body. To get a rational
basis for moral discussion we must begin with recognizing
that functions and habits are ways of using and
incorporating the environment in which the latter has
its say as surely as the former.</p>
<p>We may borrow words from a context less technical
than that of biology, and convey the same idea by saying
that habits are arts. They involve skill of sensory
and motor organs, cunning or craft, and objective
materials. They assimilate objective energies, and
eventuate in command of environment. They require
order, discipline, and manifest technique. They have
a beginning, middle and end. Each stage marks progress
in dealing with materials and tools, advance in converting
material to active use. We should laugh at any
one who said that he was master of stone working, but
that the art was cooped up within himself and in no wise
dependent upon support from objects and assistance
from tools.</p>
<p>In morals we are however quite accustomed to such
a fatuity. Moral dispositions are thought of as belonging
<span class="pb" id="Pg016"></span>
exclusively to a self. The self is thereby isolated
from natural and social surroundings. A whole school
of morals flourishes upon capital drawn from restricting
morals to character and then separating character
from conduct, motives from actual deeds. Recognition
of the analogy of moral action with functions and arts
uproots the causes which have made morals subjective
and "individualistic." It brings morals to earth, and
if they still aspire to heaven it is to the heavens of the
earth, and not to another world. Honesty, chastity,
malice, peevishness, courage, triviality, industry, irresponsibility
are not private possessions of a person.
They are working adaptations of personal capacities
with environing forces. All virtues and vices are habits
which incorporate objective forces. They are interactions
of elements contributed by the make-up of an
individual with elements supplied by the out-door world.
They can be studied as objectively as physiological
functions, and they can be modified by change of either
personal or social elements.</p>
<p>If an individual were alone in the world, he would
form his habits (assuming the impossible, namely, that
he would be able to form them) in a moral vacuum.
They would belong to him alone, or to him only in reference
to physical forces. Responsibility and virtue
would be his alone. But since habits involve the support
of environing conditions, a society or some specific
group of fellow-men, is always accessory before and
after the fact. Some activity proceeds from a man;
then it sets up reactions in the surroundings. Others
<span class="pb" id="Pg017"></span>
approve, disapprove, protest, encourage, share and resist.
Even letting a man alone is a definite response.
Envy, admiration and imitation are complicities. Neutrality
is non-existent. Conduct is always shared; this
is the difference between it and a physiological process.
It is not an ethical "ought" that conduct <em>should</em> be
social. It <em>is</em> social, whether bad or good.</p>
<p>Washing one's hands of the guilt of others is a way
of sharing guilt so far as it encourages in others a
vicious way of action. Non-resistance to evil which
takes the form of paying no attention to it is a way
of promoting it. The desire of an individual to keep
his own conscience stainless by standing aloof from
badness may be a sure means of causing evil and thus
of creating personal responsibility for it. Yet there are
circumstances in which passive resistance may be the
most effective form of nullification of wrong action,
or in which heaping coals of fire on the evil-doer may
be the most effective way of transforming conduct. To
sentimentalize over a criminal—to "forgive" because
of a glow of feeling—is to incur liability for production
of criminals. But to suppose that infliction of <ins class="corr" title="retibutive" id="Corr_017_">retributive</ins>
suffering suffices, without reference to concrete
consequences, is to leave untouched old causes of criminality
and to create new ones by fostering revenge and
brutality. The abstract theory of justice which demands
the "vindication" of law irrespective of instruction
and reform of the wrong-doer is as much a
refusal to recognize responsibility as is the sentimental
gush which makes a suffering victim out of a criminal.</p>
<p><span class="pb" id="Pg018"></span>
Courses of action which put the blame exclusively
on a person as if his evil will were the sole cause of
wrong-doing and those which condone offense on account
of the share of social conditions in producing
bad disposition, are equally ways of making an unreal
separation of man from his surroundings, mind from
the world. Causes for an act always exist, but causes
are not excuses. Questions of causation are physical,
not moral except when they concern future consequences.
It is as causes of future actions that excuses
and accusations alike must be considered. At present
we give way to resentful passion, and then "rationalize"
our surrender by calling it a vindication of justice.
Our entire tradition regarding punitive justice tends
to prevent recognition of social partnership in producing
crime; it falls in with a belief in metaphysical
free-will. By killing an evil-doer or shutting him up
behind stone walls, we are enabled to forget both him
and our part in creating him. Society excuses itself
by laying the blame on the criminal; he retorts by putting
the blame on bad early surroundings, the temptations
of others, lack of opportunities, and the persecutions
of officers of the law. Both are right, except in
the wholesale character of their recriminations. But
the effect on both sides is to throw the whole matter
back into antecedent causation, a method which refuses
to bring the matter to truly moral judgment. For
morals has to do with acts still within our control, acts
still to be performed. No amount of guilt on the part
<span class="pb" id="Pg019"></span>
of the evil-doer absolves us from responsibility for the
consequences upon him and others of our way of treating
him, or from our continuing responsibility for the
conditions under which persons develop perverse habits.</p>
<p>We need to discriminate between the physical and the
moral question. The former concerns what <em>has</em> happened,
and how it happened. To consider this question
is indispensable to morals. Without an answer to it we
cannot tell what forces are at work nor how to direct
our actions so as to improve conditions. Until we
know the conditions which have helped form the characters
we approve and disapprove, our efforts to create
the one and do away with the other will be blind and
halting. But the moral issue concerns the future. It is
prospective. To content ourselves with pronouncing
judgments of merit and demerit without reference to
the fact that our judgments are themselves facts which
have consequences and that their value depends upon
<em>their</em> consequences, is complacently to dodge the moral
issue, perhaps even to indulge ourselves in pleasurable
passion just as the person we condemn once indulged
himself. The moral problem is that of modifying the
factors which now influence future results. To change
the working character or will of another we have to
alter objective conditions which enter into his habits.
Our own schemes of judgment, of assigning blame and
praise, of awarding punishment and honor, are part
of these conditions.</p>
<p>In practical life, there are many recognitions of the
<span class="pb" id="Pg020"></span>
part played by social factors in generating personal
traits. One of them is our habit of making social
classifications. We attribute distinctive characteristics
to rich and poor, slum-dweller and captain of industry,
rustic and suburbanite, officials, politicians, professors,
to members of races, sets and parties. These judgments
are usually too coarse to be of much use. But
they show our practical awareness that personal traits
are functions of social situations. When we generalize
this perception and act upon it intelligently we are
committed by it to recognize that we change character
from worse to better only by changing conditions—among
which, once more, are our own ways of dealing
with the one we judge. We cannot change habit directly:
that notion is magic. But we can change it
indirectly by modifying conditions, by an intelligent
selecting and weighting of the objects which engage
attention and which influence the fulfilment of desires.</p>
<p>A savage can travel after a fashion in a jungle.
Civilized activity is too complex to be carried on without
smoothed roads. It requires signals and junction
points; traffic authorities and means of easy and rapid
transportation. It demands a congenial, antecedently
prepared environment. Without it, civilization would
relapse into barbarism in spite of the best of subjective
intention and internal good disposition. The eternal
dignity of labor and art lies in their effecting that permanent
reshaping of environment which is the substantial
foundation of future security and progress. Individuals
<span class="pb" id="Pg021"></span>
flourish and wither away like the grass of the
fields. But the fruits of their work endure and make
possible the development of further activities having
fuller significance. It is of grace not of ourselves that
we lead civilized lives. There is sound sense in the old
pagan notion that gratitude is the root of all virtue.
Loyalty to whatever in the established environment
makes a life of excellence possible is the beginning of
all progress. The best we can accomplish for posterity
is to transmit unimpaired and with some increment of
meaning the environment that makes it possible to
maintain the habits of decent and refined life. Our
individual habits are links in forming the endless chain
of humanity. Their significance depends upon the environment
inherited from our forerunners, and it is
enhanced as we foresee the fruits of our labors in the
world in which our successors live.</p>
<p>For however much has been done, there always remains
more to do. We can retain and transmit our own
heritage only by constant remaking of our own environment.
Piety to the past is not for its own sake nor for
the sake of the past, but for the sake of a present so
secure and enriched that it will create a yet better
future. Individuals with their exhortations, their
preachings and scoldings, their inner aspirations and
sentiments have disappeared, but their habits endure,
because these habits incorporate objective conditions in
themselves. So will it be with <em>our</em> activities. We may
desire abolition of war, industrial justice, greater
<span class="pb" id="Pg022"></span>
equality of opportunity for all. But no amount of
preaching good will or the golden rule or cultivation
of sentiments of love and equity will accomplish the
results. There must be change in objective arrangements
and institutions. We must work on the environment
not merely on the hearts of men. To think otherwise
is to suppose that flowers can be raised in a desert
or motor cars run in a jungle. Both things can happen
and without a miracle. But only by first changing the
jungle and desert.</p>
<p>Yet the distinctively personal or subjective factors in
habit count. Taste for flowers may be the initial step
in building reservoirs and irrigation canals. The stimulation
of desire and effort is one preliminary in the
change of surroundings. While personal exhortation,
advice and instruction is a feeble stimulus compared
with that which steadily proceeds from the impersonal
forces and depersonalized habitudes of the environment,
yet they may start the latter going. Taste, appreciation
and effort always spring from some accomplished
objective situation. They have objective
support; they represent the liberation of something
formerly accomplished so that it is useful in further
operation. A genuine appreciation of the beauty of
flowers is not generated within a self-enclosed consciousness.
It reflects a world in which beautiful flowers have
already grown and been enjoyed. Taste and desire
represent a prior objective fact recurring in action to
secure perpetuation and extension. Desire for flowers
comes after actual enjoyment of flowers. But it comes
<span class="pb" id="Pg023"></span>
before the work that makes the desert blossom, it comes
before <em>cultivation</em> of plants. Every ideal is preceded by
an actuality; but the ideal is more than a repetition
in inner image of the actual. It projects in securer and
wider and fuller form some good which has been previously
experienced in a precarious, accidental, fleeting
way.</p>
<hr />
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />