<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg169"></span>VII</h3>
<p>We return to the original proposition. The position
of impulse in conduct is intermediary. Morality is an
endeavor to find for the manifestation of impulse in
special situations an office of refreshment and renewal.
The endeavor is not easy of accomplishment. It is
easier to surrender the main and public channels of
action and belief to the sluggishness of custom, and
idealize tradition by emotional attachment to its ease,
comforts and privileges instead of idealizing it in practice
by making it more equably balanced with present
needs. Again, impulses not used for the work of
rejuvenation and vital recovery are sidetracked to find
their own lawless barbarities or their own sentimental
refinements. Or they are perverted to pathological
careers—some of which have been mentioned.</p>
<p>In the course of time custom becomes intolerable because
of what it suppresses and some accident of war
or inner catastrophe releases impulses for unrestrained
expression. At such times we have philosophies which
identify progress with motion, blind spontaneity with
freedom, and which under the name of the sacredness of
individuality or a return to the norms of nature make
impulse a law unto itself. The oscillation between impulse
arrested and frozen in rigid custom and impulse
isolated and undirected is seen most conspicuously when
<span class="pb" id="Pg170"></span>
epochs of conservatism and revolutionary ardor alternate.
But the same phenomenon is repeated on a
smaller scale in individuals. And in society the two
tendencies and philosophies exist simultaneously; they
waste in controversial strife the energy that is needed
for specific criticism and specific reconstruction.</p>
<p>The release of some portion of the stock of impulses
is an opportunity, not an end. In its origin it is the
product of chance; but it affords imagination and invention
<em>their</em> chance. The moral correlate of liberated
impulse is not immediate activity, but reflection upon
the way in which to use impulse to renew disposition
and reorganize habit. Escape from the clutch of custom
gives an opportunity to do old things in new ways,
and thus to construct new ends and means. Breach
in the crust of the cake of custom releases impulses;
but it is the work of intelligence to find the ways of
using them. There is an alternative between anchoring
a boat in the harbor till it becomes a rotting hulk and
letting it loose to be the sport of every contrary gust.
To discover and define this alternative is the business
of mind, of observant, remembering, contriving disposition.</p>
<p>Habit as a vital art depends upon the animation of
habit by impulse; only this inspiriting stands between
habit and stagnation. But art, little as well as great,
anonymous as well as that distinguished by titles of
dignity, cannot be improvised. It is impossible without
spontaneity, but it is not spontaneity. Impulse is
needed to arouse thought, incite reflection and enliven
<span class="pb" id="Pg171"></span>
belief. But only thought notes obstructions, invents
tools, conceives aims, directs technique, and thus converts
impulse into an art which lives in objects.
Thought is born as the twin of impulse in every moment
of impeded habit. But unless it is nurtured, it
speedily dies, and habit and instinct continue their
civil warfare. There is instinctive wisdom in the tendency
of the young to ignore the limitations of the environment.
Only thus can they discover their own
power and learn the differences in different kinds of
environing limitations. But this discovery when once
made marks the birth of intelligence; and with its birth
comes the responsibility of the mature to observe, to
recall, to forecast. Every moral life has its radicalism;
but this radical factor does not find its full expression
in direct action but in the courage of intelligence
to go deeper than either tradition or immediate
impulse goes. To the study of intelligence in action we
now turn our attention.</p>
<hr />
<h2 class="spaced"><span class="pb" id="Pg172"></span>PART THREE<br/> <small>THE PLACE OF INTELLIGENCE IN CONDUCT</small></h2>
<h3>I</h3>
<p>In discussing habit and impulse we have repeatedly
met topics where reference to the work of thought was
imperative. Explicit consideration of the place and
office of intelligence in conduct can hardly begin otherwise
than by gathering together these incidental references
and reaffirming their significance. The stimulation
of reflective imagination by impulse, its dependence
upon established habits, and its effect in transforming
habit and regulating impulse forms, accordingly,
our first theme.</p>
<p>Habits are conditions of intellectual efficiency. They
operate in two ways upon intellect. Obviously, they
restrict its reach, they fix its boundaries. They are
blinders that confine the eyes of mind to the road ahead.
They prevent thought from straying away from its imminent
occupation to a landscape more varied and
picturesque but irrelevant to practice. Outside the
scope of habits, thought works gropingly, fumbling in
confused uncertainty; and yet habit made complete in
routine shuts in thought so effectually that it is no
longer needed or possible. The routineer's road is a
<span class="pb" id="Pg173"></span>
ditch out of which he cannot get, whose sides enclose
him, directing his course so thoroughly that he no
longer thinks of his path or his destination. All habit-forming
involves the beginning of an intellectual specialization
which if unchecked ends in thoughtless
action.</p>
<p>Significantly enough this fullblown result is called
absentmindedness. Stimulus and response are mechanically
linked together in an unbroken chain. Each successive
act facilely evoked by its predecessor pushes us
automatically into the next act of a predetermined series.
Only a signal flag of distress recalls consciousness
to the task of carrying on. Fortunately nature which
beckons us to this path of least resistance also puts
obstacles in the way of our complete acceptance of its
invitation. Success in achieving a ruthless and dull
efficiency of action is thwarted by untoward circumstance.
The most skilful aptitude bumps at times into
the unexpected, and so gets into trouble from which
only observation and invention extricate it. Efficiency
in following a beaten path has then to be converted
into breaking a new road through strange lands.</p>
<p>Nevertheless what in effect is love of ease has masqueraded
morally as love of perfection. A goal of finished
accomplishment has been set up which if it were
attained would mean only mindless action. It has been
called complete and free activity when in truth it is
only a treadmill activity or marching in one place. The
practical impossibility of reaching, in an all around
way and all at once such a "perfection" has been recognized.
<span class="pb" id="Pg174"></span>
But such a goal has nevertheless been conceived
as the ideal, and progress has been defined as
approximation to it. Under diverse intellectual skies
the ideal has assumed diverse forms and colors. But
all of them have involved the conception of a completed
activity, a static perfection. Desire and need have been
treated as signs of deficiency, and endeavor as proof
not of power but of incompletion.</p>
<p>In Aristotle this conception of an end which exhausts
all realization and excludes all potentiality appears
as a definition of the highest excellence. It of
necessity excludes all want and struggle and all dependencies.
It is neither practical nor social. Nothing
is left but a self-revolving, self-sufficing thought
engaged in contemplating its own sufficiency. Some
forms of Oriental morals have united this logic with a
profounder psychology, and have seen that the final
terminus on this road is Nirvana, an obliteration of
all thought and desire. In medieval science, the ideal
reappeared as a definition of heavenly bliss accessible
only to a redeemed immortal soul. Herbert Spencer
is far enough away from Aristotle, medieval Christianity
and Buddhism; but the idea re-emerges in his conception
of a goal of evolution in which adaptation of
organism to environment is complete and final. In
popular thought, the conception lives in the vague
thought of a remote state of attainment in which we
shall be beyond "temptation," and in which virtue
by its own inertia will persist as a triumphant consummation.
Even Kant who begins with a complete scorn
<span class="pb" id="Pg175"></span>
for happiness ends with an "ideal" of the eternal and
undisturbed union of virtue and joy, though in his
case nothing but a symbolic approximation is admitted
to be feasible.</p>
<p>The fallacy in these versions of the same idea is
perhaps the most pervasive of all fallacies in philosophy.
So common is it that one questions whether it
might not be called <em>the</em> philosophical fallacy. It consists
in the supposition that whatever is found true
under certain conditions may forthwith be asserted universally
or without limits and conditions. Because a
thirsty man gets satisfaction in drinking water, bliss
consists in being drowned. Because the success of any
particular struggle is measured by reaching a point of
frictionless action, therefore there is such a thing as an
all-inclusive end of effortless smooth activity endlessly
maintained. It is forgotten that success is success <em>of</em>
a specific effort, and satisfaction the fulfilment <em>of</em> a
specific demand, so that success and satisfaction become
meaningless when severed from the wants and
struggles whose consummations they are, or when
taken universally. The philosophy of Nirvana comes
the closest to admission of this fact, but even it holds
Nirvana to be desirable.</p>
<p>Habit is however more than a restriction of thought.
Habits become negative limits because they are first
positive agencies. The more numerous our habits the
wider the field of possible observation and foretelling.
The more flexible they are, the more refined is perception
in its discrimination and the more delicate the presentation
<span class="pb" id="Pg176"></span>
evoked by imagination. The sailor is intellectually
at home on the sea, the hunter in the forest,
the painter in his studio, the man of science in his laboratory.
These commonplaces are universally recognized
in the concrete; but their significance is obscured
and their truth denied in the current general theory
of mind. For they mean nothing more or less than
that habits formed in process of exercising biological
aptitudes are the sole agents of observation, recollection,
foresight and judgment: a mind or consciousness
or soul in general which performs these operations is
a myth.</p>
<p>The doctrine of a single, simple and indissoluble soul
was the cause and the effect of failure to recognize that
concrete habits are the means of knowledge and
thought. Many who think themselves scientifically
emancipated and who freely advertise the soul for a
superstition, perpetuate a false notion of what knows,
that is, of a separate knower. Nowadays they usually
fix upon consciousness in general, as a stream or process
or entity; or else, more specifically upon sensations and
images as the tools of intellect. Or sometimes they
think they have scaled the last heights of realism by
adverting grandiosely to a formal knower in general
who serves as one term in the knowing relation;
by dismissing psychology as irrelevant to knowledge
and logic, they think to conceal the psychological monster
they have conjured up.</p>
<p>Now it is dogmatically stated that no such conceptions
of the seat, agent or vehicle will go psychologically
<span class="pb" id="Pg177"></span>
at the present time. Concrete habits do all the
perceiving, recognizing, imagining, recalling, judging,
conceiving and reasoning that is done. "Consciousness,"
whether as a stream or as special sensations and
images, expresses functions of habits, phenomena of
their formation, operation, their interruption and reorganization.</p>
<p>Yet habit does not, of itself, know, for it does not
of itself stop to think, observe or remember. Neither
does impulse of itself engage in reflection or contemplation.
It just lets go. Habits by themselves are too
organized, too insistent and determinate to need to
indulge in inquiry or imagination. And impulses are
too chaotic, tumultuous and confused to be able to
know even if they wanted to. Habit as such is too
definitely adapted to an environment to survey or analyze
it, and impulse is too indeterminately related to
the environment to be capable of reporting anything
about it. Habit incorporates, enacts or overrides objects,
but it doesn't know them. Impulse scatters and
obliterates them with its restless stir. A certain delicate
combination of habit and impulse is requisite for
observation, memory and judgment. Knowledge which
is not projected against the black unknown lives in the
muscles, not in consciousness.</p>
<p>We may, indeed, be said to <em>know how</em> by means of our
habits. And a sensible intimation of the practical function
of knowledge has led men to identify all acquired
practical skill, or even the instinct of animals, with
knowledge. We walk and read aloud, we get off and
<span class="pb" id="Pg178"></span>
on street cars, we dress and undress, and do a thousand
useful acts without thinking of them. We know something,
namely, how to do them. Bergson's philosophy
of intuition is hardly more than an elaborately documented
commentary on the popular conception that by
instinct a bird knows how to build a nest and a spider
to weave a web. But after all, this practical work
done by habit and instinct in securing prompt and exact
adjustment to the environment is not knowledge, except
by courtesy. Or, if we choose to call it knowledge—and
no one has the right to issue an ukase to the contrary—then
other things also called knowledge, knowledge
<em>of</em> and <em>about</em> things, knowledge <em>that</em> things are
thus and so, knowledge that involves reflection and conscious
appreciation, remains of a different sort, unaccounted
for and undescribed.</p>
<p>For it is a commonplace that the more suavely efficient
a habit the more unconsciously it operates. Only
a hitch in its workings occasions emotion and provokes
thought. Carlyle and Rousseau, hostile in temperament
and outlook, yet agree in looking at consciousness
as a kind of disease, since we have no consciousness
of bodily or mental organs as long as they work at ease
in perfect health. The idea of disease is, however, aside
from the point, unless we are pessimistic enough to
regard every slip in total adjustment of a person to its
surroundings as something abnormal—a point of view
which once more would identify well-being with perfect
automatism. The truth is that in every waking moment,
the complete balance of the organism and its
<span class="pb" id="Pg179"></span>
environment is constantly interfered with and as constantly
restored. Hence the "stream of consciousness"
in general, and in particular that phase of it celebrated
by William James as alternation of flights and
perchings. Life is interruptions and recoveries. Continuous
interruption is not possible in the activities
of an individual. Absence of perfect equilibrium is not
equivalent to a complete crushing of organized activity.
When the disturbance amounts to such a pitch
as that, the self goes to pieces. It is like shell-shock.
Normally, the environment remains sufficiently in harmony
with the body of organized activities to sustain
most of them in active function. But a novel factor
in the surroundings releases some impulse which tends
to initiate a different and incompatible activity, to
bring about a redistribution of the elements of organized
activity between those have been respectively
central and subsidiary. Thus the hand guided by the
eye moves toward a surface. Visual quality is the dominant
element. The hand comes in contact with an
object. The eye does not cease to operate but some
unexpected quality of touch, a voluptuous smoothness
or annoying heat, compels a readjustment in which the
touching, handling activity strives to dominate the action.
Now at these moments of a shifting in activity
conscious feeling and thought arise and are accentuated.
The disturbed adjustment of organism and environment
is reflected in a temporary strife which concludes
in a coming to terms of the old habit and the new
impulse.</p>
<p><span class="pb" id="Pg180"></span>
In this period of redistribution impulse determines
the direction of movement. It furnishes the focus about
which reorganization swirls. Our attention in short is
always directed forward to bring to notice something
which is imminent but which as yet escapes us. Impulse
defines the peering, the search, the inquiry. It is, in
logical language, the movement into the unknown, not
into the immense inane of the unknown at large, but into
that special unknown which when it is hit upon restores
an ordered, unified action. During this search, old
habit supplies content, filling, definite, recognizable,
subject-matter. It begins as vague presentiment of
what we are going towards. As organized habits are
definitely deployed and focused, the confused situation
takes on form, it is "cleared up"—the essential function
of intelligence. Processes become objects. Without
habit there is only irritation and confused hesitation.
With habit alone there is a machine-like repetition,
a duplicating recurrence of old acts. With conflict
of habits and release of impulse there is conscious
search.</p>
<hr />
<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg181"></span>II</h3>
<p>We are going far afield from any direct moral issue.
But the problem of the place of knowledge and judgment
in conduct depends upon getting the fundamental
psychology of thought straightened out. So the excursion
must be continued. We compare life to a traveler
faring forth. We may consider him first at a
moment where his activity is confident, straightforward,
organized. He marches on giving no direct attention to
his path, nor thinking of his destination. Abruptly he
is pulled up, arrested. Something is going wrong in
his activity. From the standpoint of an onlooker, he
has met an obstacle which must be overcome before his
behavior can be unified into a successful ongoing. From
his own standpoint, there is shock, confusion, perturbation,
uncertainty. For the moment he doesn't know
what hit him, as we say, nor where he is going. But
a new impulse is stirred which becomes the starting
point of an investigation, a looking into things, a trying
to see them, to find out what is going on. Habits which
were interfered with begin to get a new direction as they
cluster about the impulse to look and see. The blocked
habits of locomotion give him a sense of where he <em>was</em>
going, of what he had set out to do, and of the ground
already traversed. As he looks, he sees definite things
which are not just things at large but which are related
<span class="pb" id="Pg182"></span>
to his course of action. The momentum of the activity
entered upon persists as a sense of direction, of aim;
it is an anticipatory project. In short, he recollects,
observes and plans.</p>
<p>The trinity of these forecasts, perceptions and remembrances
form a subject-matter of discriminated
and identified objects. These objects represent habits
turned inside out. They exhibit both the onward tendency
of habit and the objective conditions which have
been incorporated within it. Sensations in immediate
consciousness are elements of action dislocated through
the shock of interruption. They never, however, completely
monopolize the scene; for there is a body of
residual undisturbed habits which is reflected in remembered
and perceived objects having a meaning. Thus
out of shock and puzzlement there gradually emerges a
figured framework of objects, past, present, future.
These shade off variously into a vast penumbra of
vague, unfigured things, a setting which is taken for
granted and not at all explicitly presented. The complexity
of the figured scene in its scope and refinement
of contents depends wholly upon prior habits and their
organization. The reason a baby can know little and
an experienced adult know much when confronting the
same things is not because the latter has a "mind"
which the former has not, but because one has already
formed habits which the other has still to acquire. The
scientific man and the philosopher like the carpenter,
the physician and politician know with their habits not
with their "consciousness." The latter is eventual, not
<span class="pb" id="Pg183"></span>
a source. Its occurrence marks a peculiarly delicate
connection between highly organized habits and unorganized
impulses. Its contents or objects, observed,
recollected, projected and generalized into principles,
represent the incorporated material of habits coming
to the surface, because habits are disintegrating at the
touch of conflicting impulses. But they also gather
themselves together to comprehend impulse and make
it effective.</p>
<p>This account is more or less strange as psychology
but certain aspects of it are commonplaces in a static
logical formulation. It is, for example, almost a truism
that knowledge is both synthetic and analytic; a set of
discriminated elements connected by relations. This
combination of opposite factors of unity and difference,
elements and relations, has been a standing paradox and
mystery of the theory of knowledge. It will remain so
until we connect the theory of knowledge with an empirically
verifiable theory of behavior. The steps of
this connection have been sketched and we may enumerate
them. We know at such times as habits are
impeded, when a conflict is set up in which impulse is
released. So far as this impulse sets up a definite forward
tendency it constitutes the forward, prospective
character of knowledge. In this phase unity or synthesis
is found. We are striving to unify our responses,
to achieve a consistent environment which will restore
unity of conduct. Unity, relations, are prospective;
they mark out lines converging to a focus. They are
"ideal." But <em>what</em> we know, the objects that present
<span class="pb" id="Pg184"></span>
themselves with definiteness and assurance, are retrospective;
they are the conditions which have been mastered,
incorporated in the past. They are elements,
discriminated, analytic just because old habits so far
as they are checked are also broken into objects which
define the obstruction of ongoing activity. They are
"real," not ideal. Unity is something sought; split,
division is something given, at hand. Were we to carry
the same psychology into detail we should come upon
the explanation of perceived particulars and conceived
universals, of the relation of discovery and proof, induction
and deduction, the discrete and the continuous.
Anything approaching an adequate discussion is too
technical to be here in place. But the main point,
however technical and abstract it may be in statement,
is of far reaching importance for everything concerned
with moral beliefs, conscience and judgments of right
and wrong.</p>
<p>The most general, if vaguest issue, concerns the nature
of the organ of moral knowledge. As long as
knowledge in general is thought to be the work of a
special agent, whether soul, consciousness, intellect or
a knower in general, there is a logical propulsion towards
postulating a special agent for knowledge of
moral distinctions. Consciousness and conscience have
more than a verbal connection. If the former is something
in itself, a seat or power which antecedes intellectual
functions, why should not the latter be also a
unique faculty with its own separate jurisdiction? If
reason in general is independent of empirically verifiable
<span class="pb" id="Pg185"></span>
realities of human nature, such as instincts and
organized habits, why should there not also exist a
moral or practical reason independent of natural operations?
On the other hand if it is recognized that
knowing is carried on through the medium of natural
factors, the assumption of special agencies for moral
knowing becomes outlawed and incredible. Now the
matter of the existence or non-existence of such special
agencies is no technically remote matter. The belief
in a separate organ involves belief in a separate and
independent subject-matter. The question fundamentally
at issue is nothing more or less than whether
moral values, regulations, principles and objects form
a separate and independent domain or whether they are
part and parcel of a normal development of a life
process.</p>
<p>These considerations explain why the denial of a
separate organ of knowledge, of a separate instinct or
impulse toward knowing, is not the wilful philistinism
it is sometimes alleged to be. There is of course a sense
in which there is a distinctive impulse, or rather habitual
disposition, to know. But in the same sense there
is an impulse to aviate, to run a typewriter or write
stories for magazines. Some activities result in knowledge,
as others result in these other things. The result
may be so important as to induce distinctive attention to
the activities in order to foster them. From an incident,
almost a by-product, attainment of truth, physical, social,
moral, may become the leading characteristic of
some activities. Under such circumstances, they become
<span class="pb" id="Pg186"></span>
transformed. Knowing is then a distinctive activity,
with its own ends and its peculiarly adapted processes.
All this is a matter of course. Having hit
upon knowledge accidentally, as it were, and the product
being liked and its importance noted, knowledge-getting
becomes, upon occasion, a definite occupation.
And education confirms the disposition, as it may confirm
that of a musician or carpenter or tennis-player.
But there is no more an original separate impulse
or power in one case than in the other. Every
habit is impulsive, that is projective, urgent, and the
habit of knowing is no exception.</p>
<p>The reason for insisting on this fact is not failure
to appreciate the distinctive value of knowledge when
once it comes into existence. This value is so immense
it may be called unique. The aim of the discussion is
not to subordinate knowing to some hard, prosaic utilitarian
end. The reason for insistence upon the derivative
position of knowing in activity, roots in a sense for
fact, and in a realization that the doctrine of a separate
original power and impulse of knowledge cuts
knowledge off from other phases of human nature, and
results in its non-natural treatment. The isolation of
intellectual disposition from concrete empirical facts
of biological impulse and habit-formation entails a denial
of the continuity of mind with nature. Aristotle
asserted that the faculty of pure knowing enters a man
from without as through a door. Many since his day
have asserted that knowing and doing have no intrinsic
connection with each other. Reason is asserted to have
<span class="pb" id="Pg187"></span>
no responsibility to experience; conscience is said to be
a sublime oracle independent of education and social influences.
All of these views follow naturally from a
failure to recognize that all knowing, judgment, belief
represent an acquired result of the workings of natural
impulses in connection with environment.</p>
<p>Upon the ethical side, as has been intimated, the matter
at issue concerns the nature of conscience. Conscience
has been asserted by orthodox moralists to be
unique in origin and subject-matter. The same view is
embodied by implication in all those popular methods
of moral training which attempt to fix rigid authoritative
notions of right and wrong by disconnecting moral
judgments from the aids and tests which are used in
other forms of knowledge. Thus it has been asserted
that conscience is an original faculty of illumination
which (if it has not been dimmed by indulgence in sin)
shines upon moral truths and objects and reveals them
without effort for precisely what they are. Those who
hold this view differ enormously among themselves as
to the nature of the objects of conscience. Some hold
them to be general principles, others individual acts,
others the order of worth among motives, others the
sense of duty in general, others the unqualified authority
of right. Still others carry the implied logic of
authority to conclusion, and identify knowledge of
moral truths with a divine supernatural revelation of a
code of commandments.</p>
<p>But among these diversities there is agreement about
one fundamental. There must be a separate non-natural
<span class="pb" id="Pg188"></span>
faculty of moral knowledge because the things
to be known, the matters of right and wrong, good and
evil, obligation and responsibility, form a separate domain,
separate that is from that of ordinary action in
its usual human and social significance. The latter activities
may be prudential, political, scientific, economic.
But, from the standpoint of these theories, they have
no moral meaning until they are brought under the
purview of this separate unique department of our
nature. It thus turns out that the so-called intuitional
theories of moral knowledge concentrate in themselves
all the ideas which are subject to criticism in these
pages: Namely, the assertion that morality is distinct
in origin, working and destiny from the natural structure
and career of human nature. This fact is the excuse,
if excuse be desired, for a seemingly technical
excursion that links intellectual activity with the conjoint
operation of habit and impulse.</p>
<hr />
<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg189"></span>III</h3>
<p>So far the discussion has ignored the fact that there
is an influential school of moralists (best represented
in contemporary thought by the utilitarians) which
also insists upon the natural, empirical character of
moral judgments and beliefs. But unfortunately this
school has followed a false psychology; and has tended,
by calling out a reaction, actually to strengthen the
hands of those who persist in assigning to morals a
separate domain of action and in demanding a separate
agent of moral knowledge. The essentials of this false
psychology consist in two traits. The first, that knowledge
originates from sensations (instead of from habits
and impulses); and the second, that judgment about
good and evil in action consists in calculation of agreeable
and disagreeable consequences, of profit and loss.
It is not surprising that this view seems to many to
degrade morals, as well as to be false to facts. If the
logical outcome of an empirical view of moral knowledge
is that all morality is concerned with calculating what
is expedient, politic, prudent, measured by consequences
in the ways of pleasurable and painful sensations, then,
say moralists of the orthodox school, we will have
naught to do with such a sordid view: It is a reduction
to the absurd of its premisses. We will have a separate
<span class="pb" id="Pg190"></span>
department for morals and a separate organ of
moral knowledge.</p>
<p>Our first problem is then to investigate the nature
of ordinary judgments upon what it is best or wise to
do, or, in ordinary language, the nature of deliberation.
We begin with a summary assertion that deliberation is
a dramatic rehearsal (in imagination) of various competing
possible lines of action. It starts from the
blocking of efficient overt action, due to that conflict
of prior habit and newly released impulse to which reference
has been made. Then each habit, each impulse,
involved in the temporary suspense of overt action
takes its turn in being tried out. Deliberation is an
experiment in finding out what the various lines of possible
action are really like. It is an experiment in
making various combinations of selected elements of
habits and impulses, to see what the resultant action
would be like if it were entered upon. But the trial is
in imagination, not in overt fact. The experiment is
carried on by tentative rehearsals in thought which do
not affect physical facts outside the body. Thought
runs ahead and foresees outcomes, and thereby avoids
having to await the instruction of actual failure and
disaster. An act overtly tried out is irrevocable, its
consequences cannot be blotted out. An act tried out
in imagination is not final or fatal. It is retrievable.</p>
<p>Each conflicting habit and impulse takes its turn in
projecting itself upon the screen of imagination. It
unrolls a picture of its future history, of the career it
would have if it were given head. Although overt exhibition
<span class="pb" id="Pg191"></span>
is checked by the pressure of contrary propulsive
tendencies, this very inhibition gives habit a chance
at manifestation in thought. Deliberation means precisely
that activity is disintegrated, and that its various
elements hold one another up. While none has force
enough to become the center of a re-directed activity,
or to dominate a course of action, each has enough
power to check others from exercising mastery. Activity
does not cease in order to give way to reflection;
activity is turned from execution into intra-organic
channels, resulting in dramatic rehearsal.</p>
<p>If activity were directly exhibited it would result in
certain experiences, contacts with the environment. It
would succeed by making environing objects, things and
persons, co-partners in its forward movement; or else
it would run against obstacles and be troubled, possibly
defeated. These experiences of contact with objects
and their qualities give meaning, character, to an
otherwise fluid, unconscious activity. We find out what
seeing means by the objects which are seen. They constitute
the significance of visual activity which would
otherwise remain a blank. "Pure" activity is for consciousness
pure emptiness. It acquires a content or
filling of meanings only in static termini, what it comes
to rest in, or in the obstacles which check its onward
movement and deflect it. As has been remarked, the object
is that which objects.</p>
<p>There is no difference in this respect between a visible
course of conduct and one proposed in deliberation.
We have no direct consciousness of what we purpose
<span class="pb" id="Pg192"></span>
to do. We can judge its nature, assign its meaning,
only by following it into the situations whither it leads,
noting the objects against which it runs and seeing how
they rebuff or unexpectedly encourage it. In imagination
as in fact we know a road only by what we see as
we travel on it. Moreover the objects which prick out
the course of a proposed act until we can see its design
also serve to direct eventual overt activity. Every object
hit upon as the habit traverses its imaginary path
has a direct effect upon existing activities. It reinforces,
inhibits, redirects habits already working or
stirs up others which had not previously actively
entered in. In thought as well as in overt action, the
objects experienced in following out a course of action
attract, repel, satisfy, annoy, promote and retard.
Thus deliberation proceeds. To say that at last it
ceases is to say that choice, decision, takes place.</p>
<p>What then is choice? Simply hitting in imagination
upon an object which furnishes an adequate stimulus
to the recovery of overt action. Choice is made as soon
as some habit, or some combination of elements of habits
and impulse, finds a way fully open. Then energy is
released. The mind is made up, composed, unified. As
long as deliberation pictures shoals or rocks or troublesome
gales as marking the route of a contemplated
voyage, deliberation goes on. But when the various
factors in action fit harmoniously together, when imagination
finds no annoying hindrance, when there is a
picture of open seas, filled sails and favoring winds, the
voyage is definitely entered upon. This decisive direction
<span class="pb" id="Pg193"></span>
of action constitutes choice. It is a great error to
suppose that we have no preferences until there is a
choice. We are always biased beings, tending in one
direction rather than another. The occasion of deliberation
is an <em>excess</em> of preferences, not natural
apathy or an absence of likings. We want things that
are incompatible with one another; therefore we have
to make a choice of what we <em>really</em> want, of the course
of action, that is, which most fully releases activities.
Choice is not the emergence of preference out of indifference.
It is the emergence of a unified preference out
of competing preferences. Biases that had held one
another in check now, temporarily at least, reinforce
one another, and constitute a unified attitude. The
moment arrives when imagination pictures an objective
consequence of action which supplies an adequate stimulus
and releases definitive action. All deliberation is
a search for a <em>way</em> to act, not for a final terminus. Its
office is to facilitate stimulation.</p>
<p>Hence there is reasonable and unreasonable choice.
The object thought of may simply stimulate some impulse
or habit to a pitch of intensity where it is temporarily
irresistible. It then overrides all competitors
and secures for itself the sole right of way. The object
looms large in imagination; it swells to fill the field. It
allows no room for alternatives; it absorbs us, enraptures
us, carries us away, sweeps us off our feet by
its own attractive force. Then choice is arbitrary, unreasonable.
But the object thought of may be one
which stimulates by unifying, harmonizing, different
<span class="pb" id="Pg194"></span>
competing tendencies. It may release an activity in
which all are fulfilled, not indeed, in their original form,
but in a "sublimated" fashion, that is in a way which
modifies the original direction of each by reducing it
to a component along with others in an action of transformed
quality. Nothing is more extraordinary than
the delicacy, promptness and ingenuity with which deliberation
is capable of making eliminations and recombinations
in projecting the course of a possible
activity. To every shade of imagined circumstance
there is a vibrating response; and to every complex situation
a sensitiveness as to its integrity, a feeling of
whether it does justice to all facts, or overrides some
to the advantage of others. Decision is reasonable
when deliberation is so conducted. There may be
error in the result, but it comes from lack of data not
from ineptitude in handling them.</p>
<p>These facts give us the key to the old controversy
as to the respective places of desire and reason in conduct.
It is notorious that some moralists have deplored
the influence of desire; they have found the heart
of strife between good and evil in the conflict of desire
with reason, in which the former has force on its side
and the latter authority. But reasonableness is in fact
a quality of an effective relationship among desires
rather than a thing opposed to desire. It signifies the
order, perspective, proportion which is achieved, during
deliberation, out of a diversity of earlier incompatible
preferences. Choice is reasonable when it induces us
to act reasonably; that is, with regard to the claims
<span class="pb" id="Pg195"></span>
of each of the competing habits and impulses. This
implies, of course, the presence of a comprehensive object,
one which coordinates, organizes and functions
each factor of the situation which gave rise to conflict,
suspense and deliberation. This is as true when some
"bad" impulses and habits enter in as when approved
ones require unification. We have already seen the
effects of choking them off, of efforts at direct suppression.
Bad habits can be subdued only by being
utilized as elements in a new, more generous and comprehensive
scheme of action, and good ones be preserved
from rot only by similar use.</p>
<p>The nature of the strife of reason and passion is
well stated by William James. The cue of passion, he
says in effect, is to keep imagination dwelling upon
those objects which are congenial to it, which feed it,
and which by feeding it intensify its force, until it
crowds out all thought of other objects. An impulse
or habit which is strongly emotional magnifies all objects
that are congruous with it and smothers those
which are opposed whenever they present themselves. A
passionate activity learns to work itself up artificially—as
Oliver Cromwell indulged in fits of anger when
he wanted to do things that his conscience would not
justify. A presentiment is felt that if the thought of
contrary objects is allowed to get a lodgment in imagination,
these objects will work and work to chill and
freeze out the ardent passion of the moment.</p>
<p>The conclusion is not that the emotional, passionate
phase of action can be or should be eliminated in behalf
<span class="pb" id="Pg196"></span>
of a bloodless reason. More "passions," not fewer,
is the answer. To check the influence of hate there must
be sympathy, while to rationalize sympathy there are
needed emotions of curiosity, caution, respect for the
freedom of others—dispositions which evoke objects
which balance those called up by sympathy, and prevent
its degeneration into maudlin sentiment and meddling
interference. Rationality, once more, is not a
force to evoke against impulse and habit. It is the
attainment of a working harmony among diverse desires.
"Reason" as a noun signifies the happy cooperation
of a multitude of dispositions, such as sympathy,
curiosity, exploration, experimentation, frankness, pursuit—to
follow things through—circumspection, to
look about at the context, etc., etc. The elaborate systems
of science are born not of reason but of impulses
at first slight and flickering; impulses to handle, move
about, to hunt, to uncover, to mix things separated and
divide things combined, to talk and to listen. Method
is their effectual organization into continuous dispositions
of inquiry, development and testing. It occurs
after these acts and because of their consequences.
Reason, the rational attitude, is the resulting disposition,
not a ready-made antecedent which can be invoked
at will and set into movement. The man who
would intelligently cultivate intelligence will widen, not
narrow, his life of strong impulses while aiming at their
happy coincidence in operation.</p>
<p>The clew of impulse is, as we say, to start something.
It is in a hurry. It rushes us off our feet. It
<span class="pb" id="Pg197"></span>
leaves no time for examination, memory and foresight.
But the clew of reason is, as the phrase also goes, to
stop and think. Force, however, is required to stop the
ongoing of a habit or impulse. This is supplied by
another habit. The resulting period of delay, of suspended
and postponed overt action, is the period in
which activities that are refused direct outlet project
imaginative counterparts. It signifies, in technical
phrase, the mediation of impulse. For an isolated impulse
<em>is</em> immediate, narrowing the world down to the
directly present. Variety of competing tendencies enlarges
the world. It brings a diversity of considerations
before the mind, and enables action to take place
finally in view of an object generously conceived and
delicately refined, composed by a long process of
selections and combinations. In popular phrase, to be
deliberate is to be slow, unhurried. It takes time to put
objects in order.</p>
<p>There are however vices of reflection as well as of
impulse. We may not look far enough ahead because
we are hurried into action by stress of impulse; but
we may also become overinterested in the delights of
reflection; we become afraid of assuming the responsibilities
of decisive choice and action, and in general be
sicklied over by a pale cast of thought. We may become
so curious about remote and abstract matters
that we give only a begrudged, impatient attention to
the things right about us. We may fancy we are glorifying
the love of truth for its own sake when we are
only indulging a pet occupation and slighting demands
<span class="pb" id="Pg198"></span>
of the immediate situation. Men who devote themselves
to thinking are likely to be unusually unthinking in
some respects, as for example in immediate personal relationships.
A man to whom exact scholarship is an
absorbing pursuit may be more than ordinarily vague
in ordinary matters. Humility and impartiality may
be shown in a specialized field, and pettiness and arrogance
in dealing with other persons. "Reason" is
not an antecedent force which serves as a panacea. It
is a laborious achievement of habit needing to be continually
worked over. A balanced arrangement of propulsive
activities manifested in deliberation—namely,
reason—depends upon a sensitive and proportionate
emotional sensitiveness. Only a one-sided, over-specialized
emotion leads to thinking of it as separate from
emotion. The traditional association of justice and
reason has good psychology back of it. Both imply a
balanced distribution of thought and energy. Deliberation
is irrational in the degree in which an end is
so fixed, a passion or interest so absorbing, that the
foresight of consequences is warped to include only
what furthers execution of its predetermined bias. Deliberation
is rational in the degree in which forethought
flexibly remakes old aims and habits, institutes perception
and love of new ends and acts.</p>
<hr />
<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg199"></span>IV</h3>
<p>We now return to a consideration of the utilitarian
theory according to which deliberation consists in calculation
of courses of action on the basis of the profit
and loss to which they lead. The contrast of this notion
with fact is obvious. The office of deliberation is
not to supply an inducement to act by figuring out
where the most advantage is to be procured. It is to
resolve entanglements in existing activity, restore continuity,
recover harmony, utilize loose impulse and redirect
habit. To this end observation of present conditions,
recollection of previous situations are devoted.
Deliberation has its beginning in troubled activity and
its conclusion in choice of a course of action which
straightens it out. It no more resembles the casting-up
of accounts of profit and loss, pleasures and pains, than
an actor engaged in drama resembles a clerk recording
debit and credit items in his ledger.</p>
<p>The primary fact is that man is a being who responds
in action to the stimuli of the environment. This fact
is complicated in deliberation, but it certainly is not
abolished. We continue to react to an object presented
in imagination as we react to objects presented in observation.
The baby does not move to the mother's
breast because of calculation of the advantages of
warmth and food over against the pains of effort. Nor
<span class="pb" id="Pg200"></span>
does the miser seek gold, nor the architect strive to
make plans, nor the physician to heal, because of reckonings
of comparative advantage and disadvantage.
Habit, occupation, furnishes the necessity of forward
action in one case as instinct does in the other. We do
not act <em>from</em> reasoning; but reasoning puts before us
objects which are not directly or sensibly present, so
that we then may react directly to these objects, with
aversion, attraction, indifference or attachment, precisely
as we would to the same objects if they were
physically present. In the end it results in a case of
direct stimulus and response. In one case the stimulus
is presented at once through sense; in the other case, it
is indirectly reached through memory and constructive
imagination. But the matter of directness and indirectness
concerns the way the stimulus is reached,
not the way in which it operates.</p>
<p>Joy and suffering, pain and pleasure, the agreeable
and disagreeable, play their considerable rôle in deliberation.
Not, however, by way of a calculated estimate
of future delights and miseries, but by way of
experiencing present ones. The reaction of joy and
sorrow, elation and depression, is as natural a response
to objects presented in imagination as to those presented
in sense. Complacency and annoyance follow
hard at the heels of any object presented in image as
they do upon its sensuous experience. Some objects
when thought of are congruent to our existing state
of activity. They fit in, they are welcome. They agree,
or are agreeable, not as matter of calculation but as
<span class="pb" id="Pg201"></span>
matter of experienced fact. Other objects rasp; they
cut across activity; they are tiresome, hateful, unwelcome.
They disagree with the existing trend of
activity, that is, they are disagreeable, and in no other
way than as a bore who prolongs his visit, a dun we
can't pay, or a pestiferous mosquito who goes on buzzing.
We do not think of future losses and expansions.
We think, through imagination, of objects into which
in the future some course of action will run, and we
are <em>now</em> delighted or depressed, pleased or pained at
what is presented. This running commentary of likes
and dislikes, attractions and disdains, joys and sorrows,
reveals to any man who is intelligent enough to
note them and to study their occasions his own character.
It instructs him as to the composition and direction
of the activities that make him what he is. To
know what jars an activity and what agrees with it is
to know something important about that activity and
about ourselves.</p>
<p>Some one may ask what practical difference it makes
whether we are influenced by calculation of future joys
and annoyances or by experience of present ones. To
such a question one can hardly reply except in the
words "All the difference in the world." In the first
place, no difference can be more important than that
which concerns the nature of the <em>subject-matter</em> of deliberation.
The calculative theory would have it that
this subject-matter is future feelings, sensations, and
that actions and thought are external means to get
and avoid these sensations. If such a theory has any
<span class="pb" id="Pg202"></span>
practical influence, it is to advise a person to concentrate
upon his own most subjective and private feelings.
It gives him no choice except between a sickly introspection
and an intricate calculus of remote, inaccessible
and indeterminate results. In fact, deliberation, as
a tentative trying-out of various courses of action, is
outlooking. It flies toward and settles upon objective
situations not upon feelings. No doubt we sometimes
fall to deliberating upon the effect of action upon our
future feelings, thinking of a situation mainly with reference
to the comforts and discomforts it will excite in
us. But these moments are precisely our sentimental
moments of self-pity or self-glorification. They conduce
to morbidity, sophistication, isolation from others;
while facing our acts in terms of their objective consequences
leads to enlightenment and to consideration
of others. The first objection therefore to deliberation
as a calculation of future feelings is that, if it is consistently
adhered to, it makes an abnormal case the
standard one.</p>
<p>If however an objective estimate is attempted,
thought gets speedily lost in a task impossible of
achievement. Future pleasures and pains are influenced
by two factors which are independent of present
choice and effort. They depend upon our own state at
some future moment and upon the surrounding circumstances
of that moment. Both of these are variables
which change independently of present resolve and
action. They are much more important determinants
of future sensations than is anything which can now be
<span class="pb" id="Pg203"></span>
calculated. Things sweet in anticipation are bitter in
actual taste, things we now turn from in aversion are
welcome at another moment in our career. Independently
of deep changes in character, such as from mercifulness
to callousness, from fretfulness to cheerfulness,
there are unavoidable changes in the waxing and waning
of activity. A child pictures a future of unlimited
toys and unrestricted sweetmeats. An adult pictures an
object as giving pleasure while he is empty while the
thing arrives in a moment of repletion. A sympathetic
person reckons upon the utilitarian basis the pains of
others as a debit item in his calculations. But why not
harden himself so that others' sufferings won't count?
Why not foster an arrogant cruelty so that the suffering
of others which will follow from one's own action
will fall on the credit side of the reckoning, be pleasurable,
all to the good?</p>
<p>Future pleasures and pains, even of one's own, are
among the things most elusive of calculation. Of all
things they lend themselves least readily to anything
approaching a mathematical calculus. And the further
into the future we extend our view, and the more the
pleasures of others enter into the account, the more
hopeless does the problem of estimating future consequences
become. All of the elements become more and
more indeterminate. Even if one could form a fairly
accurate picture of the things that give pleasure to
most people at the present moment—an exceedingly
difficult task—he cannot foresee the detailed circumstances
which will give a decisive turn to enjoyment at
<span class="pb" id="Pg204"></span>
future times and remote places. Do pleasures due to
defective education or unrefined disposition, to say
nothing of the pleasures of sensuality and brutality,
rank the same as those of cultivated persons having
acute social sensitiveness? The only reason the impossibility
of the hedonistic calculus is not self-evident
is that theorists in considering it unconsciously substitute
for calculation of future pleasures an appreciation
of present ones, a present realization in imagination
of future objective situations.</p>
<p>For, in truth, a man's judgment of future joys and
sorrows is but a projection of what now satisfies and
annoys him. A man of considerate disposition now
feels hurt at the thought of an act bringing harm to
others, and so he is on the lookout for consequences of
that sort, ranking them as of high importance. He
may even be so abnormally sensitive to such consequences
that he is held back from needed vigorous action.
He fears to do the things which are for the real
welfare of others because he shrinks from the thought
of the pain to be inflicted upon them by needed measures.
A man of an executive type, engrossed in carrying
through a scheme, will react in present emotion to
everything concerned with its external success; the pain
its execution brings to others will not occur to him, or
if it does, his mind will easily glide over it. This sort
of consequence will seem to him of slight importance
in comparison with the commercial or political changes
which bulk in his plans. What a man foresees and fails
to foresee, what he appraises highly and at a low rate,
<span class="pb" id="Pg205"></span>
what he deems important and trivial, what he dwells
upon and what he slurs over, what he easily recalls and
what he naturally forgets—all of these things depend
upon his character. His estimate of future consequences
of the agreeable and annoying is consequently
of much greater value as an index of what he now is
than as a prediction of future results.</p>
<p>One has only to read between the lines to see the
enormous difference that marks off modern utilitarianism
from epicureanism, in spite of similarities in professed
psychologies. Epicureanism is too worldly-wise
to indulge in attempts to base present action upon precarious
estimates of future and universal pleasures and
pains. On the contrary it says let the future go, for
life is uncertain. Who knows when it will end, or what
fortune the morrow will bring? Foster, then, with jealous
care every gift of pleasure now allotted to you,
dwell upon it with lingering love, prolong it as best you
may. Utilitarianism on the contrary was a part of a
philanthropic and reform movement of the nineteenth
century. Its commendation of an elaborate and impossible
calculus was in reality part of a movement to
develop a type of character which should have a wide
social outlook, sympathy with the experiences of all
sentient creatures, one zealous about the social effects
of all proposed acts, especially those of collective legislation
and administration. It was concerned not with
extracting the honey of the passing moment but with
breeding improved bees and constructing hives.</p>
<p>After all, the object of foresight of consequences is
<span class="pb" id="Pg206"></span>
not to predict the future. It is to ascertain the meaning
of present activities and to secure, so far as possible,
a present activity with a unified meaning. We are
not the creators of heaven and earth; we have no responsibility
for their operations save as their motions
are altered by our movements. Our concern is with
the significance of that slight fraction of total activity
which starts from ourselves. The best laid plans of
men as well of mice gang aglee; and for the same
reason: inability to dominate the future. The power
of man and mouse is infinitely constricted in comparison
with the power of events. Men always build better or
worse than they know, for their acts are taken up into
the broad sweep of events.</p>
<p>Hence the problem of deliberation is not to calculate
future happenings but to appraise present proposed
actions. We judge present desires and habits by their
tendency to produce certain consequences. It is our
business to watch the course of our action so as to see
what is the significance, the import of our habits and
dispositions. The future outcome is not certain. But
neither is it certain what the present fire will do in the
future. It may be unexpectedly fed or extinguished.
But its <em>tendency</em> is a knowable matter, what it will do
under certain circumstances. And so we know what is
the tendency of malice, charity, conceit, patience. We
know by observing their consequences, by recollecting
what we have observed, by using that recollection in
constructive imaginative forecasts of the future, by
<span class="pb" id="Pg207"></span>
using the thought of future consequence to tell the
quality of the act now proposed.</p>
<p>Deliberation is not calculation of indeterminate future
results. The present, not the future, is ours. No
shrewdness, no store of information will make it ours.
But by constant watchfulness concerning the tendency
of acts, by noting disparities between former judgments
and actual outcomes, and tracing that part of the disparity
that was due to deficiency and excess in disposition,
we come to know the meaning of present acts,
and to guide them in the light of that meaning. The
moral is to develop conscientiousness, ability to judge
the significance of what we are doing and to use that
judgment in directing what we do, not by means of
direct cultivation of something called conscience, or
reason, or a faculty of moral knowledge, but by fostering
those impulses and habits which experience has
shown to make us sensitive, generous, imaginative, impartial
in perceiving the tendency of our inchoate dawning
activities. Every attempt to forecast the future is
subject in the end to the auditing of present concrete
impulse and habit. Therefore the important thing is
the fostering of those habits and impulses which lead to
a broad, just, sympathetic survey of situations.</p>
<p>The occasion of deliberation, that is of the attempt
to find a stimulus to complete overt action in thought
of some future object, is confusion and uncertainty
in present activities. A similar devision in activities
and need of a like deliberative activity for the
<span class="pb" id="Pg208"></span>
sake of recovery of unity is sure to recur, to recur again
and again, no matter how wise the decision. Even the
most comprehensive deliberation leading to the most
momentous choice only fixes a disposition which has to
be continuously applied in new and unforeseen conditions,
re-adapted by future deliberations. Always our
old habits and dispositions carry us into new fields.
We have to be always learning and relearning the meaning
of our active tendencies. Does not this reduce
moral life to the futile toil of a Sisyphus who is forever
rolling a stone uphill only to have it roll back so
that he has to repeat his old task? Yes, judged from
progress made in a control of conditions which shall
stay put and which excludes the necessity of future deliberations
and reconsiderations. No, because continual
search and experimentation to discover the meaning
of changing activity, keeps activity alive, growing
in significance. The future situation involved in deliberation
is of necessity marked by contingency. What
it will be in fact remains dependent upon conditions that
escape our foresight and power of regulation. But
foresight which draws liberally upon the lessons of past
experience reveals the tendency, the meaning, of present
action; and, once more, it is this present meaning rather
than the future outcome which counts. Imaginative
forethought of the probable consequences of a proposed
act keeps that act from sinking below consciousness into
routine habit or whimsical brutality. It preserves the
meaning of that act alive, and keeps it growing in
depth and refinement of meaning. There is no limit to
<span class="pb" id="Pg209"></span>
the amount of meaning which reflective and meditative
habit is capable of importing into even simple acts,
just as the most splendid successes of the skilful executive
who manipulates events may be accompanied by an
incredibly meager and superficial consciousness.</p>
<hr />
<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg210"></span>V</h3>
<p>The reason for dividing conduct into two distinct
regions, one of expediency and the other of morality,
disappears when the psychology that identifies ordinary
deliberation with calculation is disposed of. There
is seen to be but one issue involved in all reflection upon
conduct: The rectifying of present troubles, the harmonizing
of present incompatibilities by projecting a
course of action which gathers into itself the meaning
of them all. The recognition of the true psychology
also reveals to us the nature of good or satisfaction.
Good consists in the meaning that is experienced to
belong to an activity when conflict and entanglement
of various incompatible impulses and habits terminate
in a unified orderly release in action. This human good,
being a fulfilment conditioned upon thought, differs
from the pleasures which an animal nature—of course
we also remain animals so far as we do not think—hits
upon accidentally. Moreover there is a genuine difference
between a false good, a spurious satisfaction,
and a "true" good, and there is an empirical test for
discovering the difference. The unification which ends
thought in act may be only a superficial compromise,
not a real decision but a postponement of the issue.
Many of our so-called decisions are of this nature. Or
it may present, as we have seen, a victory of a temporarily
<span class="pb" id="Pg211"></span>
intense impulse over its rivals, a unity by oppression
and suppression, not by coordination. These
seeming unifications which are not unifications of fact
are revealed by the event, by subsequent occurrences.
It is one of the penalties of evil choice, perhaps the chief
penalty, that the wrong-doer becomes more and more incapable
of detecting these objective revelations of
himself.</p>
<p>In quality, the good is never twice alike. It never
copies itself. It is new every morning, fresh every
evening. It is unique in its every <ins class="corr" title="presentation" id="Corr_211_">presentation.</ins> For it
marks the resolution of a distinctive complication of
competing habits and impulses which can never repeat
itself. Only with a habit rigid to the point of immobility
could exactly the same good recur twice. And
with such rigid routines the same good does not after
all recur, for it does not even occur. There is no consciousness
at all, either of good or bad. Rigid habits
sink below the level of any meaning at all. And since
we live in a moving world, they plunge us finally against
conditions to which they are not adapted and so terminate
in disaster.</p>
<p>To utilitarianism with all its defects belongs the distinction
of enforcing in an unforgettable way the fact
that moral good, like every good, consists in a satisfaction
of the forces of human nature, in welfare, happiness.
To Bentham remains, in spite of all crudities
and eccentricities, the imperishable renown of forcing
home to the popular consciousness that "conscience,"
intelligence applied to in moral matters, is too often
<span class="pb" id="Pg212"></span>
not intelligence but is veiled caprice, dogmatic <i lang="la" xml:lang="la">ipse
dixitism</i>, vested class interest. It is truly conscience
only as it contributes to relief of misery and promotion
of happiness. An examination of utilitarianism
brings out however the catastrophe involved in thinking
of the good to which intelligence is pertinent as consisting
in future pleasures and pains, and moral reflection
as their algebraic calculus. It emphasizes the
contrast between such conceptions of good and of intelligence,
and the facts of human nature according to
which good, happiness, is found in the present meaning
of activity, depending upon the proportion, order and
freedom introduced into it by thought as it discovers
objects which release and unify otherwise contending
elements.</p>
<p>An adequate discussion of why utilitarianism with its
just insight into the central place of good, and its
ardent devotion to rendering morals more intelligent
and more equitably human took its onesided course (and
thereby provoked an intensified reaction to transcendental
and dogmatic morals) would take us far afield
into social conditions and the antecedent history of
thought. We can deal with <ins class="corr" title="only" id="Corr_212_">only one</ins> factor, the domination
of intellectual interest by economic considerations. The
industrial revolution was bound in any case to give a
new direction to thought. It enforced liberation from
other-worldly concerns by fixing attention upon the
possibility of the betterment of this world through control
and utilization of natural forces; it opened up
marvelous possibilities in industry and commerce, and
<span class="pb" id="Pg213"></span>
new social conditions conducive to invention, ingenuity,
enterprise, constructive energy and an impersonal habit
of mind dealing with mechanisms rather than appearances.
But new movements do not start in a new and
clear field. The context of old institutions and corresponding
habits of thought persisted. The new movement
was perverted in theory because prior established
conditions deflected it in practice. Thus the new industrialism
was largely the old feudalism, living in a
bank instead of a castle and brandishing the check of
credit instead of the sword.</p>
<p>An old theological doctrine of total depravity was
continued and carried over in the idea of an inherent
laziness of human nature which rendered it averse to
useful work, unless bribed by expectations of pleasure,
or driven by fears of pains. This being the "incentive"
to action, it followed that the office of reason is
only to enlighten the search for good or gain by instituting
a more exact calculus of profit and loss. Happiness
was thus identified with a maximum net gain of
pleasures on the basis of analogy with business conducted
for pecuniary profit, and directed by means of
a science of accounting dealing with quantities of receipts
and expenses expressed in definite monetary
units.<SPAN name="FNanchor_6_" id="FNanchor_6_" href="#Footnote_6_" title="I owe the suggestion of this mode of interpreting the hedonistic calculus of utilitarianism to Dr. Wesley Mitchell. See his articles in Journal of Political Economy, vol. 18. Compare also his article in Political Science Quarterly, vol. 33." class="fnanchor">[6]</SPAN>
For business was conducted as matter of fact
with primary reference to procuring gain and averting
loss. Gain and loss were reckoned in terms of units of
<span class="pb" id="Pg214"></span>
money, assumed to be fixed and equal, exactly comparable
whether loss or gain occurred, while business foresight
reduced future prospects to definitely measured
forms, to dollars and cents. A dollar is a dollar, past,
present or future; and every business transaction, every
expenditure and consumption of time, energy, goods,
is, in theory, capable of exact statement in terms of
dollars. Generalize this point of view into the notion
that gain is the object of <em>all</em> action; that gain takes the
form of pleasure; that there are definite, commensurable
units of pleasure, which are exactly offset by units
of pain (loss), and the working psychology of the
Benthamite school is at hand.</p>
<p>Now admitting that the device of money accounting
makes possible more exact estimates of the consequences
of many acts than is otherwise possible, and that accordingly
the use of money and accounting may work a
triumph for the application of intelligence in daily affairs,
yet there exists a difference in kind between business
calculation of profit and loss and deliberation upon
what purposes to form. Some of these differences are
inherent and insuperable. Others of them are due to
the nature of present business conducted for pecuniary
profit, and would disappear if business were conducted
primarily for service of needs. But it is important to
see <em>how</em> in the latter case the assimilation of business
accounting and normal deliberation would occur. For
it would not consist in making deliberation identical
with calculation of loss and gain; it would proceed in
the opposite direction. It would make accounting and
<span class="pb" id="Pg215"></span>
auditing a subordinate factor in discovering the meaning
of present activity. Calculation would be a means
of stating future results more exactly and objectively
and thus of making action more humane. Its function
would be that of statistics in all social science.</p>
<p>But first as to the inherent difference between deliberation
regarding business profit and loss and deliberation
about ordinary conduct. The distinction between
wide and narrow use of reason has already been
noted. The latter holds a fixed end in view and deliberates
only upon means of reaching it. The former
regards the end-in-view in deliberation as tentative and
permits, nay encourages the coming into view of consequences
which will transform it and create a new
purpose and plan. Now business calculation is obviously
of the kind where the end is taken for granted
and does not enter into deliberation. It resembles the
case in which a man has already made his final decision,
say to take a walk, and deliberates only upon what
walk to take. His end-in-view already exists; it is not
questioned. The question is as to comparative advantages
of this tramp or that. Deliberation is not free
but occurs within the limits of a decision reached by
some prior deliberation or else fixed by unthinking routine.
Suppose, however, that a man's question is not
which path to walk upon, but whether to walk or to
stay with a friend whom continued confinement has rendered
peevish and uninteresting as a companion. The
utilitarian theory demands that in the latter case the
two alternatives still be of the same kind, alike in quality,
<span class="pb" id="Pg216"></span>
that their only difference be a quantitative one, of
plus or minus in pleasure. This assumption that all
desires and dispositions, all habits and impulses, are
the same in quality is equivalent to the assertion that
no real or significant conflict among them is possible;
and hence there is no need of discovering an object and
an activity which will bring them into unity. It asserts
by implication that there is no genuine doubt or suspense
as to the meaning of any impulse or habit. Their
meaning is ready-made, fixed: pleasure. The only
"problem" or doubt is as to the <em>amount</em> of pleasure
(or pain) that is involved.</p>
<p>This assumption does violence to fact. The poignancy
of situations that evoke reflection lies in the fact
that we really do not know the meaning of the tendencies
that are pressing for action. We have to
search, to experiment. Deliberation is a work of discovery.
Conflict is acute; one impulse carries us one
way into one situation, and another impulse takes us
another way to a radically different objective result.
Deliberation is not an attempt to do away with this
opposition of quality by reducing it to one of amount.
It is an attempt to <em>uncover</em> the conflict in its full scope
and bearing. What we want to find out is what difference
each impulse and habit imports, to reveal qualitative
incompatibilities by detecting the different
courses to which they commit us, the different dispositions
they form and foster, the different situations
into which they plunge us.</p>
<p>In short, the thing actually at stake in any serious
<span class="pb" id="Pg217"></span>
deliberation is not a difference of quantity, but what
kind of person one is to become, what sort of self is in
the making, what kind of a world is making. This
is plain enough in those crucial decisions where the
course of life is thrown into widely different channels,
where the pattern of life is rendered different and diversely
dyed according as this alternative or that is
chosen. Deliberation as to whether to be a merchant
or a school teacher, a physician or a politician is not a
choice of quantities. It is just what it appears to be,
a choice of careers which are incompatible with one
another, within each of which definitive inclusions and
rejections are involved. With the difference in career
belongs a difference in the constitution of the self, of
habits of thought and feeling as well as of outward
action. With it comes profound differences in all future
objective relationships. Our minor decisions differ
in acuteness and range, but not in principle. Our world
does not so obviously hang upon any one of them; but
put together they make the world what it is in meaning
for each one of us. Crucial decisions can hardly be
more than a disclosure of the cumulative force of trivial
choices.</p>
<p>A radical distinction thus exists between deliberation
where the only question is whether to invest money in
this bond or that stock, and deliberation where the
primary decision is as to the <em>kind</em> of activity which is
to be engaged in. Definite quantitative calculation is
possible in the former case because a decision as to kind
or direction of action does not have to be made. It has
<span class="pb" id="Pg218"></span>
been decided already, whether by persistence of habit,
or prior deliberation, that the man is to be an investor.
The significant thing in decisions proper, the course
of action, the kind of a self simply, doesn't enter in;
it isn't in question. To reduce all cases of judgment of
action to this simplified and comparatively unimportant
case of calculation of quantities, is to miss the
whole point of deliberation.<SPAN name="FNanchor_7_" id="FNanchor_7_" href="#Footnote_7_" title="So far as I am aware Dr. H. W. Stuart was the first to point out this difference between economic and moral valuations in his essay in Studies in Logical Theory." class="fnanchor">[7]</SPAN></p>
<p>It is another way of saying the same thing to note
that business calculations about pecuniary gain never
concern direct use in experience. They are, as such,
not deliberations about good or satisfaction at all. The
man who decides to put business activity before all other
claims whatsoever, before that of family or country or
art or science, does make a choice about satisfaction
or good. But he makes it as a man, not as a business
man. On the other hand, what is to be <em>done</em> with business
profit when it accrues (except to invest it in similar
undertakings) does not enter at all into a strictly
business deliberation. Its use, in which alone good or
satisfaction is found, is left indeterminate, contingent
upon further deliberation, or else is left matter of routine
habit. We do not eat money, or wear it, or marry
it, or listen for musical strains to issue from it. If by
any chance a man prefers a less amount of money to
a greater amount, it is not for economic reasons. Pecuniary
profit in itself, in other words, is always strictly
<span class="pb" id="Pg219"></span>
instrumental, and it is of the nature of this instrument
to be effective in proportion to size. In choosing with
respect to it, we are not making a significant choice,
a choice of ends.</p>
<p>We have already seen, however, there is something
abnormal and in the strict sense impossible in mere
means, in, that is, instruments totally dissevered from
ends. We may view economic activity in abstraction,
but it does not <em>exist</em> by itself. Business takes for
granted non-business uses to which its results are to
be put. The stimuli for economic activity (in the sense
in which business means activity subject to monetary
reckoning) are found in non-pecuniary, non-economic
activities. Taken by itself then economic action throws
no light upon the nature of satisfaction and the relation
of intelligence to it, because the whole question of
satisfaction is either taken for granted or else is ignored
by it. Only when money-making is itself taken as
a good does it exhibit anything pertinent to the question.
And when it is so taken, then the question is not
one of future gain but of present activity and its meaning.
Business then becomes an activity carried on for
its own sake. It is then a career, a continuous occupation
in which are developed daring, adventure,
power, rivalry, overcoming of competitors, conspicuous
achievement which attracts admiration, play of imagination,
technical knowledge, skill in foresight and
making combinations, management of men and goods
and so on. In this case, it exemplifies what has been
said about good or happiness as incorporating in itself
<span class="pb" id="Pg220"></span>
at <em>present</em> the foreseen future consequences that result
from intelligent action. The problem concerns the
quality of such a good.</p>
<p>In short the attempt to assimilate other activities
to the model of economic activity (defined as a calculated
pursuit of gain) reverses the state of the facts.
The "economic man" defined as a creature devoted to
an enlightened or calculating pursuit of gain is morally
objectionable because the conception of such a being
empirically falsifies empirical facts. Love of pecuniary
gain is an undoubted and powerful fact. But
it and its importance are affairs of social not of psychological
nature. It is not a primary fact which can
be used to account for other phenomena. It depends
upon other impulses and habits. It expresses and organizes
the use to which they are put. It cannot be
used to define the nature of desire, effort and satisfaction,
because it embodies a socially selected type of desire
and satisfaction. It affords, like steeple-chasing,
or collecting postage stamps, seeking political office, astronomical
observation of the heavens, a special case of
desire, effort, and happiness. And like them it is subject
to examination, criticism and valuation in the light
of the place it occupies in the system of developing
activities.</p>
<p>The reason that it is so easy and for specific purposes
so useful to select economic activities and subject
them to separate scientific treatment is because the men
who engage in it are men who are also more than business
men, whose usual habits may be more or less safely
<span class="pb" id="Pg221"></span>
guessed at. As human beings they have desires and occupations
which are affected by social custom, expectation
and admiration. The uses to which gains will be
put, that is the current scheme of activities into which
they enter as factors, are passed over only because they
are so inevitably present. Support of family, of church,
philanthropic benefactions, political influence, automobiling,
command of luxuries, freedom of movement, respect
from others, are in general terms some of the
obvious activities into which economic activity fits.
This context of activities enters into the real make-up
and meaning of economic activity. Calculated pursuit
of gain is in fact never what it is made out to be when
economic action is separated from the rest of life, for
in fact it is what it is because of a complex social environment
involving scientific, legal, political and domestic
conditions.</p>
<p>A certain tragic fate seems to attend all intellectual
movements. That of utilitarianism is suggested in the
not infrequent criticism that it exaggerated the rôle of
rational thought in human conduct, that it assumed
that everybody is moved by conscious considerations
and that all that is really necessary is to make the process
of consideration sufficiently enlightened. Then it
is objected that a better psychology reveals that men
are not moved by thought but rather by instinct and
habit. Thus a partially sound criticism is employed to
conceal the one factor in utilitarianism from which we
ought to learn something; is used to foster an obscurantist
doctrine of trusting to impulse, instinct or intuition.
<span class="pb" id="Pg222"></span>
Neither the utilitarians nor any one else can exaggerate
the proper office of reflection, of intelligence,
in conduct. The mistake lay not here but in a false
conception of what constitutes reflection, deliberation.
The truth that men are not moved by consideration of
self-interest, that men are not good judges of where
their interests lie and are not moved to act by these
judgments, cannot properly be converted into the belief
that consideration of consequences is a negligible factor
in conduct. So far as it is negligible in fact it evinces
the rudimentary character of civilization. We may
indeed safely start from the assumption that impulse
and habit, not thought, are the primary determinants
of conduct. But the conclusion to be drawn from these
facts is that the need is therefore the greater for cultivation
of thought. The error of utilitarianism is not
at this point. It is found in its wrong conception of
what thought, deliberation, is and does.</p>
<hr />
<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg223"></span>VI</h3>
<p>Our problem now concerns the nature of ends, that
is ends-in-view or aims. The essential elements in the
problem have already been stated. It has been pointed
out that the ends, objectives, of conduct are those foreseen
consequences which influence present deliberation
and which finally bring it to rest by furnishing an adequate
stimulus to overt action. Consequently ends arise
and function within action. They are not, as current
theories too often imply, things lying beyond activity
at which the latter is directed. They are not strictly
speaking ends or termini of action at all. They are
terminals of deliberation, and so turning points <em>in</em> activity.
Many opposed moral theories agree however in
placing ends beyond action, although they differ in
their notions of what the ends are. The utilitarian sets
up pleasure as such an outside-and-beyond, as something
necessary to induce action and in which it terminates.
Many harsh critics of utilitarianism have however
agreed that there is some end in which action terminates,
a final goal. They have denied that pleasure is
such an outside aim, and put perfection or self-realization
in its place. The entire popular notion of
"ideals" is infected with this conception of some fixed
end beyond activity at which we should aim. According
to this view ends-in-themselves come before aims.
<span class="pb" id="Pg224"></span>
We have a moral aim only as our purpose coincides
with some end-in-itself. We <em>ought</em> to aim at the latter
whether we actually do or not.</p>
<p>When men believed that fixed ends existed for all
normal changes in nature, the conception of similar
ends for men was but a special case of a general belief.
If the changes in a tree from acorn to full-grown oak
were regulated by an end which was somehow immanent
or potential in all the less perfect forms, and if change
was simply the effort to realize a perfect or complete
form, then the acceptance of a like view for human conduct
was consonant with the rest of what passed for
science. Such a view, consistent and systematic, was
foisted by Aristotle upon western culture and endured
for two thousand years. When the notion was expelled
from natural science by the intellectual revolution of
the seventeenth century, logically it should also have
disappeared from the theory of human action. But
man is not logical and his intellectual history is a record
of mental reserves and compromises. He hangs on
to what he can in his old beliefs even when he is compelled
to surrender their logical basis. So the doctrine
of fixed ends-in-themselves at which human acts are—or
should be—directed and by which they are regulated
if they are regulated at all persisted in morals, and was
made the cornerstone of orthodox moral theory. The
immediate effect was to dislocate moral from natural
science, to divide man's world as it never had been divided
in prior culture. One point of view, one method
and spirit animated inquiry into natural occurrences;
<span class="pb" id="Pg225"></span>
a radically opposite set of ideas prevailed about man's
affairs. Completion of the scientific change begun in
the seventeenth century thus depends upon a revision
of the current notion of ends of action as fixed limits
and conclusions.</p>
<p>In fact, ends are ends-in-view or aims. They arise
out of natural effects or consequences which in the
beginning are hit upon, stumbled upon so far as any
purpose is concerned. Men <em>like</em> some of the consequences
and <em>dislike</em> others. Henceforth (or till attraction
and repulsion alter) attaining or averting similar
consequences are aims or ends. These consequences
constitute the meaning and value of an activity as it
comes under deliberation. Meantime of course imagination
is busy. Old consequences are enhanced, recombined,
modified in imagination. Invention operates.
Actual consequences, that is effects which have happened
in the past, become possible future consequences
of acts still to be performed. This operation of imaginative
thought complicates the relation of ends to
activity, but it does not alter the substantial fact: Ends
are foreseen consequences which arise in the course of
activity and which are employed to give activity added
meaning and to direct its further course. They are in
no sense ends <em>of</em> action. In being ends of <em>deliberation</em>
they are redirecting pivots <em>in</em> action.</p>
<p>Men shoot and throw. At first this is done as an
"instinctive" or natural reaction to some situation.
The result when it is observed gives a new meaning to
the activity. Henceforth men in throwing and shooting
<span class="pb" id="Pg226"></span>
think of it in terms of its outcome; they act intelligently
or have an end. Liking the activity in its acquired
meaning, they not only "take aim" when they
throw instead of throwing at random, but they find or
make targets at which to aim. This is the origin and
nature of "goals" of action. They are ways of defining
and deepening the meaning of activity. Having
an end or aim is thus a characteristic of <em>present</em> activity.
It is the means by which an activity becomes
adapted when otherwise it would be blind and disorderly,
or by which it gets meaning when otherwise it
would be mechanical. In a strict sense an end-in-view
is a <em>means</em> in present action; present action is not a
means to a remote end. Men do not shoot because targets
exist, but they set up targets in order that throwing
and shooting may be more effective and significant.</p>
<p>A mariner does not sail towards the stars, but by
noting the stars he is aided in conducting his present
activity of sailing. A port or harbor is his objective,
but only in the sense of <em>reaching</em> it not of taking possession
of it. The harbor stands in his thought as a
significant point at which his activity will need re-direction.
Activity will not cease when the port is attained,
but merely the <em>present direction</em> of activity. The port
is as truly the beginning of another mode of activity as
it is the termination of the present one. The only
reason we ignore this fact is because it is empirically
taken for granted. We know without thinking that our
"ends" are perforce beginnings. But theories of ends
and ideals have converted a theoretical ignoring which
<span class="pb" id="Pg227"></span>
is equivalent to practical acknowledgment into an intellectual
denial, and have thereby confused and perverted
the nature of ends.</p>
<p>Even the most important among all the consequences
of an act is not necessarily its aim. Results which
are objectively most important may not even be thought
of at all; ordinarily a man does not think in connection
with exercise of his profession that it will sustain him
and his family in existence. The end-thought-of is
uniquely important, but it is indispensable to state the
respect in which it is important. It gives the decisive
clew to the act to be performed under the existing circumstances.
It is that particular foreseen object that
will stimulate the act which relieves existing troubles,
straightens out existing entanglements. In a temporary
annoyance, even if only that caused by the singing
of a mosquito, the thought of that which gives relief
may engross the mind in spite of consequences much
more important, objectively speaking. Moralists have
deplored such facts as evidence of levity. But the remedy,
if a remedy be needed, is not found in insisting
upon the importance of ends in general. It is found in
a change of the dispositions which make things either
immediately troublesome or tolerable or agreeable.</p>
<p>When ends are regarded as literally ends to action
rather than as directive stimuli to present choice they
are frozen and isolated. It makes no difference whether
the "end" is "natural" good like health or a "moral"
good like honesty. Set up as complete and exclusive,
as demanding and justifying action as a means to itself,
<span class="pb" id="Pg228"></span>
it leads to narrowness; in extreme cases fanaticism, inconsiderateness,
arrogance and hypocrisy. Joshua's
reputed success in getting the sun to stand still to serve
his desire is recognized to have involved a miracle. But
moral theorists constantly assume that the continuous
course of events can be arrested at the point of a particular
object; that men can plunge with their own
desires into the unceasing flow of changes, and
seize upon some object as their end irrespective of
everything else. The use of intelligence to discover the
object that will best operate as a releasing and unifying
stimulus in the existing situation is discounted. One
reminds one's self that one's end is justice or charity
or professional achievement or putting over a deal for
a needed public improvement, and further questionings
and qualms are stilled.</p>
<p>It is customary to suppose that such methods merely
ignore the question of the morality of the means which
are used to secure the end desired. Common sense revolts
against the maxim, conveniently laid off upon
Jesuits or other far-away people, that the end justifies
the means. There is no incorrectness in saying that the
question of means employed is overlooked in such cases.
But analysis would go further if it were also pointed
out that overlooking means is only a device for failing
to note those ends, or consequences, which, if they were
noted would be seen to be so evil that action would be
estopped. Certainly nothing can justify or condemn
means except ends, results. But we have to include
consequences impartially. Even admitting that lying
<span class="pb" id="Pg229"></span>
will save a man's soul, whatever that may mean, it
would still be true that lying will have other consequences,
namely, the usual consequences that follow
from tampering with good faith and that lead lying to
be condemned. It is wilful folly to fasten upon some
single end or consequence which is liked, and permit
the view of that to blot from perception all other undesired
and undesirable consequences. It is like supposing
that when a finger held close to the eye covers
up a distant mountain the finger is really larger than
the mountain. Not <em>the</em> end—in the singular—justifies
the means; for there is no such thing as the single all-important
end. To suppose that there is such an end
is like working over again, in behalf of our private
wishes, the miracle of Joshua in arresting the course of
nature. It is not possible adequately to characterize
the presumption, the falsity and the deliberate perversion
of intelligence involved in refusal to note the plural
effects that flow from any act, a refusal adopted in
order that we may justify an act by picking out that
one consequence which will enable us to do what we wish
to do and for which we feel the need of justification.</p>
<p>Yet this assumption is continually made. It is made
by implication in the current view of purposes or ends-in-view
as objects in themselves, instead of means to
unification and liberation of present conflicting, confused
habits and impulses. There is something almost
sinister in the desire to label the doctrine that the end
justifies the means with the name of some one obnoxious
school. Politicians, especially if they have to do with
<span class="pb" id="Pg230"></span>
the foreign affairs of a nation and are called statesmen,
almost uniformly act upon the doctrine that the
welfare of their own country justifies any measure irrespective
of all the demoralization it works. Captains
of industry, great executives in all lines, usually work
upon this plan. But they are not the original offenders
by any means. Every man works upon it so far as he
permits himself to become so absorbed in one aspect of
what he is doing that he loses a view of its varied consequences,
hypnotizing his attention by consideration
of just those consequences which in the abstract are
desirable and slurring over other consequences equally
real. Every man works upon this principle who becomes
over-interested in any cause or project, and who
uses its desirability in the abstract to justify himself
in employing any means that will assist him in arriving,
ignoring all the collateral "ends" of his behavior. It
is frequently pointed out that there is a type of executive-man
whose conduct seems to be as non-moral as
the action of the forces of nature. We all tend to
relapse into this non-moral condition whenever we want
any one thing intensely. In general, the identification
of the end prominent in conscious desire and effort with
<em>the</em> end is part of the technique of avoiding a reasonable
survey of consequences. The survey is avoided
because of a subconscious recognition that it would reveal
desire in its true worth and thus preclude action to
satisfy it—or at all events give us an uneasy conscience
in striving to realize it. Thus the doctrine of the isolated,
complete or fixed end limits intelligent examination,
<span class="pb" id="Pg231"></span>
encourages insincerity, and puts a pseudo-stamp
of moral justification upon success at any price.</p>
<p>Moralistic persons are given to escaping this evil
by falling into another pit. They deny that consequences
have anything at all to do with the morality
of acts. Not ends but motives they say justify or condemn
acts. The thing to do, accordingly, is to cultivate
certain motives or dispositions, benevolence, purity,
love of perfection, loyalty. The denial of consequences
thus turns out formal, verbal. In reality a
consequence is set up at which to aim, only it is a subjective
consequence. "Meaning well" is selected as <em>the</em>
consequence or end to be cultivated at all hazards, an
end which is all-justifying and to which everything else
is offered up in sacrifice. The result is a sentimental
futile complacency rather than the brutal efficiency of
the executive. But the root of both evils is the same.
One man selects some external consequence, the other
man a state of internal feeling, to serve as the end. The
doctrine of meaning well as <em>the</em> end is if anything the
more contemptible of the two, for it shrinks from accepting
any responsibility for actual results. It is negative,
self-protective and sloppy. It lends itself to complete
self-deception.</p>
<p>Why have men become so attached to fixed, external
ends? Why is it not universally recognized that an end
is a device of intelligence in guiding action, instrumental
to freeing and harmonizing troubled and divided tendencies?
The answer is virtually contained in what was
earlier said about rigid habits and their effect upon intelligence.
<span class="pb" id="Pg232"></span>
Ends are, in fact, literally endless, forever
coming into existence as new activities occasion new
consequences. "Endless ends" is a way of saying that
there are no ends—that is no fixed self-enclosed finalities.
While however we cannot actually prevent change
from occurring we can and do regard it as evil. We
strive to retain action in ditches already dug. We regard
novelties as dangerous, experiments as illicit and
deviations as forbidden. Fixed and separate ends reflect
a projection of our own fixed and non-interacting
compartmental habits. We see only consequences which
correspond to our habitual courses. As we have said,
men did not begin to shoot because there were ready-made
targets to aim at. They made things into targets
by shooting at them, and then made special targets to
make shooting more significantly interesting. But if
generation after generation were shown targets they
had had no part in constructing, if bows and arrows
were thrust into their hands, and pressure were brought
to bear upon them to keep them shooting in season and
out, some wearied soul would soon propound to willing
listeners the theory that shooting was unnatural, that
man was naturally wholly at rest, and that targets existed
in order that men might be forced to be active;
that the duty of shooting and the virtue of hitting are
externally imposed and fostered, and that otherwise
there would be no such thing as a shooting-activity—that
is, morality.</p>
<p>The doctrine of fixed ends not only diverts attention
from examination of consequences and the intelligent
<span class="pb" id="Pg233"></span>
creation of purpose, but, since means and ends are two
ways of regarding the same actuality, it also renders
men careless in their inspection of existing conditions.
An aim not framed on the basis of a survey of those
present conditions which are to be employed as means
of its realization simply throws us back upon past habits.
We then do not do what we intended to do but
what we have got used to doing, or else we thrash about
in a blind ineffectual way. The result is failure. Discouragement
follows, assuaged perhaps by the thought
that in any case the end is too ideal, too noble and
remote, to be capable of realization. We fall back on
the consoling thought that our moral ideals are too
good for this world and that we must accustom ourselves
to a gap between aim and execution. Actual
life is then thought of as a compromise with the best,
an enforced second or third best, a dreary exile from
our true home in the ideal, or a temporary period of
troubled probation to be followed by a period of unending
attainment and peace. At the same time, as has
been repeatedly pointed out, persons of a more practical
turn of mind accept the world "as it is," that is as
past customs have made it to be, and consider what
advantages for themselves may be extracted from it.
They form aims on the basis of existing habits of life
which may be turned to their own private account.
They employ intelligence in framing ends and selecting
and arranging means. But intelligence is confined to
manipulation; it does not extend to construction. It is
the intelligence of the politician, administrator and professional
<span class="pb" id="Pg234"></span>
executive—the kind of intelligence which has
given a bad meaning to a word that ought to have a fine
meaning, opportunism. For the highest task of intelligence
is to grasp and realize genuine opportunity,
possibility.</p>
<p>Roughly speaking, the course of forming aims is as
follows. The beginning is with a wish, an emotional
reaction against the present state of things and a hope
for something different. Action fails to connect satisfactorily
with surrounding conditions. Thrown back
upon itself, it projects itself in an imagination of a
scene which if it were present would afford satisfaction.
This picture is often called an aim, more often an ideal.
But in itself it is a fancy which may be only a <ins class="corr" title="phantasy" id="Corr_234_">fantasy</ins>,
a dream, a castle in the air. In itself it is a romantic
embellishment of the present; at its best it is
material for poetry or the novel. Its natural home is
not in the future but in the dim past or in some distant
and supposedly better part of the present world. Every
such idealized object is suggested by something actually
experienced, as the flight of birds suggests the liberation
of human beings from the restrictions of slow
locomotion on dull earth. It becomes an aim or end
only when it is worked out in terms of concrete conditions
available for its realization, that is in terms of
"means."</p>
<p>This transformation depends upon study of the conditions
which generate or make possible the fact observed
to exist already. The fancy of the delight of
moving at will through the air became an actuality
<span class="pb" id="Pg235"></span>
only after men carefully studied the way in which a bird
although heavier than air actually sustains itself in
air. A fancy becomes an aim, in short, when some past
sequence of known cause-and-effect is projected into the
future, and when by assembling its causal conditions
we strive to generate a like result. We have to fall back
upon what has already happened naturally without design,
and study it to see <em>how</em> it happened, which is what
is meant by causation. This knowledge joined to wish
creates a purpose. Many men have doubtless dreamed
of ability to have light in darkness without the trouble
of oil, lamps and friction. Glow-worms, lightning, the
sparks of cut electric conductors suggest such a possibility.
But the picture remained a dream until an
Edison studied all that could be found out about such
casual phenomena of light, and then set to work to
search out and gather together the means for reproducing
their operation. The great trouble with what
passes for moral ends and ideals is that they do not
get beyond the stage of fancy of something agreeable
and desirable based upon an emotional wish; very often,
at that, not even an original wish, but the wish of some
leader which has been conventionalized and transmitted
through channels of authority. Every gain in natural
science makes possible new aims. That is, the discovery
of how things <em>do</em> occur makes it possible to conceive
of their happening at will, and gives us a start on selecting
and combining the conditions, the means, to
command their happening. In technical matters, this
lesson has been fairly well learned. But in moral matters,
<span class="pb" id="Pg236"></span>
men still largely neglect the need of studying the
way in which results similar to those which we desire
actually happen. Mechanism is despised as of importance
only in low material things. The consequent
divorce of moral ends from scientific study of natural
events renders the former impotent wishes, compensatory
dreams in consciousness. In <em>fact</em> ends or
consequences are still determined by fixed habit and
the force of circumstance. The evils of idle dreaming
and of routine are experienced in conjunction.
"Idealism" must indeed come first—the imagination of
some better state generated by desire. But unless ideals
are to be dreams and idealism a synonym for romanticism
and <ins class="corr" title="phantasy-building" id="Corr_236_">fantasy-building</ins>, there must be a most
realistic study of actual conditions and of the mode or
law of natural events, in order to give the imagined or
ideal object definite form and solid substance—to give
it, in short, practicality and constitute it a working
end.</p>
<p>The acceptance of fixed ends in themselves is an
aspect of man's devotion to an ideal of certainty. This
affection was inevitably cherished as long as men believed
that the highest things in physical nature are at
rest, and that science is possible only by grasping immutable
forms and species: in other words, for much
the greater part of the intellectual history of mankind.
Only reckless sceptics would have dared entertain any
idea of ends except as fixed in themselves as long
as the whole structure of science was erected upon the
immobile. Behind however the conception of fixity
<span class="pb" id="Pg237"></span>
whether in science or morals lay adherence to certainty
of "truth," a clinging to something fixed, born of fear
of the new and of attachment to possessions. When
the classicist condemns concession to impulse and holds
up to admiration the patterns tested in tradition, he
little suspects how much he is himself affected by unavowed
impulses—timidity which makes him cling to
authority, conceit which moves him to be himself the
authority who speaks in the name of authority,
possessive impulse which fears to risk acquisition in
new adventures. Love of certainty is a demand for
guarantees in advance of action. Ignoring the fact
that truth can be bought only by the adventure of
experiment, dogmatism turns truth into an insurance
company. Fixed ends upon one side and fixed "principles"—that
is authoritative rules—on the other, are
props for a feeling of safety, the refuge of the timid
and the means by which the bold prey upon the timid.</p>
<hr />
<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg238"></span>VII</h3>
<p>Intelligence is concerned with foreseeing the future
so that action may have order and direction. It is also
concerned with principles and criteria of judgment.
The diffused or wide applicability of habits is reflected
in the <em>general</em> character of principles: a principle is
intellectually what a habit is for direct action. As
habits set in grooves dominate activity and swerve it
from conditions instead of increasing its adaptability,
so principles treated as fixed rules instead of as helpful
methods take men away from experience. The more
complicated the situation, and the less we really know
about it, the more insistent is the orthodox type of
moral theory upon the prior existence of some fixed
and universal principle or law which is to be directly
applied and followed. Ready-made rules available at
a moment's notice for settling any kind of moral difficulty
and resolving every species of moral doubt have
been the chief object of the ambition of moralists. In
the much less complicated and less changing matters of
bodily health such pretensions are known as quackery.
But in morals a hankering for certainty, born of timidity
and nourished by love of authoritative prestige,
has led to the idea that absence of immutably fixed and
universally applicable ready-made principles is equivalent
to moral chaos.</p>
<p><span class="pb" id="Pg239"></span>
In fact, situations into which change and the unexpected
enter are a challenge to intelligence to create
new principles. Morals must be a growing science if
it is to be a science at all, not merely because all truth
has not yet been appropriated by the mind of man, but
because life is a moving affair in which old moral truth
ceases to apply. Principles are methods of inquiry and
forecast which require verification by the event; and the
time honored effort to assimilate morals to mathematics
is only a way of bolstering up an old dogmatic authority,
or putting a new one upon the throne of the old.
But the experimental character of moral judgments
does not mean complete uncertainty and fluidity. Principles
exist as hypotheses with which to experiment.
Human history is long. There is a long record of past
experimentation in conduct, and there are cumulative
verifications which give many principles a well earned
prestige. Lightly to disregard them is the height of
foolishness. But social situations alter; and it is also
foolish not to observe how old principles actually work
under new conditions, and not to modify them so that
they will be more effectual instruments in judging new
cases. Many men are now aware of the harm done in
legal matters by assuming the antecedent existence of
fixed principles under which every new case may be
brought. They recognize that this assumption merely
puts an artificial premium on ideas developed under bygone
conditions, and that their perpetuation in the
present works inequity. Yet the choice is not between
throwing away rules previously developed and sticking
<span class="pb" id="Pg240"></span>
obstinately by them. The intelligent alternative is to
revise, adapt, expand and alter them. The problem is
one of continuous, vital readaptation.</p>
<p>The popular objection to casuistry is similar to the
popular objection to the maxim that the end justifies
the means. It is creditable to practical moral sense,
but not to popular logical consistency. For recourse
to casuistry is the only conclusion which can be drawn
from belief in fixed universal principles, just as the
Jesuit maxim is the only conclusion proper to be drawn
from belief in fixed ends. Every act, every deed is individual.
What is the sense in having fixed general
rules, commandments, laws, unless they are such as to
confer upon individual cases of action (where alone instruction
is finally needed) something of their own infallible
certainty? Casuistry, so-called, is simply the
systematic effort to secure for particular instances of
conduct the advantage of general rules which are asserted
and believed in. By those who accept the notion
of immutable regulating principles, casuistry ought to
be lauded for sincerity and helpfulness, not dispraised
as it usually is. Or else men ought to carry back their
aversion to manipulation of particular cases, until they
will fit into the procrustean beds of fixed rules, to the
point where it is clear that all principles are empirical
generalizations from the ways in which previous judgments
of conduct have practically worked out. When
this fact is apparent, these generalizations will be seen
to be not fixed rules for deciding doubtful cases, but
instrumentalities for their investigation, methods by
<span class="pb" id="Pg241"></span>
which the net value of past experience is rendered available
for present scrutiny of new perplexities. Then it
will also follow that they are hypotheses to be tested
and revised by their further working.<SPAN name="FNanchor_8_" id="FNanchor_8_" href="#Footnote_8_" title="Among contemporary moralists, Mr. G. E. Moore may be cited as almost alone in having the courage of the convictions shared by many. He insists that it is the true business of moral theory to enable men to arrive at precise and sure judgments in concrete cases of moral perplexity." class="fnanchor">[8]</SPAN></p>
<p>Every such statement meets with prompt objection.
We are told that in deliberation rival goods present
themselves. We are faced by competing desires and
ends which are incompatible with one another. They
are all attractive, seductive. How then shall we choose
among them? We can choose rationally among values,
the argument continues, only if we have some fixed
measure of values, just as we decide the respective
lengths of physical things by recourse to the fixed foot-rule.
One might reply that after all there is no fixed
foot-rule, no fixed foot "in itself" and that the standard
length or weight of measure is only another special
portion of matter, subject to change from heat, moisture
and gravitational position, defined only by conditions,
relations. One might reply that the foot-rule is
a tool which has been worked out in actual prior comparisons
of concrete things for use in facilitating further
comparisons. But we content ourselves with remarking
that we find in this conception of a fixed antecedent
standard another manifestation of the desire to
escape the strain of the actual moral situation, its
genuine uncertainty of possibilities and consequences.
<span class="pb" id="Pg242"></span>
We are confronted with another case of the all too
human love of certainty, a case of the wish for an intellectual
patent issued by authority. The issue after all
is one of fact. The critic is not entitled to enforce
against the facts his private wish for a ready-made
standard which will relieve him from the burden of examination,
observation and continuing generalization
and test.</p>
<p>The worth of this private wish is moreover open to
question in the light of the history of the development
of natural science. There was a time when in astronomy,
chemistry and biology men claimed that judgment
of individual phenomena was possible only because the
mind was already in possession of fixed truths, universal
principles, pre-ordained axioms. Only by their
means could contingent, varying particular events be
truly known. There was, it was argued, no way to
judge the truth of any particular statement about a
particular plant, heavenly body, or case of combustion
unless there was a general truth already in hand with
which to compare a particular empirical occurrence.
The contention was successful, that is for a long time
it maintained its hold upon men's minds. But its effect
was merely to encourage intellectual laziness, reliance
upon authority and blind acceptance of conceptions
that had somehow become traditional. The actual
advance of science did not begin till men broke
away from this method. When men insisted upon judging
astronomical phenomena by bringing them directly
under established truths, those of geometry, they had
<span class="pb" id="Pg243"></span>
no astronomy, but only a private esthetic construction.
Astronomy began when men trusted themselves to embarking
upon the uncertain sea of events and were willing
to be instructed by changes in the concrete. Then
antecedent principles were tentatively employed as
methods for conducting observations and experiments,
and for organizing special facts: as hypotheses.</p>
<p>In morals now, as in physical science then, the work
of intelligence in reaching such relative certainty, or
tested probability, as is open to man is retarded by the
false notion of fixed antecedent truths. Prejudice is
confirmed. Rules formed accidentally or under the
pressure of conditions long past, are protected from
criticism and thus perpetuated. Every group and person
vested with authority strengthens possessed power
by harping upon the sacredness of immutable principle.
Moral facts, that is the concrete careers of special
courses of action, are not studied. There is no counterpart
to clinical medicine. Rigid classifications forced
upon facts are relied upon. And all is done, as it used
to be done in natural science, in praise of Reason and
in fear of the variety and fluctuation of actual
happenings.</p>
<p>The hypothesis that each moral situation is unique
and that consequently general moral principles are instrumental
to developing the individualized meaning of
situations is declared to be anarchic. It is said to be
ethical atomism, pulverizing the order and dignity of
morals. The question, again is not what our inherited
habits lead us to prefer, but where the facts take us.
<span class="pb" id="Pg244"></span>
But in this instance the facts do not take us into atomism
and anarchy. These things are specters seen by the
critic when he is suddenly confused by the loss of customary
spectacles. He takes his own confusion due to
loss of artificial aids for an objective situation. <em>Because</em>
situations in which deliberation is evoked are new,
and therefore unique, general principles are needed.
Only an uncritical vagueness will assume that the sole
alternative to fixed generality is absence of continuity.
Rigid habits insist upon duplication, repetition, recurrence;
in their case there is accordingly fixed principles.
Only there is no <em>principle</em> at all, that is, no conscious
intellectual rule, for thought is not needed. But all
habit has <em>continuity</em>, and while a flexible habit does not
secure in its operation bare recurrence nor absolute assurance
neither does it plunge us into the hopeless confusion
of the absolutely different. To insist upon
change and the new is to insist upon alteration <em>of</em> the
old. In denying that the meaning of any genuine case
of deliberation can be exhausted by treating it as a
mere case of an established classification the value of
classification is not denied. It is shown where its value
lies, namely, in directing attention to resemblances and
differences in the new case, in economizing effort in foresight.
To call a generalization a tool is not to say it is
useless; the contrary is patently the case. A tool is
something to use. Hence it is also something to be improved
by noting how it works. The need of such noting
and improving is indispensable if, as is the case with
moral principles, the tool has to be used in unwonted
<span class="pb" id="Pg245"></span>
circumstances. Continuity of growth not atomism is
thus the alternative to fixity of principles and aims.
This is no Bergsonian plea for dividing the universe
into two portions, one all of fixed, recurrent habits, and
the other all spontaneity of flux. Only in such a universe
would reason in morals have to take its choice between
absolute fixity and absolute looseness.</p>
<p>Nothing is more instructive about the genuine value
of generalization in conduct than the errors of Kant.
He took the doctrine that the essence of reason is complete
universality (and hence necessity and immutability),
with the seriousness becoming the professor of
logic. Applying the doctrine to morality he saw that
this conception severed morals from connection with
experience. Other moralists had gone that far before
his day. But none of them had done what Kant proceeded
to do: carry this separation of moral principles
and ideals from experience to its logical conclusion.
He saw that to exclude from principles all
connection with empirical details meant to exclude
all reference of any kind to consequences.
He then saw with a clearness which does his
logic credit that with such exclusion, reason becomes
entirely empty: nothing is left except the universality
of the universal. He was then confronted by the seemingly
insoluble problem of getting moral instruction regarding
special cases out of a principle that having
forsworn intercourse with experience was barren and
empty. His ingenious method was as follows. Formal
universality means at least logical identity; it means
<span class="pb" id="Pg246"></span>
self-consistency or absence of contradiction. Hence
follows the method by which a would-be truly moral
agent will proceed in judging the rightness of any proposed
act. He will ask: Can its motive be made universal
for all cases? How would one like it if by one's
act one's motive in that act were to be erected into a
universal law of actual nature? Would one then be
willing to make the same choice?</p>
<p>Surely a man would hesitate to steal if by his choice
to make stealing the motive of his act he were also to
erect it into such a fixed law of nature that henceforth
he and everybody else would always steal whenever
property was in question. No stealing without property,
and with universal stealing also no property; a
clear self-contradiction. Looked at in the light of
reason every mean, insincere, inconsiderate motive of
action shrivels into a private exception which a person
wants to take advantage of in his own favor, and which
he would be horrified to have others act upon. It violates
the great principle of logic that A is A. Kindly,
decent acts, on the contrary, extend and multiply
themselves in a continuing harmony.</p>
<p>This treatment by Kant evinces deep insight into
the office of intelligence and principle in conduct. But
it involves flat contradiction of Kant's own original
intention to exclude consideration of concrete consequences.
It turns out to be a method of recommending
a broad impartial view of consequences. Our forecast
of consequences is always subject, as we have noted, to
the bias of impulse and habit. We see what we want to
<span class="pb" id="Pg247"></span>
see, we obscure what is unfavorable to a cherished, probably
unavowed, wish. We dwell upon favoring circumstances
till they become weighted with reinforcing considerations.
We don't give opposing consequences half
a chance to develop in thought. Deliberation needs
every possible help it can get against the twisting, exaggerating
and slighting tendency of passion and habit.
To form the habit of asking how we should be willing
to be treated in a similar case—which is what Kant's
maxim amounts to—is to gain an ally for impartial and
sincere deliberation and judgment. It is a safeguard
against our tendency to regard our own case as exceptional
in comparison with the case of others. "Just
this once," a plea for isolation; secrecy—a plea for
non-inspection, are forces which operate in every passionate
desire. Demand for consistency, for "universality,"
far from implying a rejection of all consequences,
is a demand to survey consequences broadly,
to link effect to effect in a chain of continuity. Whatever
force works to this end <em>is</em> reason. For reason, let
it be repeated is an outcome, a function, not a primitive
force. What we need are those habits, dispositions
which lead to impartial and consistent foresight of consequences.
Then our judgments are reasonable; we are
then reasonable creatures.</p>
<hr />
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />