<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg075"></span>V</h3>
<p>For practical purposes morals mean customs, folkways,
established collective habits. This is a commonplace
of the anthropologist, though the moral theorist
generally suffers from an illusion that his own place
and day is, or ought to be, an exception. But always
and everywhere customs supply the standards for personal
activities. They are the pattern into which individual
activity must weave itself. This is as true
today as it ever was. But because of present mobility
and interminglings of customs, an individual is now
offered an enormous range of custom-patterns, and can
exercise personal ingenuity in selecting and rearranging
their elements. In short he can, if he will, intelligently
adapt customs to conditions, and thereby remake them.
Customs in any case constitute moral standards. For
they are active demands for certain ways of acting.
Every habit creates an unconscious expectation. It
forms a certain outlook. What psychologists have laboriously
treated under the caption of association of
ideas has little to do with ideas and everything to do
with the influence of habit upon recollection and perception.
A habit, a routine habit, when interfered with
generates uneasiness, sets up a protest in favor of
restoration and a sense of need of some expiatory act,
or else it goes off in casual reminiscence. It is the
<span class="pb" id="Pg076"></span>
essence of routine to insist upon its own continuation.
Breach of it is violation of right. Deviation from it
is transgression.</p>
<p>All that metaphysics has said about the nisus of
Being to conserve its essence and all that a mythological
psychology has said about a special instinct of
self-preservation is a cover for the persistent self-assertion
of habit. Habit is energy organized in certain
channels. When interfered with, it swells as resentment
and as an avenging force. To say that it
will be obeyed, that custom makes law, that <i lang="la" xml:lang="la">nomos</i> is
lord of all, is after all only to say that habit is habit.
Emotion is a perturbation from clash or failure of
habit, and reflection, roughly speaking, is the painful
effort of disturbed habits to readjust themselves. It
is a pity that Westermarck in his monumental collection
of facts which show the connection of custom with
morals<SPAN name="FNanchor_4_" id="FNanchor_4_" href="#Footnote_4_" title="'The Origin and Development of Moral Ideas.'" class="fnanchor">[4]</SPAN>
is still so much under the influence of current
subjective psychology that he misstates the point of
his data. For although he recognizes the objectivity
of custom, he treats sympathetic resentment and approbation
as distinctive inner feelings or conscious
states which give rise to acts. In his anxiety to displace
an unreal rational source of morals he sets up an
equally unreal emotional basis. In truth, feelings as
well as reason spring up within action. Breach of custom
or habit is the source of sympathetic resentment,
while overt approbation goes out to fidelity to custom
maintained under exceptional circumstances.</p>
<p><span class="pb" id="Pg077"></span>
Those who recognize the place of custom in lower
social forms generally regard its presence in civilized
society as a mere survival. Or, like Sumner, they fancy
that to recognize its abiding place is equivalent to the
denial of all rationality and principle to morality;
equivalent to the assertion of blind, arbitrary forces
in life. In effect, this point of view has already
been dealt with. It overlooks the fact that the real
opposition is not between reason and habit but between
routine, unintelligent habit, and intelligent habit or
art. Even a savage custom may be reasonable in that
it is adapted to social needs and uses. Experience may
add to such adaptation a conscious recognition of it,
and then the custom of rationality is added to a prior
custom.</p>
<p>External reasonableness or adaptation to ends precedes
reasonableness of mind. This is only to say that
in morals as well as in physics things have to be there
before we perceive them, and that rationality of mind
is not an original endowment but is the offspring of
intercourse with objective adaptations and relations—a
view which under the influence of a conception of
knowing the like by the like has been distorted into
Platonic and other objective idealisms. Reason as
observation of an adaptation of acts to valuable results
is not however a mere idle mirroring of pre-existent
facts. It is an additional event having its own
career. It sets up a heightened emotional appreciation
and provides a new motive for fidelities previously blind.
It sets up an attitude of criticism, of inquiry, and
<span class="pb" id="Pg078"></span>
makes men sensitive to the brutalities and extravagancies
of customs. In short, it becomes a custom of
expectation and outlook, an active demand for reasonableness
in other customs. The reflective disposition is
not self-made nor a gift of the gods. It arises in some
exceptional circumstance out of social customs, as we
see in the case of the Greeks. But when it has been
generated it establishes a new custom, which is capable
of exercising the most revolutionary influence upon
other customs.</p>
<p>Hence the growing importance of personal rationality
or intelligence, in moral theory if not in practice.
That current customs contradict one another, that
many of them are unjust, and that without criticism
none of them is fit to be the guide of life was the discovery
with which the Athenian Socrates initiated conscious
moral theorizing. Yet a dilemma soon presented
itself, one which forms the burden of Plato's ethical
writings. How shall thought which is personal arrive
at standards which hold good for all, which, in modern
phrase, are objective? The solution found by Plato
was that reason is itself objective, universal, cosmic
and makes the individual soul its vehicle. The result,
however, was merely to substitute a metaphysical or
transcendental ethics for the ethics of custom. If Plato
had been able to see that reflection and criticism express
a conflict of customs, and that their purport and office
is to re-organize, re-adjust customs, the subsequent
course of moral theory would have been very different.
Custom would have provided needed objective and substantial
<span class="pb" id="Pg079"></span>
ballast, and personal rationality or reflective
intelligence been treated as the necessary organ of
experimental initiative and creative invention in remaking
custom.</p>
<p>We have another difficulty to face: a greater wave
rises to overwhelm us. It is said that to derive moral
standards from social customs is to evacuate the latter
of all authority. Morals, it is said, imply the subordination
of fact to ideal consideration, while the view presented
makes morals secondary to bare fact, which is
equal to depriving them of dignity and jurisdiction.
The objection has the force of the custom of moral
theorists behind it; and therefore in its denial of custom
avails itself of the assistance of the notion it attacks.
The criticism rests upon a false separation.
It argues in effect that either ideal standards antecede
customs and confer their moral quality upon them, or
that in being subsequent to custom and evolved from
them, they are mere accidental by-products. But how
does the case stand with language? Men did not intend
language; they did not have social objects consciously
in view when they began to talk, nor did they
have grammatical and phonetic principles before them
by which to regulate their efforts at communication.
These things come after the fact and because of it.
Language grew out of unintelligent babblings, instinctive
motions called gestures, and the pressure of circumstance.
But nevertheless language once called into existence
is language and operates as language. It operates
not to perpetuate the forces which produced it
<span class="pb" id="Pg080"></span>
but to modify and redirect them. It has such transcendent
importance that pains are taken with its use.
Literatures are produced, and then a vast apparatus
of grammar, rhetoric, dictionaries, literary criticism,
reviews, essays, a derived literature <i lang="fr" xml:lang="fr">ad lib</i>. Education,
schooling, becomes a necessity; literacy an end. In
short language when it is produced meets old needs and
opens new possibilities. It creates demands which take
effect, and the effect is not confined to speech and literature,
but extends to the common life in communication,
counsel and instruction.</p>
<p>What is said of the institution of language holds
good of every institution. Family life, property, legal
forms, churches and schools, academies of art and science
did not originate to serve conscious ends nor was
their generation regulated by consciousness of principles
of reason and right. Yet each institution has
brought with its development demands, expectations,
rules, standards. These are not mere embellishments
of the forces which produced them, idle decorations of
the scene. They are additional forces. They reconstruct.
They open new avenues of endeavor and impose
new labors. In short they are civilization, culture,
morality.</p>
<p>Still the question recurs: What authority have standards
and ideas which have originated in this way?
What claim have they upon us? In one sense
the question is unanswerable. In the same sense,
however, the question is unanswerable whatever
origin and sanction is ascribed to moral obligations
<span class="pb" id="Pg081"></span>
and loyalties. Why attend to metaphysical and
transcendental ideal realities even if we concede they
are the authors of moral standards? Why do this act
if I feel like doing something else? Any moral question
may reduce itself to this question if we so choose.
But in an empirical sense the answer is simple. The
authority is that of life. Why employ language, cultivate
literature, acquire and develop science, sustain
industry, and submit to the refinements of art? To
ask these questions is equivalent to asking: Why live?
And the only answer is that if one is going to live one
must live a life of which these things form the substance.
The only question having sense which can be
asked is <em>how</em> we are going to use and be used by these
things, not whether we are going to use them. Reason,
moral principles, cannot in any case be shoved behind
these affairs, for reason and morality grow out of them.
But they have grown into them as well as out of them.
They are there as part of them. No one can escape
them if he wants to. He cannot escape the problem
of <em>how</em> to engage in life, since in any case he must engage
in it in some way or other—or else quit and get
out. In short, the choice is not between a moral authority
outside custom and one within it. It is between
adopting more or less intelligent and significant
customs.</p>
<p>Curiously enough, the chief practical effect of refusing
to recognize the connection of custom with moral
standards is to deify some special custom and treat it
as eternal, immutable, outside of criticism and revision.
<span class="pb" id="Pg082"></span>
This consequence is especially harmful in times of rapid
social flux. For it leads to disparity between nominal
standards, which become ineffectual and hypocritical in
exact ratio to their theoretical exaltation, and actual
habits which have to take note of existing conditions.
The disparity breeds disorder. Irregularity
and confusion are however practically intolerable, and
effect the generation of a new rule of some sort or
other. Only such complete disturbance of the physical
bases of life and security as comes from plague and
starvation can throw society into utter disorder. No
amount of intellectual transition can seriously disturb
the main tenor of custom, or morals. Hence the
greater danger which attends the attempt in period of
social change to maintain the immutability of old
standards is not general moral relaxation. It is rather
social clash, an irreconciled conflict of moral standards
and purposes, the most serious form of class warfare.</p>
<p>For segregated classes develop their own customs,
which is to say their own working morals. As long as
society is mainly immobile these diverse principles and
ruling aims do not clash. They exist side by side in
different strata. Power, glory, honor, magnificence,
mutual faith here; industry, obedience, abstinence,
humility, and reverence there: noble and plebeian virtues.
Vigor, courage, energy, enterprise here; submission,
patience, charm, personal fidelity there: the
masculine and feminine virtues. But mobility invades
society. War, commerce, travel, communication, contact
with the thoughts and desires of other classes, new
<span class="pb" id="Pg083"></span>
inventions in productive industry, disturb the settled
distribution of customs. Congealed habits thaw out,
and a flood mixes things once separated.</p>
<p>Each class is rigidly sure of the rightness of its own
ends and hence not overscrupulous about the means of
attaining them. One side proclaims the ultimacy of
order—that of some old order which conduces to its
own interest. The other side proclaims its rights to
freedom, and identifies justice with its submerged
claims. There is no common ground, no moral understanding,
no agreed upon standard of appeal. Today
such a conflict occurs between propertied classes and
those who depend upon daily wage; between men and
women; between old and young. Each appeals to its
own standard of right, and each thinks the other the
creature of personal desire, whim or obstinacy. Mobility
has affected peoples as well. Nations and races
face one another, each with its own immutable standards.
Never before in history have there existed such
numerous contacts and minglings. Never before have
there been such occasions for conflict which are the
more significant because each side feels that it is supported
by moral principles. Customs relating to what
has been and emotions referring to what may come to
be go their independent ways. The demand of each side
treats its opponent as a wilful violator of moral principles,
an expression of self-interest or superior might.
Intelligence which is the only possible messenger of
reconciliation dwells in a far land of abstractions or
comes after the event to record accomplished facts.</p>
<hr />
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />