<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg265"></span>IX</h3>
<p>Over and over again, one point has recurred for criticism;—the
subordination of activity to a result outside
itself. Whether that goal be thought of as pleasure, as
virtue, as perfection, as final enjoyment of salvation,
is secondary to the fact that the moralists who
have asserted fixed ends have in all their differences
from one another agreed in the basic idea that present
activity is but a means. We have insisted that happiness,
reasonableness, virtue, perfecting, are on the
contrary parts of the present significance of present
action. Memory of the past, observation of the present,
foresight of the future are indispensable. But they
are indispensable <em>to</em> a present liberation, an enriching
growth of action. Happiness is fundamental in morals
only because happiness is not something to be sought
for, but is something now attained, even in the midst of
pain and trouble, whenever recognition of our ties with
nature and with fellow-men releases and informs our
action. Reasonableness is a necessity because it is the
perception of the continuities that take action out of
its immediateness and isolation into connection with
the past and future.</p>
<p>Perhaps the criticism and insistence have been too
incessant. They may have provoked the reader to reaction.
He may readily concede that orthodox theories
<span class="pb" id="Pg266"></span>
have been onesided in sacrificing the present to
future good, making of the present but an onerous
obligation or a sacrifice endured for future gain. But
why, he may protest, go to an opposite extreme and
make the future but a means to the significance of the
present? Why should the power of foresight and effort
to shape the future, to regulate what is to happen, be
slighted? Is not the effect of such a doctrine to weaken
putting forth of endeavor in order to make the future
better than the present? Control of the future may be
limited in extent, but it is correspondingly precious;
we should jealously cherish whatever encourages and
sustains effort to that end. To make little of this possibility,
in effect, it will be argued, is to decrease the
care and endeavor upon which progress depends.</p>
<p>Control of the future is indeed precious in exact
proportion to its difficulty, its moderate degree of attainability.
Anything that actually tends to make that
control less than it now is would be a movement backward
into sloth and triviality. But there is a difference
between future improvement as a result and as a
direct aim. To make it an aim is to throw away the
surest means of attaining it, namely attention to the
full use of present resources in the present situation.
Forecast of future conditions, scientific study of past
and present in order that the forecast may be intelligent,
are indeed necessities. Concentration of intellectual
concern upon the future, solicitude for scope and
precision of estimate characteristic of any well conducted
affair, naturally give the impression that their
<span class="pb" id="Pg267"></span>
animating purpose is control of the future. But
thought about future happenings is the only way we
can judge the present; it is the only way to appraise
its significance. Without such projection, there can be
no projects, no plans for administering present energies,
overcoming present obstacles. Deliberately to
subordinate the present to the future is to subject the
comparatively secure to the precarious, exchange resources
for liabilities, surrender what is under control
to what is, relatively, incapable of control.</p>
<p>The <em>amount</em> of control which will come into existence
in the future is not within control. But such
an amount as turns out to be practicable accrues only
in consequence of the best possible management of
present means and obstacles. Dominating <em>intellectual</em>
pre-occupation with the future is the way by which
efficiency in dealing with the present is attained. It is
a way, not a goal. And, upon the very most hopeful
outlook, study and planning are more important in the
meaning, the enrichment of content, which they add to
present activity than is the increase of external control
they effect. Nor is this doctrine passivistic in
tendency. What sense is there in increased external
control except to increase the intrinsic significance of
living? The future that is foreseen is a future that is
sometime to be a present. Is the value of <em>that</em> present
also to be postponed to a future date, and so on indefinitely?
Or, if the good we are struggling to attain in
the future is one to be actually realized when that future
becomes present, why should not the good of <em>this</em>
<span class="pb" id="Pg268"></span>
present be equally precious? And is there, again, any
intelligent way of modifying the future except to attend
to the full possibilities of the present? Scamping
the present in behalf of the future leads only to rendering
the future less manageable. It increases the probability
of molestation by future events.</p>
<p>Remarks cast in this form probably seem too much
like a logical manipulation of the concepts of present
and future to be convincing. Building a house is a
typical instance of an intelligent activity. It is an
activity directed by a plan, a design. The plan is
itself based upon a foresight of future uses. This foresight
is in turn dependent upon an organized survey
of past experiences and of present conditions, a recollection
of former experiences of living in houses and an
acquaintance with present materials, prices, resources,
etc. Now if a legitimate case of subordination of present
to regulation of the future may anywhere be found,
it is in such a case as this. For a man usually builds
a house for the sake of the comfort and security, the
"control," thereby afforded to future living rather than
just for the fun—or the trouble—of building. If in
such a case inspection shows that, after all, intellectual
concern with the past and future is for the sake of
directing present activity and giving it meaning, the
conclusion may be accepted for other cases.</p>
<p>Note that the present activity is the only one really
under control. The man may die before the house is
built, or his financial conditions may change, or he may
need to remove to another place. If he attempts to
<span class="pb" id="Pg269"></span>
provide for all contingencies, he will never do anything;
if he allows his attention to be much distracted by them,
he won't do well his present planning and execution.
The more he considers the future uses to which the house
will probably be put the better he will do his present
job which is the activity of building. Control of future
living, such as it may turn out to be, is wholly
dependent upon taking his present activity, seriously
and devotedly, as an end, not a means. And a man has
his hands full in doing well what now needs to be done.
Until men have formed the habit of using intelligence
fully as a guide to present action they will never find
out how much control of future contingencies is possible.
As things are, men so habitually scamp present
action in behalf of future "ends" that the facts for
estimating the extent of the possibility of reduction of
future contingencies have not been disclosed. What a
man <em>is</em> doing limits both his direct control and his responsibility.
We must not confuse the act of building
with the house when built. The latter <em>is</em> a means, not
a fulfilment. But it is such only because it enters into
a new activity which is present not future. Life is continuous.
The act of building in time gives way to the
acts connected with a domicile. But everywhere the
good, the fulfilment, the meaning of activity, resides in
a present made possible by judging existing conditions
in their connections.</p>
<p>If we seek for an illustration on a larger scale, education
furnishes us with a poignant example. As traditionally
conducted, it strikingly exhibits a subordination
<span class="pb" id="Pg270"></span>
of the living present to a remote and precarious
future. To prepare, to get ready, is its key-note. The
actual outcome is lack of adequate preparation, of intelligent
adaptation. The professed exaltation of the
future turns out in practice a blind following of tradition,
a rule of thumb muddling along from day to
day; or, as in some of the projects called industrial
education, a determined effort on the part of one class
of the community to secure <em>its</em> future at the expense
of another class. If education were conducted as a
process of fullest utilization of present resources, liberating
and guiding capacities that are now urgent, it
goes without saying that the lives of the young would
be much richer in meaning than they are now. It also
follows that intelligence would be kept busy in studying
all indications of power, all obstacles and perversions,
all products of the past that throw light upon present
capacity, and in forecasting the future career of impulse
and habit now active—not for the sake of subordinating
the latter but in order to treat them intelligently.
As a consequence whatever fortification
and expansion of the future that is possible will be
achieved—as it is now dismally unattained.</p>
<p>A more complicated instance is found in the dominant
quality of our industrial activity. It may be dogmatically
declared that the roots of its evils are found
in the separation of production from consumption—that
is, actual consummation, fulfilment. A normal
case of their relationship is found in the taking of
food. Food is consumed and vigor is produced. The
<span class="pb" id="Pg271"></span>
difference between the two is one of directions or dimensions
distinguished by intellect. In reality there is
simply conversion of energy from one form to another
wherein it is more available—of greater significance.
The activity of the artist, the sportsman, the scientific
inquirer exemplifies the same balance. Activity should
be productive. This is to say it should have a bearing
on the future, should effect control of it. But so far as
a productive action is intrinsically creative, it has its
own intrinsic value. Reference to future products and
future enjoyments is but a way of enhancing perception
of an immanent meaning. A skilled artisan who
enjoys his work is aware that what he is making is made
for future use. Externally his action is one technically
labeled "production." It seems to illustrate the subjection
of present activity to remote ends. But actually,
morally, psychologically, the sense of the utility
of the article produced is a factor in the present significance
of action due to the present utilization of
abilities, giving play to taste and skill, accomplishing
something now. The moment production is severed
from immediate satisfaction, it becomes "labor,"
drudgery, a task reluctantly performed.</p>
<p>Yet the whole tendency of modern economic life has
been to assume that consumption will take care of itself
provided only production is grossly and intensely attended
to. Making things is frantically accelerated;
and every mechanical device used to swell the senseless
bulk. As a result most workers find no replenishment,
no renewal and growth of mind, no fulfilment in work.
<span class="pb" id="Pg272"></span>
They labor to get mere means of later satisfaction.
This when procured is isolated in turn from production
and is reduced to a barren physical affair or a sensuous
compensation for normal goods denied. Meantime the
fatuity of severing production from consumption, from
present enriching of life, is made evident by economic
crises, by periods of unemployment alternating with
periods of exercise, work or "over-production." Production
apart from fulfilment becomes purely a matter
of quantity; for distinction, quality, is a matter of present
meaning. Esthetic elements being excluded, the
mechanical reign. Production lacks criteria; one thing
is better than another if it can be made faster or in
greater mass. Leisure is not the nourishment of mind
in work, nor a recreation; it is a feverish hurry for
diversion, excitement, display, otherwise there is no
leisure except a sodden torpor. Fatigue due for some
to monotony and for others to overstrain in maintaining
the pace is inevitable. Socially, the separation
of production and consumption, means and ends, is the
root of the most profound division of classes. Those
who fix the "ends" for production are in control, those
who engage in isolated productive activity are the subject-class.
But if the latter are oppressed the former
are not truly free. Their consumptions are accidental
ostentation and extravagance, not a normal consummation
or fulfilment of activity. The remainder of
their lives is spent in enslavement to keeping the machinery
going at an increasingly rapid rate.</p>
<p>Meantime class struggle grows between those whose
<span class="pb" id="Pg273"></span>
productive labor is enforced by necessity and those who
are privileged consumers. And the exaggeration of
production due to its isolation from ignored consumption
so hypnotizes attention that even would-be reformers,
like Marxian socialists, assert that the entire
social problem focuses at the point of production.
Since this separation of means from ends signifies an
erection of means into ends, it is no wonder that a
"materialistic conception of history" emerges. It is
not an invention of Marx; it is a record of fact so far
as the separation in question obtains. For practicable
idealism is found only in a fulfilment, a consumption
which is a replenishing, growth, renewal of mind and
body. Harmony of social interests is found in the
wide-spread sharing of activities significant in themselves,
that is to say, at the point of <em>consumption</em>.<SPAN name="FNanchor_9_" id="FNanchor_9_" href="#Footnote_9_" title="Acknowledgment is due 'The Social Interpretation of History' by Maurice Williams." class="fnanchor">[9]</SPAN> But
the forcing of production apart from consumption leads
to the monstrous belief that class-struggle civil war is
a means of social progress, instead of a register of the
barriers to its attainment. Yet here too the Marxian
reads aright the character of most current economic
activity.</p>
<p>The history of economic activity thus exemplifies the
moral consequences of the separation of present activity
and future "ends" from each other. It also embodies
the difficulty of the problem—the tax placed by
it upon thought and good will. For the professed idealist
and the hard-headed materialist or "practical"
man, have conspired together to sustain this situation.
<span class="pb" id="Pg274"></span>
The "idealist" sets up as the ideal not fullness of
meaning of the present but a remote goal. Hence the
present is evacuated of meaning. It is reduced to being
a mere external instrument, an evil necessity due to the
distance between us and significant valid satisfaction.
Appreciation, joy, peace in present activity are suspect.
They are regarded as diversions, temptations,
unworthy relaxations. Then since human nature <em>must</em>
have present realization, a sentimental, romantic enjoyment
of the ideal becomes a substitute for intelligent
and rewarding activity. The utopia cannot be
realized in fact but it may be appropriated in fantasy
and serve as an anodyne to blunt the sense of a misery
which after all endures. Some private key to a present
entering upon remote and superior bliss is sought, just
as the evangelical enjoys a complacent and superior
sense of a salvation unobtained by fellow mortals. Thus
the normal demand for realization, for satisfaction in
the present, is abnormally met.</p>
<p>Meantime the practical man wants something definite,
tangible and presumably obtainable for which to
work. He is looking after "a good thing" as the average
man is looking after a "good time," that natural
caricature of an intrinsically significant activity. Yet
his activity is impractical. He is looking for satisfaction
somewhere else than where it can be found. In his
utopian search for a future good he neglects the only
place where good can be found. He empties present
activity of meaning by making it a mere instrumentality.
When the future arrives it is only after all another
<span class="pb" id="Pg275"></span>
despised present. By habit as well as by definition it
is still a means to something which has yet to come.
Again human nature must have its claims satisfied, and
sensuality is the inevitable recourse. Usually a compromise
is worked out, by which a man for his working-hours
accepts the philosophy of activity for some future
result, while at odd leisure times he enters by conventionally
recognized channels upon an enjoyment of
"spiritual" blessings and "ideal" refinements. The
problem of serving God and Mammon is thus solved.
The situation exemplifies the concrete meaning of the
separation of means from ends which is the intellectual
reflex of the divorce of theory and practice, intelligence
and habit, foresight and present impulse. Moralists
have spent time and energy in showing what happens
when appetite, impulse, is indulged without reference to
consequences and reason. But they have mostly ignored
the counterpart evils of an intelligence that conceives
ideals and goods which do not enter into present impulse
and habit. The life of reason has been specialized,
romanticized, or made a heavy burden. This situation
embodies the import of the problem of actualizing the
place of intelligence in conduct.</p>
<p>Our whole account of the place of intelligence in conduct
is exposed however to the charge of being itself
romantic, a compensatory idealization. The history of
mind is a record of intellect which registers, with more
or less inaccuracy, what has happened after it has happened.
The crisis in which the intervention of foreseeing
and directing mind is needed passes unnoted,
<span class="pb" id="Pg276"></span>
with attention directed toward incidentals and irrelevancies.
The work of intellect is <i lang="la" xml:lang="la">post mortem</i>. The
rise of social science, it will be pointed out, has increased
the amount of registering that occurs. Social
post mortems occur much more frequently than they
used to. But one of the things which the unbiased mind
will register is the impotency of discussion, analysis
and reporting in modifying the course of events. The
latter goes its way unheeding. The reply that this
condition of matters shows not the impotency of intelligence
but that what passes for science is not science
is too easy a retort to be satisfactory. We must have
recourse to some concrete facts or surrender our doctrine
just at the moment when we have formulated it.</p>
<p>Technical affairs give evidence that the work of inquiry,
reporting <ins class="corr" title="an" id="Corr_276_">and</ins> analysis is not always ineffectual.
The development of a chain of "nation-wide" tobacco
shops, of a well managed national telephone system, of
the extension of the service of an electric-light plant
testify to the fact that study, reflection and the formation
of plans do in some instances determine a course
of events. The effect is seen in both engineering management
and in national commercial expansion. Such
potency however, it must be admitted, is limited to just
those matters that are called technical in contrast with
the larger affairs of humanity. But if we seek, as we
should, for a definition of "technical," we can hardly
find any save one that goes in a circle: Affairs are technical
in which observation, analysis and intellectual organization
are determining factors. Is the conclusion
<span class="pb" id="Pg277"></span>
to be drawn a conviction that our wider social interests
are so different from those in which intelligence is a
directing factor that in the former science must always
remain a belated visitor coming upon the scene after
matters are settled? No, the logical conclusion is that
as yet we have no technique in important economic,
political and international affairs. Complexity of conditions
render the difficulties in the way of the development
of a technique enormous. It is imaginable they
will never be overcome. But our choice is between the
development of a technique by which intelligence will
become an intervening partner and a continuation of a
regime of accident, waste and distress.</p>
<hr />
<h2 class="spaced"><span class="pb" id="Pg278"></span>PART FOUR<br/> <small>CONCLUSION</small></h2>
<p>Conduct when distributed under heads like habit, impulse
and intelligence gets artificially shredded. In
discussing each of these topics we have run into the
others. We conclude, then, with an attempt to gather
together some outstanding considerations about conduct
as a whole.</p>
<h3>I</h3>
<p>The foremost conclusion is that morals has to do
with all activity into which alternative possibilities
enter. For wherever they enter a difference between
better and worse arises. Reflection upon action means
uncertainty and consequent need of decision as to which
course is better. The better is the good; the best is
not better than the good but is simply the discovered
good. Comparative and superlative degrees are only
paths to the positive degree of action. The worse or
evil is a rejected good. In deliberation and before
choice no evil presents itself as evil. Until it is rejected,
it is a competing good. After rejection, it figures not
as a lesser good, but as the bad of that situation.</p>
<p><span class="pb" id="Pg279"></span>
Actually then only deliberate action, conduct into
which reflective choice enters, is distinctively moral, for
only then does there enter the question of better and
worse. Yet it is a perilous error to draw a hard and
fast line between action into which deliberation and
choice enter and activity due to impulse and matter-of-fact
habit. One of the consequences of action is to involve
us in predicaments where we have to reflect upon
things formerly done as matter of course. One of the
chief problems of our dealings with others is to induce
them to reflect upon affairs which they usually perform
from unreflective habit. On the other hand, every reflective
choice tends to relegate some conscious issue
into a deed or habit henceforth taken for granted and
not thought upon. Potentially therefore every and
any act is within the scope of morals, being a candidate
for possible judgment with respect to its better-or-worse
quality. It thus becomes one of the most perplexing
problems of reflection to discover just how far
to carry it, what to bring under examination and what
to leave to unscrutinized habit. Because there is no
final recipe by which to decide this question all moral
judgment is experimental and subject to revision by its
issue.</p>
<p>The recognition that conduct covers every act that
is judged with reference to better and worse and that
the need of this judgment is potentially coextensive
with all portions of conduct, saves us from the mistake
which makes morality a separate department of life.
Potentially conduct is one hundred per cent of our acts.
<span class="pb" id="Pg280"></span>
Hence we must decline to admit theories which identify
morals with the purification of motives, edifying character,
pursuing remote and elusive perfection, obeying
supernatural command, acknowledging the authority of
duty. Such notions have a dual bad effect. First they
get in the way of observation of conditions and consequences.
They divert thought into side issues. Secondly,
while they confer a morbid exaggerated quality
upon things which are viewed under the aspect of morality,
they release the larger part of the acts of life
from serious, that is moral, survey. Anxious solicitude
for the few acts which are deemed moral is accompanied
by edicts of exemption and baths of immunity for most
acts. A moral moratorium prevails for everyday
affairs.</p>
<p>When we observe that morals is at home wherever
considerations of the worse and better are involved, we
are committed to noting that morality is a continuing
process not a fixed achievement. Morals means growth
of conduct in meaning; at least it means that kind of
expansion in meaning which is consequent upon observations
of the conditions and outcome of conduct. It
is all one with growing. Growing and growth are the
same fact expanded in actuality or telescoped in
thought. In the largest sense of the word, morals is
education. It is learning the meaning of what we are
about and employing that meaning in action. The
good, satisfaction, "end," of growth of present action
in shades and scope of meaning is the only good within
our control, and the only one, accordingly, for which
<span class="pb" id="Pg281"></span>
responsibility exists. The rest is luck, fortune. And
the tragedy of the moral notions most insisted upon by
the morally self-conscious is the relegation of the only
good which can fully engage thought, namely present
meaning of action, to the rank of an incident of a remote
good, whether that future good be defined as
pleasure, or perfection, or salvation, or attainment of
virtuous character.</p>
<p>"Present" activity is not a sharp narrow knife-blade
in time. The present is complex, containing
within itself a multitude of habits and impulses. It is
enduring, a course of action, a process including memory,
observation and foresight, a pressure forward, a
glance backward and a look outward. It is of <em>moral</em>
moment because it marks a transition in the direction
of breadth and clarity of action or in that of triviality
and confusion. Progress is present reconstruction adding
fullness and distinctness of meaning, and retrogression
is a present slipping away of significance, determinations,
grasp. Those who hold that progress can
be perceived and measured only by reference to a remote
goal, first confuse meaning with space, and then treat
spatial position as absolute, as limiting movement instead
of being bounded in and by movement. There are
plenty of negative elements, due to conflict, entanglement
and obscurity, in most of the situations of life,
and we do not require a revelation of some supreme
perfection to inform us whether or no we are making
headway in present rectification. We move on from
the worse and into, not just towards, the better, which
<span class="pb" id="Pg282"></span>
is authenticated not by comparison with the foreign but
in what is indigenous. Unless progress is a present
reconstructing, it is nothing; if it cannot be told by
qualities belonging to the movement of transition it
can never be judged.</p>
<p>Men have constructed a strange dream-world when
they have supposed that without a fixed ideal of a remote
good to inspire them, they have no inducement to
get relief from present troubles, no desires for liberation
from what oppresses and for clearing-up what
confuses present action. The world in which we could
get enlightenment and instruction about the direction
in which we are moving only from a vague conception of
an unattainable perfection would be totally unlike our
present world. Sufficient unto the day is the evil
thereof. Sufficient it is to stimulate us to remedial
action, to endeavor in order to convert strife into harmony,
monotony into a variegated scene, and limitation
into expansion. The converting is progress, the only
progress conceivable or attainable by man. Hence
every situation has its own measure and quality of
progress, and the need for progress is recurrent, constant.
If it is better to travel than to arrive, it is because
traveling is a constant arriving, while arrival
that precludes further traveling is most easily attained
by going to sleep or dying. We find our clews to direction
in the projected recollections of definite experienced
goods not in vague anticipations, even when
we label the vagueness perfection, the Ideal, and proceed
to manipulate its definition with dry dialectic logic.
<span class="pb" id="Pg283"></span>
Progress means increase of present meaning, which involves
multiplication of sensed distinctions as well as
harmony, unification. This statement may, perhaps, be
made generally, in application to the experience of
humanity. If history shows progress it can hardly be
found elsewhere than in this complication and extension
of the significance found within experience. It is clear
that such progress brings no surcease, no immunity
from perplexity and trouble. If we wished to transmute
this generalization into a categorical imperative
we should say: "So act as to increase the meaning of
present experience." But even then in order to get instruction
about the concrete quality of such increased
meaning we should have to run away from the law and
study the needs and alternative possibilities lying within
a unique and localized situation. The imperative,
like everything absolute, is sterile. Till men give up
the search for a general formula of progress they will
not know where to look to find it.</p>
<p>A business man proceeds by comparing today's liabilities
and assets with yesterday's, and projects plans
for tomorrow by a study of the movement thus indicated
in conjunction with study of the conditions of
the environment now existing. It is not otherwise with
the business of living. The future is a projection of the
subject-matter of the present, a projection which is not
arbitrary in the extent in which it divines the movement
of the moving present. The physician is lost who would
guide his activities of healing by building up a picture
of perfect health, the same for all and in its nature
<span class="pb" id="Pg284"></span>
complete and self-enclosed once for all. He employs
what he has discovered about actual cases of good
health and ill health and their causes to investigate the
present ailing individual, so as to further his recovering;
recovering, an intrinsic and living process rather
than recovery, which is comparative and static. Moral
theories, which however have not remained mere theories
but which have found their way into the opinions of
the common man, have reversed the situation and made
the present subservient to a rigid yet abstract future.</p>
<p>The ethical import of the doctrine of evolution is
enormous. But its import has been misconstrued because
the doctrine has been appropriated by the very
traditional notions which in truth it subverts. It has
been thought that the doctrine of evolution means the
complete subordination of present change to a future
goal. It has been constrained to teach a futile dogma
of approximation, instead of a gospel of present
growth. The usufruct of the new science has been
seized upon by the old tradition of fixed and external
ends. In fact evolution means continuity of change;
and the fact that change may take the form of present
growth of complexity and interaction. Significant
stages in change are found not in access of fixity of
attainment but in those crises in which a seeming fixity
of habits gives way to a release of capacities that have
not previously functioned: in times that is of readjustment
and redirection.</p>
<p>No matter what the present success in straightening
out difficulties and harmonizing conflicts, it is certain
<span class="pb" id="Pg285"></span>
that problems will recur in the future in a new form
or on a different plane. Indeed every genuine accomplishment
instead of winding up an affair and enclosing
it as a jewel in a casket for future contemplation,
complicates the practical situation. It effects a new
distribution of energies which have henceforth to be
employed in ways for which past experience gives no
exact instruction. Every important satisfaction of an
old want creates a new one; and this new one has to
enter upon an experimental adventure to find its satisfaction.
From the side of what has gone before
achievement settles something. From the side of what
comes after, it complicates, introducing new problems,
unsettling factors. There is something pitifully juvenile
in the idea that "evolution," progress, means a
definite sum of accomplishment which will forever stay
done, and which by an exact amount lessens the amount
still to be done, disposing once and for all of just so
many perplexities and advancing us just so far on our
road to a final stable and unperplexed goal. Yet the
typical nineteenth century, mid-victorian conception of
evolution was precisely a formulation of such a consummate
juvenilism.</p>
<p>If the true ideal is that of a stable condition free
from conflict and disturbance, then there are a number
of theories whose claims are superior to those of the
popular doctrine of evolution. Logic points rather in
the direction of Rousseau and Tolstoi who would recur
to some primitive simplicity, who would return from
complicated and troubled civilization to a state of nature.
<span class="pb" id="Pg286"></span>
For certainly progress in civilization has not only
meant increase in the scope and intricacy of problems
to be dealt with, but it entails increasing instability.
For in multiplying wants, instruments and possibilities,
it increases the variety of forces which enter into relations
with one another and which have to be intelligently
directed. Or again, Stoic indifference or Buddhist
calm have greater claims. For, it may be argued,
since all objective achievement only complicates the situation,
the victory of a final stability can be secured
only by renunciation of desire. Since every satisfaction
of desire increases force, and this in turn creates
new desires, withdrawal into an inner passionless state,
indifference to action and attainment, is the sole road
to possession of the eternal, stable and final reality.</p>
<p>Again, from the standpoint of definite approximation
to an ultimate goal, the balance falls heavily on the side
of pessimism. The more striving the more attainments,
perhaps; but also assuredly the more needs and the
more disappointments. The more we do and the more
we accomplish, the more the end is vanity and vexation.
From the standpoint of attainment of good that
stays put, that constitutes a definite sum performed
which lessens the amount of effort required in order to
reach the ultimate goal of final good, progress <em>is</em> an
illusion. But we are looking for it in the wrong place.
The world war is a bitter commentary on the nineteenth
century misconception of moral achievement—a misconception
however which it only inherited from the
traditional theory of fixed ends, attempting to bolster
<span class="pb" id="Pg287"></span>
up that doctrine with aid from the "scientific" theory
of evolution. The doctrine of progress is not yet bankrupt.
The bankruptcy of the notion of fixed goods to
be attained and stably possessed may possibly be the
means of turning the mind of man to a tenable theory
of progress—to attention to present troubles and possibilities.</p>
<p>Adherents of the idea that betterment, growth in
goodness, consists in approximation to an exhaustive,
stable, immutable end or good, have been compelled to
recognize the truth that in fact we envisage the good
in specific terms that are relative to existing needs, and
that the attainment of every specific good merges insensibly
into a new condition of maladjustment with its
need of a new end and a renewed effort. But they
have elaborated an ingenious dialectical theory to account
for the facts while maintaining their theory intact.
The goal, the ideal, is infinite; man is finite, subject
to conditions imposed by space and time. The
specific character of the ends which man entertains
and of the satisfaction he achieves is due therefore
precisely to his empirical and finite nature in its contrast
with the infinite and complete character of the
true reality, the end. Consequently when man reaches
what he had taken to be the destination of his journey
he finds that he has only gone a piece on the road. Infinite
vistas still stretch before him. Again he sets his
mark a little way further ahead, and again when he
reaches the station set, he finds the road opening before
him in unexpected ways, and sees new distant objects
<span class="pb" id="Pg288"></span>
beckoning him forward. Such is the popular doctrine.</p>
<p>By some strange perversion this theory passes for
moral idealism. An office of inspiration and guidance is
attributed to the thought of the goal of ultimate completeness
or perfection. As matter of fact, the idea
sincerely held brings discouragement and despair not
inspiration or hopefulness. There is something either
ludicrous or tragic in the notion that inspiration to
continued progress is had in telling man that no matter
what he does or what he achieves, the outcome is negligible
in comparison with what he set out to achieve, that
every endeavor he makes is bound to turn out a failure
compared with what should be done, that every attained
satisfaction is only forever bound to be only a
disappointment. The honest conclusion is pessimism.
All is vexation, and the greater the effort the greater
the vexation. But the fact is that it is not the negative
aspect of an outcome, its failure to reach infinity,
which renews courage and hope. Positive attainment,
actual enrichment of meaning and powers opens new
vistas and sets new tasks, creates new aims and stimulates
new efforts. The facts are not such as to yield
unthinking optimism and consolation; for they render
it impossible to rest upon attained goods. New struggles
and failures are inevitable. The total scene of
action remains as before, only for us more complex,
and more subtly unstable. But this very situation is a
consequence of expansion, not of failures of power, and
when grasped and admitted it is a challenge to intelligence.
Instruction in what to do next can never come
<span class="pb" id="Pg289"></span>
from an infinite goal, which for us is bound to be empty.
It can be derived only from study of the deficiencies,
irregularities and possibilities of the actual situation.</p>
<p>In any case, however, arguments about pessimism and
optimism based upon considerations regarding fixed
attainment of good and evil are mainly literary in quality.
Man continues to live because he is a living creature
not because reason convinces him of the certainty
or probability of future satisfactions and achievements.
He is instinct with activities that carry him on. Individuals
here and there cave in, and most individuals
sag, withdraw and seek refuge at this and that point.
But man as man still has the dumb pluck of the animal.
He has endurance, hope, curiosity, eagerness, love of
action. These traits belong to him by structure, not by
taking thought. Memory of past and foresight of future
convert dumbness to some degree of articulateness.
They illumine curiosity and steady courage.
Then when the future arrives with its inevitable disappointments
as well as fulfilments, and with new
sources of trouble, failure loses something of its fatality,
and suffering yields fruit of instruction not of bitterness.
Humility is more demanded at our moments
of triumph than at those of failure. For humility is
not a caddish self-depreciation. It is the sense of our
slight inability even with our best intelligence and effort
to command events; a sense of our dependence
upon forces that go their way without our wish and
plan. Its purport is not to relax effort but to make
us prize every opportunity of present growth. In
<span class="pb" id="Pg290"></span>
morals, the infinitive and the imperative develop from
the participle, present tense. Perfection means perfecting,
fulfilment, fulfilling, and the good is now or
never.</p>
<p>Idealistic philosophies, those of Plato, Aristotle, Spinoza,
like the hypothesis now offered, have found the
good in meanings belonging to a conscious life, a life
of reason, not in external achievement. Like it, they
have exalted the place of intelligence in securing fulfilment
of conscious life. These theories have at least
not subordinated conscious life to external obedience,
not thought of virtue as something different from excellence
of life. But they set up a transcendental meaning
and reason, remote from present experience and
opposed to it; or they insist upon a special form of
meaning and consciousness to be attained by peculiar
modes of knowledge inaccessible to the common man,
involving not continuous reconstruction of ordinary
experience, but its wholesale reversal. They have
treated regeneration, change of heart, as wholesale and
self-enclosed, not as continuous.</p>
<p>The utilitarians also made good and evil, right and
wrong, matters of conscious experience. In addition
they brought them down to earth, to everyday experience.
They strove to humanize other-worldly goods.
But they retained the notion that the good is future,
and hence outside the meaning of present activity. In
so far it is sporadic, exceptional, subject to accident,
passive, an enjoyment not a joy, something hit upon,
not a fulfilling. The future end is for them not <em>so</em>
<span class="pb" id="Pg291"></span>
remote from present action as the Platonic realm of
ideals, or as the Aristotelian rational thought, or the
Christian heaven, or Spinoza's conception of the universal
whole. But still it is separate in principle and
in fact from present activity. The next step is to identify
the sought for good with the meaning of our
impulses and our habits, and the specific <em>moral</em> good
or virtue with <em>learning</em> this meaning, a learning that
takes us back not into an isolated self but out into the
open-air world of objects and social ties, terminating
in an increment of present significance.</p>
<p>Doubtless there are those who will think that we
thus escape from remote and external ends only to fall
into an Epicureanism which teaches us to subordinate
everything else to present satisfactions. The hypothesis
preferred may seem to some to advise a subjective,
self-centered life of intensified consciousness, an esthetically
dilettante type of egoism. For is not its lesson
that we should concentrate attention, each upon the
consciousness accompanying his action so as to refine
and develop it? Is not this, like all subjective morals,
an anti-social doctrine, instructing us to subordinate
the objective consequences of our acts, those which promote
the welfare of others, to an enrichment of our
private conscious lives?</p>
<p>It can hardly be denied that as compared with the
dogmas against which it reacted there is an element of
truth in Epicureanism. It strove to center attention
upon what is actually within control and to find the
good in the present instead of in a contingent uncertain
<span class="pb" id="Pg292"></span>
future. The trouble with it lies in its account of
present good. It failed to connect this good with the
full reach of activities. It contemplated good of withdrawal
rather than of active participation. That is
to say, the objection to Epicureanism lies in its conception
of what constitutes present good, not in its
emphasis upon satisfaction as at present. The same remark
may be made about every theory which recognizes
the individual self. If any such theory is objectionable,
the objection is against the character or quality
assigned to the self. Of course an individual is the
bearer or carrier of experience. What of that? Everything
depends upon the kind of experience that centers
in him. Not the residence of experience counts, but its
contents, what's in the house. The center is not in the
abstract amenable to our control, but what gathers
about it is our affair. We can't help being individual
selves, each one of us. If selfhood as such is a bad
thing, the blame lies not with the self but with the universe,
with providence. But in fact the distinction between
a selfishness with which we find fault and an
unselfishness which we esteem is found in the quality
of the activities which proceed from and enter into the
self, according as they are contractive, exclusive, or
expansive, outreaching. Meaning exists for some self,
but this truistic fact doesn't fix the quality of any particular
meaning. It may be such as to make the self
small, or such as to exalt and dignify the self. It is
as impertinent to decry the worth of experience because
it is connected with a self as it is fantastic to
<span class="pb" id="Pg293"></span>
idealize personality just as personality aside from the
question what sort of a person one is.</p>
<p>Other persons are selves too. If one's own present
experience is to be depreciated in its meaning because
it centers in a self, why act for the welfare of others?
Selfishness for selfishness, one is as good as another;
our own is worth as much as another's. But the recognition
that good is always found in a present growth
of significance in activity protects us from thinking
that welfare can consist in a soup-kitchen happiness,
in pleasures we can confer upon others from without.
It shows that good is the same in quality wherever it is
found, whether in some other self or in one's own. An
activity has meaning in the degree in which it establishes
and acknowledges variety and intimacy of connections.
As long as any social impulse endures, so long an activity
that shuts itself off will bring inward dissatisfaction
and entail a struggle for compensatory goods, no matter
what pleasures or external successes acclaim its
course.</p>
<p>To say that the welfare of others, like our own,
consists in a widening and deepening of the perceptions
that give activity its meaning, in an educative growth,
is to set forth a proposition of political import. To
"make others happy" except through liberating their
powers and engaging them in activities that enlarge
the meaning of life is to harm them and to indulge
ourselves under cover of exercising a special virtue.
Our moral measure for estimating any existing arrangement
or any proposed reform is its effect upon
<span class="pb" id="Pg294"></span>
impulse and habits. Does it liberate or suppress, ossify
or render flexible, divide or unify interest? Is perception
quickened or dulled? Is memory made apt and
extensive or narrow and diffusely irrelevant? Is imagination
diverted to fantasy and compensatory dreams,
or does it add fertility to life? Is thought creative or
pushed one side into pedantic specialisms? There is a
sense in which to set up social welfare as an end of
action only promotes an offensive condescension, a
harsh interference, or an oleaginous display of complacent
kindliness. It always tends in this direction
when it is aimed at giving happiness to others
directly, that is, as we can hand a physical thing to
another. To foster conditions that widen the horizon
of others and give them command of their own powers,
so that they can find their own happiness in their own
fashion, is the way of "social" action. Otherwise the
prayer of a freeman would be to be left alone, and to be
delivered, above all, from "reformers" and "kind"
people.</p>
<hr />
<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg295"></span>II</h3>
<p>Since morals is concerned with conduct, it grows out
of specific empirical facts. Almost all influential moral
theories, with the exception of the utilitarian, have refused
to admit this idea. For Christendom as a whole,
morality has been connected with supernatural commands,
rewards and penalties. Those who have escaped
this superstition have contented themselves with
converting the difference between this world and the
next into a distinction between the actual and the ideal,
what is and what should be. The actual world has not
been surrendered to the devil in name, but it is treated
as a display of physical forces incapable of generating
moral values. Consequently, moral considerations must
be introduced from above. Human nature may not be
officially declared to be infected because of some aboriginal
sin, but it is said to be sensuous, impulsive, subjected
to necessity, while natural intelligence is such
that it cannot rise above a reckoning of private expediency.</p>
<p>But in fact morals is the most humane of all subjects.
It is that which is closest to human nature; it
is ineradicably empirical, not theological nor metaphysical
nor mathematical. Since it directly concerns
human nature, everything that can be known of the
human mind and body in physiology, medicine, anthropology,
<span class="pb" id="Pg296"></span>
and psychology is pertinent to moral inquiry.
Human nature exists and operates in an environment.
And it is not "in" that environment as coins are in a
box, but as a plant is in the sunlight and soil. It is
of them, continuous with their energies, dependent upon
their support, capable of increase only as it utilizes
them, and as it gradually rebuilds from their crude indifference
an environment genially civilized. Hence
physics, chemistry, history, statistics, engineering science,
are a part of disciplined moral knowledge so far
as they enable us to understand the conditions and
agencies through which man lives, and on account of
which he forms and executes his plans. Moral science
is not something with a separate province. It is physical,
biological and historic knowledge placed in a
human context where it will illuminate and guide the
activities of men.</p>
<p>The path of truth is narrow and straitened. It is
only too easy to wander beyond the course from this
side to that. In a reaction from that error which has
made morals fanatic or fantastic, sentimental or
authoritative by severing them from actual facts and
forces, theorists have gone to the other extreme. They
have insisted that natural laws are themselves moral
laws, so that it remains, after noting them, only to conform
to them. This doctrine of accord with nature
has usually marked a transition period. When mythology
is dying in its open forms, and when social life is
so disturbed that custom and tradition fail to supply
their wonted control, men resort to Nature as a norm.
<span class="pb" id="Pg297"></span>
They apply to Nature all the eulogistic predicates previously
associated with divine law; or natural law is
conceived of as the only true divine law. This happened
in one form in Stoicism. It happened in another
form in the deism of the eighteenth century with its
notion of a benevolent, harmonious, wholly rational
order of Nature.</p>
<p>In our time this notion has been perpetuated in connection
with a laissez-faire social philosophy and the
theory of evolution. Human intelligence is thought to
mark an artificial interference if it does more than register
fixed natural laws as rules of human action. The
process of natural evolution is conceived as the exact
model of human endeavor. The two ideas met in Spencer.
To the "enlightened" of a former generation,
Spencer's evolutionary philosophy seemed to afford a
scientific sanction for the necessity of moral progress,
while it also proved, up to the hilt, the futility of deliberate
"interference" with the benevolent operations
of nature. The idea of justice was identified with the
law of cause and effect. Transgression of natural law
wrought in the struggle for existence its own penalty of
elimination, and conformity with it brought the reward
of increased vitality and happiness. By this process
egoistic desire is gradually coming into harmony with
the necessity of the environment, till at last the individual
automatically finds happiness in doing what the
natural and social environment demands, and serves
himself in serving others. From this point of view,
earlier "scientific" philosophers made a mistake, but
<span class="pb" id="Pg298"></span>
only the mistake of anticipating the date of complete
natural harmony. All that reason can do is to acknowledge
the evolutionary forces, and thereby refrain from
retarding the arrival of the happy day of perfect harmony.
Meantime justice demands that the weak and
ignorant suffer the effect of violation of natural law,
while the wise and able reap the rewards of their
superiority.</p>
<p>The fundamental defect of such views is that they
fail to see the difference made in conditions and energies
by perception of them. It is the first business of
mind to be "realistic," to see things "as they are."
If, for example, biology can give us knowledge of the
causes of competency and incompetency, strength and
weakness, that knowledge is all to the good. A non-sentimental
morals will seek for all the instruction natural
science can give concerning the biological conditions
and consequences of inferiority and superiority.
But knowledge of facts does not entail conformity and
acquiescence. The contrary is the case. Perception
of things as they are is but a stage in the process of
making them different. They have already begun to be
different in being known, for by that fact they enter
into a different context, a context of foresight and
judgment of better and worse. A false psychology of
a separate realm of consciousness is the only reason
this fact is not generally acknowledged. Morality resides
not in perception of fact, but in the <em>use</em> made of
its perception. It is a monstrous assumption that
its sole use is to utter benedictions upon fact and its
<span class="pb" id="Pg299"></span>
offspring. It is the part of intelligence to tell when
to use the fact to conform and perpetuate, and when
to use it to vary conditions and consequences.</p>
<p>It is absurd to suppose that knowledge about the connection
between inferiority and its consequences prescribes
adherence to that connection. It is like supposing
that knowledge of the connection between malaria
and mosquitoes enjoins breeding mosquitoes. The
fact when it is known enters into a new environment.
Without ceasing to belong to the physical environment
it enters also into a medium of human activities, of
desires and aversions, habits and instincts. It thereby
gains new potencies, new capacities. Gunpowder in
water does not act the same as gunpowder next a flame.
A fact known does not operate the same as a fact unperceived.
When it is known it comes into contact with
the flame of desire and the cold bath of antipathy.
Knowledge of the conditions that breed incapacity may
fit into some desire to maintain others in that state
while averting it for one's self. Or it may fall in with
a character which finds itself blocked by such facts, and
therefore strives to use knowledge of causes to make a
change in effects. Morality begins at this point of use
of knowledge of natural law, a use varying with the
active system of dispositions and desires. Intelligent
action is not concerned with the bare consequences of
the thing known, but with consequences <em>to be</em> brought
into existence by action conditioned on the knowledge.
Men may use their knowledge to induce conformity or
exaggeration, or to effect change and abolition of conditions.
<span class="pb" id="Pg300"></span>
The quality of these consequences determines
the question of better or worse.</p>
<p>The exaggeration of the harmony attributed to Nature
aroused men to note its disharmonies. An optimistic
view of natural benevolence was followed by a more
honest, less romantic view of struggle and conflict in
nature. After Helvetius and Bentham came Malthus
and Darwin. The problem of morals is the problem of
desire and intelligence. What is to be done with these
facts of disharmony and conflict? After we have discovered
the place and consequences of conflict in nature,
we have still to discover its place and working in
human need and thought. What is its office, its function,
its <em>possibility</em>, or use? In general, the answer is simple.
Conflict is the gadfly of thought. It stirs us to observation
and memory. It instigates to invention. It
shocks us out of sheep-like passivity, and sets us at
noting and contriving. Not that it always effects this
result; but that conflict is a <i lang="la" xml:lang="la">sine qua non</i> of reflection
and ingenuity. When this possibility of making use of
conflict has once been noted, it is possible to utilize it
systematically to substitute the arbitration of mind for
that of brutal attack and brute collapse. But the
tendency to take natural law for a norm of action which
the supposedly scientific have inherited from eighteenth
century rationalism leads to an idealization of the principle
of conflict itself. Its office in promoting progress
through arousing intelligence is overlooked, and it is
erected into the generator of progress. Karl Marx
borrowed from the dialectic of Hegel the idea of the
<span class="pb" id="Pg301"></span>
necessity of a negative element, of opposition, for advance.
He projected it into social affairs and reached
the conclusion that all social development comes from
conflict between classes, and that therefore class-warfare
is to be cultivated. Hence a supposedly scientific
form of the doctrine of social evolution preaches social
hostility as the road to social harmony. It would be
difficult to find a more striking instance of what happens
when natural events are given a social and practical
sanctification. Darwinism has been similarly used
to justify war and the brutalities of competition for
wealth and power.</p>
<p>The excuse, the provocation, though not the justification
for such a doctrine is found in the actions of those
who say peace, peace, when there is no peace, who refuse
to recognize facts as they are, who proclaim a natural
harmony of wealth and merit, of capital and labor, and
the natural justice, in the main, of existing conditions.
There is something horrible, something that makes one
fear for civilization, in denunciations of class-differences
and class struggles which proceed from a class in
power, one that is seizing every means, even to a monopoly
of moral ideals, to carry on its struggle for
class-power. This class adds hypocrisy to conflict and
brings all idealism into disrepute. It does everything
which ingenuity and prestige can do to give color to
the assertions of those who say that all moral considerations
are irrelevant, and that the issue is one of
brute trial of forces between this side and that. The
alternative, here as elsewhere, is not between denying
<span class="pb" id="Pg302"></span>
facts in behalf of something termed moral ideals and
accepting facts as final. There remains the possibility
of recognizing facts and using them as a challenge
to intelligence to modify the environment and change
habits.</p>
<hr />
<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg303"></span>III</h3>
<p>The place of natural fact and law in morals brings us
to the problem of freedom. We are told that seriously
to import empirical facts into morals is equivalent to
an abrogation of freedom. Facts and laws mean necessity
we are told. The way to freedom is to turn our
back upon them and take flight to a separate ideal
realm. Even if the flight could be successfully accomplished,
the efficacy of the prescription may be
doubted. For we need freedom in and among
actual events, not apart from them. It is to
be hoped therefore that there remains an alternative;
that the road to freedom may be found in that
knowledge of facts which enables us to employ them in
connection with desires and aims. A physician or engineer
is free in his thought and his action in the degree
in which he knows what he deals with. Possibly we find
here the key to any freedom.</p>
<p>What men have esteemed and fought for in the name
of liberty is varied and complex—but certainly it has
never been a metaphysical freedom of will. It seems
to contain three elements of importance, though on
their face not all of them are directly compatible with
one another. (i) It includes efficiency in action, ability
to carry out plans, the absence of cramping and
thwarting obstacles. (ii) It also includes capacity to
<span class="pb" id="Pg304"></span>
vary plans, to change the course of action, to experience
novelties. And again (iii) it signifies the power of
desire and choice to be factors in events.</p>
<p>Few men would purchase even a high amount of efficient
action along definite lines at the price of monotony,
or if success in action were bought by all abandonment
of personal preference. They would probably feel
that a more precious freedom was possessed in a life
of ill-assured objective achievement that contained
undertaking of risks, adventuring in new fields, a pitting
of personal choice against the odds of events, and
a mixture of success and failures, provided choice had
a career. The slave is a man who executes the wish of
others, one doomed to act along lines predetermined to
regularity. Those who have defined freedom as ability
to act have unconsciously assumed that this ability is
exercised in accord with desire, and that its operation
introduces the agent into fields previously unexplored.
Hence the conception of freedom as involving three
factors.</p>
<p>Yet efficiency in execution cannot be ignored. To say
that a man is free to choose to walk while the only walk
he can take will lead him over a precipice is to strain
words as well as facts. Intelligence is the key to freedom
in act. We are likely to be able to go ahead prosperously
in the degree in which we have consulted conditions
and formed a plan which enlists their consenting
cooperation. The gratuitous help of unforeseen
circumstance we cannot afford to despise. Luck, bad
if not good, will always be with us. But it has a way
<span class="pb" id="Pg305"></span>
of favoring the intelligent and showing its back to the
stupid. And the gifts of fortune when they come are
fleeting except when they are made taut by intelligent
adaptation of conditions. In neutral and adverse circumstances,
study and foresight are the only roads to
unimpeded action. Insistence upon a metaphysical
freedom of will is generally at its most strident pitch
with those who despise knowledge of matters-of-fact.
They pay for their contempt by halting and confined
action. Glorification of freedom in general at the expense
of positive abilities in particular has often characterized
the official creed of historic liberalism. Its
outward sign is the separation of politics and law from
economics. Much of what is called the "individualism"
of the early nineteenth century has in truth little
to do with the nature of individuals. It goes back to a
metaphysics which held that harmony between man and
nature can be taken for granted, if once certain artificial
restrictions upon man are removed. Hence it
neglected the necessity of studying and regulating industrial
conditions so that a nominal freedom can
be made an actuality. Find a man who believes that all
men need is freedom <em>from</em> oppressive legal and political
measures, and you have found a man who, unless he is
merely obstinately maintaining his own private privileges,
carries at the back of his head some heritage of
the metaphysical doctrine of free-will, plus an optimistic
confidence in natural harmony. He needs a philosophy
that recognizes the objective character of freedom
and its dependence upon a congruity of environment
<span class="pb" id="Pg306"></span>
with human wants, an agreement which can be
obtained only by profound thought and unremitting
application. For freedom as a fact depends upon conditions
of work which are socially and scientifically
buttressed. Since industry covers the most pervasive
relations of man with his environment, freedom is unreal
which does not have as its basis an economic command
of environment.</p>
<p>I have no desire to add another to the cheap and easy
solutions which exist of the seeming conflict between
freedom and organization. It is reasonably obvious
that organization may become a hindrance to freedom;
it does not take us far to say that the trouble lies not
in organization but in over-organization. At the same
time, it must be admitted that there is no effective or
objective freedom without organization. It is easy to
criticize the contract theory of the state which states
that individuals surrender some at least of their natural
liberties in order to make secure as civil liberties what
they retain. Nevertheless there is some truth in the
idea of surrender and exchange. A certain natural
freedom is possessed by man. That is to say, in some
respects harmony exists between a man's energies and
his surroundings such that the latter support and execute
his purposes. In so far he is free; without such
a basic natural support, conscious contrivances of legislation,
administration and deliberate human institution
of social arrangements cannot take place. In this
sense natural freedom is prior to political freedom and
is its condition. But we cannot trust wholly to a freedom
<span class="pb" id="Pg307"></span>
thus procured. It is at the mercy of accident.
Conscious agreements among men must supplement and
in some degree supplant freedom of action which is the
gift of nature. In order to arrive at these agreements,
individuals have to make concessions. They must consent
to curtailment of some natural liberties in order
that any of them may be rendered secure and enduring.
They must, in short, enter into an organization with
other human beings so that the activities of others may
be permanently counted upon to assure regularity of
action and far-reaching scope of plans and courses of
action. The procedure is not, in so far, unlike surrendering
a portion of one's income in order to buy insurance
against future contingencies, and thus to render
the future course of life more equably secure. It would
be folly to maintain that there is no sacrifice; we can
however contend that the sacrifice is a reasonable one,
justified by results.</p>
<p>Viewed in this light, the relation of individual freedom
to organization is seen to be an experimental affair.
It is not capable of being settled by abstract
theory. Take the question of labor unions and the
closed or open shop. It is folly to fancy that no restrictions
and surrenders of prior freedoms and possibilities
of future freedoms are involved in the extension
of this particular form of organization. But to
condemn such organization on the theoretical ground
that a restriction of liberty is entailed is to adopt a
position which would have been fatal to every advance
step in civilization, and to every net gain in effective
<span class="pb" id="Pg308"></span>
freedom. Every such question is to be judged not on
the basis of antecedent theory but on the basis of concrete
consequences. The question is to the balance of
freedom and security achieved, as compared with practicable
alternatives. Even the question of the point
where membership in an organization ceases to be a
voluntary matter and becomes coercive or required, is
also an experimental matter, a thing to be decided by
scientifically conducted study of consequences, of pros
and cons. It is definitely an affair of specific detail,
not of wholesale theory. It is equally amusing to see
one man denouncing on grounds of pure theory the
coercion of workers by a labor union while he avails
himself of the increased power due to corporate action
in business and praises the coercion of the political
state; and to see another man denouncing the latter as
pure tyranny, while lauding the power of industrial
labor organizations. The position of one or the other
may be justified in particular cases, but justification
is due to results in practice not to general theory.</p>
<p>Organization tends, however, to become rigid and
to limit freedom. In addition to security and energy
in action, novelty, risk, change are ingredients of the
freedom which men desire. Variety is more than the
spice of life; it is largely of its essence, making a difference
between the free and the enslaved. Invariant
virtue appears to be as mechanical as uninterrupted
vice, for true excellence changes with conditions. Unless
character rises to overcome some new difficulty or
conquer some temptation from an unexpected quarter
<span class="pb" id="Pg309"></span>
we suspect its grain is only a veneer. Choice is an element
in freedom and there can be no choice without
unrealized and precarious possibilities. It is this demand
for genuine contingency which is caricatured in
the orthodox doctrine of a freedom of indifference, a
power to choose this way or that apart from any habit
or impulse, without even a desire on the part of will to
show off. Such an indetermination of choice is not
desired by the lover of either reason or excitement.
The theory of arbitrary free choice represents indeterminateness
of conditions grasped in a vague and lazy
fashion and hardened into a desirable attribute of will.
Under the title of freedom men prize such uncertainty
of conditions as give deliberation and choice an opportunity.
But uncertainty of volition which is more than
a reflection of uncertainty of conditions is the mark of
a person who has acquired imbecility of character
through permanent weakening of his springs of action.</p>
<p>Whether or not indeterminateness, uncertainty,
actually exists in the world is a difficult question. It is
easier to think of the world as fixed, settled once for
all, and man as accumulating all the uncertainty there
is in his will and all the doubt there is in his intellect.
The rise of natural science has facilitated this dualistic
partitioning, making nature wholly fixed and mind
wholly open and empty. Fortunately for us we do not
have to settle the question. A hypothetical answer is
enough. <em>If</em> the world is already done and done for, if
its character is entirely achieved so that its behavior
is like that of a man lost in routine, then the only freedom
<span class="pb" id="Pg310"></span>
for which man can hope is one of efficiency in overt
action. But <em>if</em> change is genuine, if accounts are still
in process of making, and if objective uncertainty is the
stimulus to reflection, then variation in action, novelty
and experiment, have a true meaning. In any case the
question is an objective one. It concerns not man in
isolation from the world but man in his connection with
it. A world that is at points and times indeterminate
enough to call out deliberation and to give play to
choice to shape its future is a world in which will is
free, not because it is inherently vacillating and unstable,
but because deliberation and choice are determining
and stabilizing factors.</p>
<p>Upon an empirical view, uncertainty, doubt, hesitation,
contingency and novelty, genuine change which is
not mere disguised repetition, are facts. Only deductive
reasoning from certain fixed premisses creates a
bias in favor of complete determination and finality.
To say that these things exist only in human experience
not in the world, and exist there only because of our
"finitude" is dangerously like paying ourselves with
words. Empirically the life of man seems in these respects
as in others to express a culmination of facts in
nature. To admit ignorance and uncertainty in man
while denying them to nature involves a curious dualism.
Variability, initiative, innovation, departure from
routine, experimentation are empirically the manifestation
of a genuine nisus in things. At all events it is
these things that are precious to us under the name
of freedom. It is their elimination from the life of a
<span class="pb" id="Pg311"></span>
slave which makes his life servile, intolerable to the
freeman who has once been on his own, no matter what
his animal comfort and security. A free man would
rather take his chance in an open world than be guaranteed
in a closed world.</p>
<p>These considerations give point to the third factor
in love of freedom: the desire to have desire count as a
factor, a force. Even if will chooses unaccountably,
even if it be a capricious impulse, it does not follow
that there are real alternatives, genuine possibilities,
open in the future. What we want is possibilities open
in the <em>world</em> not in the will, except as will or deliberate
activity reflects the world. To foresee future objective
alternatives and to be able by deliberation to choose
one of them and thereby weight its chances in the
struggle for future existence, measures our freedom.
It is assumed sometimes that if it can be shown that
deliberation determines choice and deliberation is determined
by character and conditions, there is no freedom.
This is like saying that because a flower comes
from root and stem it cannot bear fruit. The question
is not what are the antecedents of deliberation and
choice, but what are their consequences. What do they
do that is distinctive? The answer is that they give us
all the control of future possibilities which is open to us.
And this control is the crux of our freedom. Without
it, we are pushed from behind. With it we walk in the
light.</p>
<p>The doctrine that knowledge, intelligence rather than
will, constitutes freedom is not new. It has been
<span class="pb" id="Pg312"></span>
preached by moralists of many a school. All rationalists
have identified freedom with action emancipated
by insight into truth. But insight into necessity has
by them been substituted for foresight of possibilities.
Tolstoi for example expressed the idea of Spinoza and
Hegel when he said that the ox is a slave as long as
he refuses to recognize the yoke and chafes under it,
while if he identifies himself with its necessity and draws
willingly instead of rebelliously, he is free. But as long
as the yoke is a yoke it is impossible that voluntary
identification with it should occur. Conscious submission
is then either fatalistic submissiveness or cowardice.
The ox accepts in fact not the yoke but the stall
and the hay to which the yoke is a necessary incident.
But if the ox foresees the consequences of the use of
the yoke, if he anticipates the possibility of harvest,
and identifies himself not with the yoke but with the
realization of its possibilities, he acts freely, voluntarily.
He hasn't accepted a necessity as unavoidable; he
has welcomed a possibility as a desirability.</p>
<p>Perception of necessary law plays, indeed, a part.
But no amount of insight into necessity brings with it,
as such, anything but a consciousness of necessity.
Freedom is the "truth of necessity" only when we use
one "necessity" to alter another. When we use the
law to foresee consequences and to consider how they
may be averted or secured, then freedom begins. Employing
knowledge of law to enforce desire in execution
gives power to the engineer. Employing knowledge of
law in order to submit to it without further action constitutes
<span class="pb" id="Pg313"></span>
fatalism, no matter how it be dressed up. Thus
we recur to our main contention. Morality depends
upon events, not upon commands and ideals alien to
nature. But intelligence treats events as moving, as
fraught with possibilities, not as ended, final. In forecasting
their possibilities, the distinction between better
and worse arises. Human desire and ability cooperates
with this or that natural force according as this
or that eventuality is judged better. We do not use
the present to control the future. We use the foresight
of the future to refine and expand present activity.
In this use of desire, deliberation and choice, freedom
is actualized.</p>
<hr />
<h3><span class="pb" id="Pg314"></span>IV</h3>
<p>Intelligence becomes ours in the degree in which we
use it and accept responsibility for consequences. It
is not ours originally or by production. "It thinks"
is a truer psychological statement than "I think."
Thoughts sprout and vegetate; ideas proliferate. They
come from deep unconscious sources. "I think" is a
statement about voluntary action. Some suggestion
surges from the unknown. Our active body of habits
appropriates it. The suggestion then becomes an assertion.
It no longer merely comes to us. It is accepted
and uttered by us. We act upon it and thereby assume,
by implication, its consequences. The stuff of belief
and proposition is not originated by us. It comes to us
from others, by education, tradition and the suggestion
of the environment. Our intelligence is bound up, so
far as its materials are concerned, with the community
life of which we are a part. We know what it communicates
to us, and know according to the habits it forms
in us. Science is an affair of civilization not of individual
intellect.</p>
<p>So with conscience. When a child acts, those about
him re-act. They shower encouragement upon him,
visit him with approval, or they bestow frowns and
rebuke. What others do to us when we act is as natural
a consequence of our action as what the fire does
<span class="pb" id="Pg315"></span>
to us when we plunge our hands in it. The social environment
may be as artificial as you please. But its
action in response to ours is natural not artificial. In
language and imagination we rehearse the responses of
others just as we dramatically enact other consequences.
We foreknow how others will act, and the foreknowledge
is the beginning of judgment passed on action. We
know <em>with</em> them; there is conscience. An assembly is
formed within our breast which discusses and appraises
proposed and performed acts. The community without
becomes a forum and tribunal within, a judgment-seat
of charges, assessments and exculpations. Our
thoughts of our own actions are saturated with the
ideas that others entertain about them, ideas which
have been expressed not only in explicit instruction but
still more effectively in reaction to our acts.</p>
<p>Liability is the beginning of responsibility. We are
held accountable by others for the consequences of our
acts. They visit their like and dislike of these consequences
upon us. In vain do we claim that these are
not ours; that they are products of ignorance not
design, or are incidents in the execution of a most laudable
scheme. Their authorship is imputed to us. We
are disapproved, and disapproval is not an inner state
of mind but a most definite act. Others say to us by
their deeds we do not care a fig whether you did this
deliberately or not. We intend that you <em>shall</em> deliberate
before you do it again, and that if possible your
deliberation shall prevent a repetition of this act we
object to. The reference in blame and every unfavorable
<span class="pb" id="Pg316"></span>
judgment is prospective, not retrospective. Theories
about responsibility may become confused, but in
practice no one is stupid enough to try to change the
past. Approbation and disapprobation are ways of
influencing the formation of habits and aims; that is,
of influencing future acts. The individual is <em>held</em> accountable
for what he <em>has</em> done in order that he may be
responsive in what he is <em>going</em> to do. Gradually persons
learn by dramatic imitation to hold themselves
accountable, and liability becomes a voluntary deliberate
acknowledgment that deeds are our own, that
their consequences come from us.</p>
<p>These two facts, that moral judgment and moral
responsibility are the work wrought in us by the social
environment, signify that all morality is social; not
because we <em>ought</em> to take into account the effect of our
acts upon the welfare of others, but because of facts.
Others <em>do</em> take account of what we do, and they respond
accordingly to our acts. Their responses actually
<em>do</em> affect the meaning of what we do. The significance
thus contributed is as inevitable as is the effect
of interaction with the physical environment. In fact
as civilization advances the physical environment gets
itself more and more humanized, for the meaning of
physical energies and events becomes involved with the
part they play in human activities. Our conduct <em>is</em>
socially conditioned whether we perceive the fact or
not.</p>
<p>The effect of custom on habit, and of habit upon
thought is enough to prove this statement. When we
<span class="pb" id="Pg317"></span>
begin to forecast consequences, the consequences that
most stand out are those which will proceed from other
people. The resistance and the cooperation of others
is the central fact in the furtherance or failure of our
schemes. Connections with our fellows furnish both the
opportunities for action and the instrumentalities by
which we take advantage of opportunity. All of the
actions of an individual bear the stamp of his community
as assuredly as does the language he speaks.
Difficulty in reading the stamp is due to variety of impressions
in consequence of membership in many groups.
This social saturation is, I repeat, a matter of fact,
not of what should be, not of what is desirable or undesirable.
It does not guarantee the rightness of goodness
of an act; there is no excuse for thinking of evil
action as individualistic and right action as social.
Deliberate unscrupulous pursuit of self-interest is as
much conditioned upon social opportunities, training
and assistance as is the course of action prompted by
a beaming benevolence. The difference lies in the quality
and degree of the perception of ties and interdependencies;
in the use to which they are put. Consider
the form commonly assumed today by self-seeking;
namely command of money and economic power.
Money is a social institution; property is a legal custom;
economic opportunities are dependent upon the
state of society; the objects aimed at, the rewards
sought for, are what they are because of social admiration,
prestige, competition and power. If money-making
is morally obnoxious it is because of the way these
<span class="pb" id="Pg318"></span>
social facts are handled, not because a money-making
man has withdrawn from society into an isolated selfhood
or turned his back upon society. His "individualism"
is not found in his original nature but in his
habits acquired under social influences. It is found in
his concrete aims, and these are reflexes of social conditions.
Well-grounded moral objection to a mode of
conduct rests upon the kind of social connections that
figure, not upon lack of social aim. A man may attempt
to utilize social relationships for his own advantage
in an inequitable way; he may intentionally
or unconsciously try to make them feed one of his own
appetites. Then he is denounced as egoistic. But both
his course of action and the disapproval he is subject
to are facts <em>within</em> society. They are social phenomena.
He pursues his unjust advantage as a social
asset.</p>
<p>Explicit recognition of this fact is a prerequisite of
improvement in moral education and of an intelligent
understanding of the chief ideas or "categories" of
morals. Morals is as much a matter of interaction of
a person with his social environment as walking is an
interaction of legs with a physical environment. The
character of walking depends upon the strength and
competency of legs. But it also depends upon whether
a man is walking in a bog or on a paved street, upon
whether there is a safeguarded path set aside or whether
he has to walk amid dangerous vehicles. If the standard
of morals is low it is because the education given
by the interaction of the individual with his social environment
<span class="pb" id="Pg319"></span>
is defective. Of what avail is it to preach
unassuming simplicity and contentment of life when
communal admiration goes to the man who "succeeds"—who
makes himself conspicuous and envied because of
command of money and other forms of power? If a
child gets on by peevishness or intrigue, then others
are his accomplices who assist in the habits which are
built up. The notion that an abstract ready-made
conscience exists in individuals and that it is only necessary
to make an occasional appeal to it and to indulge
in occasional crude rebukes and punishments, is associated
with the causes of lack of definitive and orderly
moral advance. For it is associated with lack of attention
to social forces.</p>
<p>There is a peculiar inconsistency in the current idea
that morals <em>ought</em> to be social. The introduction of
the moral "ought" into the idea contains an implicit
assertion that morals depend upon something apart
from social relations. Morals <em>are</em> social. The question
of ought, should be, is a question of better and
worse <em>in</em> social affairs. The extent to which the weight
of theories has been thrown against the perception of
the place of social ties and connections in moral activity
is a fair measure of the extent to which social forces
work blindly and develop an accidental morality. The
chief obstacle for example to recognizing the truth of
a proposition frequently set forth in these pages to the
effect that all conduct is potential, if not actual, matter
of moral judgment is the habit of identifying moral
judgment with praise and blame. So great is the influence
<span class="pb" id="Pg320"></span>
of this habit that it is safe to say that every
professed moralist when he leaves the pages of theory
and faces some actual item of his own or others' behavior,
first or "instinctively" thinks of acts as moral
or non-moral in the degree in which they are exposed to
condemnation or approval. Now this kind of judgment
is certainly not one which could profitably be dispensed
with. Its influence is much needed. But the tendency
to equate it with all moral judgment is largely responsible
for the current idea that there is a sharp
line between moral conduct and a larger region of non-moral
conduct which is a matter of expediency, shrewdness,
success or manners.</p>
<p>Moreover this tendency is a chief reason why the
social forces effective in shaping actual morality work
blindly and unsatisfactorily. Judgment in which the
emphasis falls upon blame and approbation has more
heat than light. It is more emotional than intellectual.
It is guided by custom, personal convenience and resentment
rather than by insight into causes and consequences.
It makes toward reducing moral instruction,
the educative influence of social opinion, to an
immediate personal matter, that is to say, to an adjustment
of personal likes and dislikes. Fault-finding creates
resentment in the one blamed, and approval, complacency,
rather than a habit of scrutinizing conduct
objectively. It puts those who are sensitive to the
judgments of others in a standing defensive attitude,
creating an apologetic, self-accusing and self-exculpating
habit of mind when what is needed is an impersonal
<span class="pb" id="Pg321"></span>
impartial habit of observation. "Moral" persons get
so occupied with defending their conduct from real and
imagined criticism that they have little time left to see
what their acts really amount to, and the habit of self-blame
inevitably extends to include others since it is a
habit.</p>
<p>Now it is a wholesome thing for any one to be
made aware that thoughtless, self-centered action on
his part exposes him to the indignation and dislike of
others. There is no one who can be safely trusted to
be exempt from immediate reactions of criticism, and
there are few who do not need to be braced by occasional
expressions of approval. But these influences are
immensely overdone in comparison with the assistance
that might be given by the influence of social judgments
which operate without accompaniments of praise
and blame; which enable an individual to see for himself
what he is doing, and which put him in command of
a method of analyzing the obscure and usually unavowed
forces which move him to act. We need a permeation
of judgments on conduct by the method and
materials of a science of human nature. Without such
enlightenment even the best-intentioned attempts at
the moral guidance and improvement of others often
eventuate in tragedies of misunderstanding and division,
as is so often seen in the relations of parents and
children.</p>
<p>The development therefore of a more adequate science
of human nature is a matter of first-rate importance.
The present revolt against the notion that psychology
<span class="pb" id="Pg322"></span>
is a science of consciousness may well turn out
in the future to be the beginning of a definitive turn
in thought and action. Historically there are good
reasons for the isolation and exaggeration of the conscious
phase of human action, an isolation which forgot
that "conscious" is an adjective of some acts and
which erected the resulting abstraction, "consciousness,"
into a noun, an existence separate and complete.
These reasons are interesting not only to the student
of technical philosophy but also to the student of the
history of culture and even of politics. They have to
do with the attempt to drag realities out of occult essences
and hidden forces and get them into the light of
day. They were part of the general movement called
phenomenalism, and of the growing importance of individual
life and private voluntary concerns. But the
effect was to isolate the individual from his connections
both with his fellows and with nature, and thus to create
an artificial human nature, one not capable of being
understood and effectively directed on the basis of
analytic understanding. It shut out from view, not to
say from scientific examination, the forces which really
move human nature. It took a few surface phenomena
for the whole story of significant human motive-forces
and acts.</p>
<p>As a consequence physical science and its technological
applications were highly developed while the science
of man, moral science, is backward. I believe
that it is not possible to estimate how much of the difficulties
of the present world situation are due to the
<span class="pb" id="Pg323"></span>
disproportion and unbalance thus introduced into affairs.
It would have seemed absurd to say in the seventeenth
century that in the end the alteration in
methods of physical investigation which was then beginning
would prove more important than the religious
wars of that century. Yet the wars marked the end
of one era; the dawn of physical science the beginning
of a new one. And a trained imagination may discover
that the nationalistic and economic wars which are the
chief outward mark of the present are in the end to be
less significant than the development of a science of
human nature now inchoate.</p>
<p>It sounds academic to say that substantial bettering
of social relations waits upon the growth of a scientific
social psychology. For the term suggests something
specialized and remote. But the formation of habits of
belief, desire and judgment is going on at every instant
under the influence of the conditions set by men's
contact, intercourse and associations with one another.
This is the fundamental fact in social life and in personal
character. It is the fact about which traditional
human science gives no enlightenment—a fact which
this traditional science blurs and virtually denies. The
enormous rôle played in popular morals by appeal to
the supernatural and quasi-magical is in effect a desperate
admission of the futility of our science. Consequently
the whole matter of the formation of the predispositions
which effectively control human relationships
is left to accident, to custom and immediate personal
likings, resentments and ambitions. It is a commonplace
<span class="pb" id="Pg324"></span>
that modern industry and commerce are conditioned
upon a control of physical energies due to
proper methods of physical inquiry and analysis. We
have no social arts which are comparable because we
have so nearly nothing in the way of psychological science.
Yet through the development of physical science,
and especially of chemistry, biology, physiology, medicine
and anthropology we now have the basis for the
development of such a science of man. Signs of its
coming into existence are present in the movements in
clinical, behavioristic and social (in its narrower sense)
psychology.</p>
<p>At present we not only have no assured means of
forming character except crude devices of blame, praise,
exhortation and punishment, but the very meaning of
the general notions of moral inquiry is matter of doubt
and dispute. The reason is that these notions are discussed
in isolation from the concrete facts of the interactions
of human beings with one another—an abstraction
as fatal as was the old discussion of phlogiston,
gravity and vital force apart from concrete correlations
of changing events with one another. Take
for example such a basic conception as that of Right
involving the nature of authority in conduct. There
is no need here to rehearse the multitude of contending
views which give evidence that discussion of this matter
is still in the realm of opinion. We content ourselves
with pointing out that this notion is the last resort of
the anti-empirical school in morals and that it proves
the effect of neglect of social conditions.</p>
<p><span class="pb" id="Pg325"></span>
In effect its adherents argue as follows: "Let us concede
that concrete ideas about right and wrong and
particular notions of what is obligatory have grown up
within experience. But we cannot admit this about the
idea of Right, of Obligation itself. Why does moral
authority exist at all? Why is the claim of the Right
recognized in conscience even by those who violate it
in deed? Our opponents say that such and such a
course is wise, expedient, better. But <em>why</em> act for the
wise, or good, or better? Why not follow our own immediate
devices if we are so inclined? There is only
one answer: We have a moral nature, a conscience, call
it what you will. And this nature responds directly in
acknowledgment of the supreme authority of the Right
over all claims of inclination and habit. We may not
act in accordance with this acknowledgment, but we
still know that the authority of the moral law, although
not its power, is unquestionable. Men may differ indefinitely
according to what their experience has been as
to just <em>what</em> is Right, what its contents are. But they
all spontaneously agree in recognizing the supremacy of
the claims of whatever is thought of as Right. Otherwise
there would be no such thing as morality, but
merely calculations of how to satisfy <ins class="corr" title="desire." id="Corr_325_">desire."</ins></p>
<p>Grant the foregoing argument, and all the apparatus
of abstract moralism follows in its wake. A remote
goal of perfection, ideals that are contrary in a wholesale
way to what is actual, a free will of arbitrary
choice; all of these conceptions band themselves together
with that of a non-empirical authority of Right
<span class="pb" id="Pg326"></span>
and a non-empirical conscience which acknowledges it.
They constitute its ceremonial or formal train.</p>
<p>Why, indeed, acknowledge the authority of Right?
That many persons do not acknowledge it in fact, in
action, and that all persons ignore it at times, is assumed
by the argument. Just what is the significance
of an alleged recognition of a supremacy which is continually
denied in fact? How much would be lost if it
were dropped out, and we were left face to face with
actual facts? If a man lived alone in the world there
might be some sense in the question "Why be moral?"
were it not for one thing: No such question would then
arise. As it is, we live in a world where other persons
live too. Our acts affect them. They perceive these
effects, and react upon us in consequence. Because they
are living beings they make demands upon us for certain
things from us. They approve and condemn—not
in abstract theory but in what they do to us. The answer
to the question "Why not put your hand in the
fire?" is the answer of fact. If you do your hand will
be burnt. The answer to the question why acknowledge
the right is of the same sort. For Right is only an
abstract name for the multitude of concrete demands
in action which others impress upon us, and of which
we are obliged, if we would live, to take some account.
Its authority is the exigency of their demands, the efficacy
of their insistencies. There may be good ground
for the contention that in theory the idea of the right
is subordinate to that of the good, being a statement
of the course proper to attain good. But in fact it
<span class="pb" id="Pg327"></span>
signifies the totality of social pressures exercised upon
us to induce us to think and desire in certain ways.
Hence the right can in fact become the road to the good
only as the elements that compose this unremitting
pressure are enlightened, only as social relationships
become themselves reasonable.</p>
<p>It will be retorted that all pressure is a non-moral
affair partaking of force, not of right; that right must
be ideal. Thus we are invited to enter again the circle
in which the ideal has no force and social actualities no
ideal quality. We refuse the invitation because social
pressure is involved in our own lives, as much so as the
air we breathe and the ground we walk upon. If we
had desires, judgments, plans, in short a mind, apart
from social connections, then the latter would be external
and their action might be regarded as that of a non-moral
force. But we live mentally as physically only
<em>in</em> and <em>because</em> of our environment. Social pressure is
but a name for the interactions which are always going
on and in which we participate, living so far as we partake
and dying so far as we do not. The pressure is
not ideal but empirical, yet empirical here means only
actual. It calls attention to the fact that considerations
of right are claims originating not outside of life,
but within it. They are "ideal" in precisely the degree
in which we intelligently recognize and act upon
them, just as colors and canvas become ideal when
used in ways that give an added meaning to life.</p>
<p>Accordingly failure to recognize the authority of
right means defect in effective apprehension of the realities
<span class="pb" id="Pg328"></span>
of human association, not an arbitrary exercise of
free will. This deficiency and perversion in apprehension
indicates a defect in education—that is to say, in
the operation of actual conditions, in the consequences
upon desire and thought of existing interactions and
interdependencies. It is false that every person has a
consciousness of the supreme authority of right and
then misconceives it or ignores it in action. One has
such a sense of the claims of social relationships as
those relationships enforce in one's desires and observations.
The belief in a separate, ideal or transcendental,
practically ineffectual Right is a reflex of the
inadequacy with which existing institutions perform
their educative office—their office in generating observation
of social continuities. It is an endeavor to
"rationalize" this defect. Like all rationalizations, it
operates to divert attention from the real state of
affairs. Thus it helps maintain the conditions which
created it, standing in the way of effort to make our
institutions more humane and equitable. A theoretical
acknowledgment of the supreme authority of Right, of
moral law, gets twisted into an effectual substitute for
acts which would better the customs which now produce
vague, dull, halting and evasive observation of
actual social ties. We are not caught in a circle; we
traverse a spiral in which social customs generate some
consciousness of interdependencies, and this consciousness
is embodied in acts which in improving the environment
generate new perceptions of social ties, and so
on forever. The relationships, the interactions are forever
<span class="pb" id="Pg329"></span>
there as fact, but they acquire meaning only in
the desires, judgments and purposes they awaken.</p>
<p>We recur to our fundamental propositions. Morals
is connected with actualities of existence, not with
ideals, ends and obligations independent of concrete
actualities. The facts upon which it depends are those
which arise out of active connections of human beings
with one another, the consequences of their mutually
intertwined activities in the life of desire, belief, judgment,
satisfaction and dissatisfaction. In this sense
conduct and hence morals are social: they are not just
things which <em>ought</em> to be social and which fail to come
up to the scratch. But there are enormous differences
of better and worse in the quality of what is social.
Ideal morals begin with the perception of these differences.
Human interaction and ties are there, are
operative in any case. But they can be regulated, employed
in an orderly way for good only as we know how
to observe them. And they cannot be observed aright,
they cannot be understood and utilized, when the mind
is left to itself to work without the aid of science. For
the natural unaided mind means precisely the habits
of belief, thought and desire which have been accidentally
generated and confirmed by social institutions or
customs. But with all their admixture of accident and
reasonableness we have at last reached a point where
social conditions create a mind capable of scientific
outlook and inquiry. To foster and develop this spirit
is the social obligation of the present because it is its
urgent need.</p>
<p><span class="pb" id="Pg330"></span>
Yet the last word is not with obligation nor with the
future. Infinite relationships of man with his fellows
and with nature already exist. The ideal means, as
we have seen, a sense of these encompassing continuities
with their infinite reach. This meaning even now
attaches to present activities because they are set in a
whole to which they belong and which belongs to them.
Even in the midst of conflict, struggle and defeat a
consciousness is possible of the enduring and comprehending
whole.</p>
<p>To be grasped and held this consciousness needs, like
every form of consciousness, objects, symbols. In the
past men have sought many symbols which no longer
serve, especially since men have been idolators worshiping
symbols as things. Yet within these symbols which
have so often claimed to be realities and which have imposed
themselves as dogmas and intolerances, there has
rarely been absent some trace of a vital and enduring
reality, that of a community of life in which continuities
of existence are consummated. Consciousness of the
whole has been connected with reverences, affections,
and loyalties which are communal. But special ways of
expressing the communal sense have been established.
They have been limited to a select social group; they
have hardened into obligatory rites and been imposed
as conditions of salvation. Religion has lost itself in
cults, dogmas and myths. Consequently the office of
religion as sense of community and one's place in
it has been lost. In effect religion has been distorted
into a possession—or burden—of a limited part of
<span class="pb" id="Pg331"></span>
human nature, of a limited portion of humanity which
finds no way to universalize religion except by imposing
its own dogmas and ceremonies upon others; of a limited
class within a partial group; priests, saints, a
church. Thus other gods have been set up before the
one God. Religion as a sense of the whole is the most
individualized of all things, the most spontaneous, undefinable
and varied. For individuality signifies unique
connections in the whole. Yet it has been perverted
into something uniform and immutable. It has been
formulated into fixed and defined beliefs expressed in
required acts and ceremonies. Instead of marking the
freedom and peace of the individual as a member of an
infinite whole, it has been petrified into a slavery of
thought and sentiment, an intolerant superiority on
the part of the few and an intolerable burden on the
part of the many.</p>
<p>Yet every act may carry within itself a consoling and
supporting consciousness of the whole to which it
belongs and which in some sense belongs to it. With
responsibility for the intelligent determination of particular
acts may go a joyful emancipation from the
burden for responsibility for the whole which sustains
them, giving them their final outcome and quality.
There is a conceit fostered by perversion of religion
which assimilates the universe to our personal desires;
but there is also a conceit of carrying the load of the
universe from which religion liberates us. Within the
flickering inconsequential acts of separate selves dwells
a sense of the whole which claims and dignifies them.
<span class="pb" id="Pg332"></span>
In its presence we put off mortality and live in the universal.
The life of the community in which we live
and have our being is the fit symbol of this relationship.
The acts in which we express our perception of the ties
which bind us to others are its only rites and ceremonies.</p>
<hr />
<h2><span class="pb" id="Pg333"></span>INDEX</h2>
<p>Absentmindedness, <SPAN href="#Pg173">173</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Accident" id="Accident"></SPAN>Accidents, in history, <SPAN href="#Pg101">101</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">in consequences, <SPAN href="#Pg049">49</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg051">51</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg206">206–208</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg241">241</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg253">253</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg304">304</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg309">309</SPAN></span><br/>
Acquisition, <SPAN href="#Pg116">116–118</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg143">143–148</SPAN><br/>
Activity is natural, <SPAN href="#Pg118">118–123</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg160">160</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg226">226</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg293">293</SPAN><br/>
Aims, <em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Consequences">Consequences</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Ends">Ends</SPAN><br/>
Alexander M., <SPAN href="#Pg028">28</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg036">36</SPAN><br/>
Altruism, <SPAN href="#Pg133">133</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg293">293</SPAN><br/>
Analysis, <SPAN href="#Pg183">183</SPAN><br/>
Anger, <SPAN href="#Pg090">90</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg152">152</SPAN><br/>
Appetite, <SPAN href="#Pg007">7</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg275">275</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Impulse">Impulse</SPAN></span><br/>
Aristotle, <SPAN href="#Pg033">33</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg109">109</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg174">174</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg224">224</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg290">290</SPAN><br/>
Arts, <SPAN href="#Pg015">15</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg023">23</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg071">71</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg159">159–164</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg263">263</SPAN><br/>
Atomism moral, <SPAN href="#Pg243">243</SPAN><br/>
Attitude, <SPAN href="#Pg041">41</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Habit">Habit</SPAN></span><br/>
Authority, <SPAN href="#Pg002">2</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg065">65</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg072">72</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg079">79</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg187">187</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg324">324</SPAN></p>
<p>Benevolence, <SPAN href="#Pg133">133</SPAN><br/>
Bergson, <SPAN href="#Pg073">73</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg178">178</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg245">245</SPAN><br/>
Blame, <SPAN href="#Pg018">18</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg121">121</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg320">320</SPAN></p>
<p>Causation, <SPAN href="#Pg018">18</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg044">44</SPAN><br/>
Calculation, <SPAN href="#Pg189">189</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg199">199–209</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Deliberation">Deliberation</SPAN></span><br/>
Casuistry, <SPAN href="#Pg240">240</SPAN><br/>
Certainty, love of, <SPAN href="#Pg236">236</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Character" id="Character"></SPAN>Character, defined, <SPAN href="#Pg038">38</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">and consequences, <SPAN href="#Pg047">47</SPAN></span><br/>
Childhood, <SPAN href="#Pg002">2</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg064">64</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg089">89</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg096">96</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg099">99</SPAN><br/>
Choice, <SPAN href="#Pg192">192</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg304">304</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg311">311</SPAN><br/>
Classes, <SPAN href="#Pg002">2</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg082">82</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg270">270</SPAN><br/>
Classification, <SPAN href="#Pg131">131</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg244">244</SPAN><br/>
Codes, <SPAN href="#Pg103">103</SPAN><br/>
Compensatory, <SPAN href="#Pg008">8</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg030">30</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg033">33</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg257">257</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg275">275</SPAN><br/>
Conduct, <em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Character">Character</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Habit">Habit</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Impulse">Impulse</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Intelligence">Intelligence</SPAN><br/>
Confidence, <SPAN href="#Pg139">139</SPAN><br/>
Conflict, <SPAN href="#Pg012">12</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg039">39</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg066">66</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg082">82</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg194">194</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg208">208</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg217">217</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg300">300</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Conscience" id="Conscience"></SPAN>Conscience, <SPAN href="#Pg184">184–188</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg314">314</SPAN><br/>
Consciousness, <SPAN href="#Pg062">62</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg179">179</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg184">184</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg208">208</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Consequences" id="Consequences"></SPAN>Consequences, and motives, <SPAN href="#Pg045">45–47</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">and aims, <SPAN href="#Pg225">225–229</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg245">245–247</SPAN></span><br/>
Conservatism, <SPAN href="#Pg066">66</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg106">106</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg168">168</SPAN><br/>
Continuity, <SPAN href="#Pg012">12</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg232">232</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg239">239</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg244">244</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg259">259</SPAN><br/>
Control, <SPAN href="#Pg021">21</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg023">23</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg037">37</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg101">101</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg139">139</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg148">148</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg266">266–270</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Accident">Accident</SPAN></span><br/>
Conventions, <SPAN href="#Pg006">6</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg097">97</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg166">166</SPAN><br/>
Crowd psychology, <SPAN href="#Pg060">60</SPAN><br/>
Creative and acquisitive, <SPAN href="#Pg143">143–148</SPAN><br/>
Customs and habits, <SPAN href="#Pg058">58–69</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">and standards, <SPAN href="#Pg075">75–83</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">rigidity, <SPAN href="#Pg103">103–105</SPAN></span></p>
<p><SPAN name="Deliberation" id="Deliberation"></SPAN>Deliberation, <SPAN href="#Pg189">189–209</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">as discovery, <SPAN href="#Pg216">216</SPAN></span><br/>
Democracy, <SPAN href="#Footnote_3_">61n</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg066">66</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg072">72</SPAN><br/>
Desire, <SPAN href="#Pg024">24</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg033">33</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg194">194</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg234">234</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg299">299</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg304">304</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">and intelligence, <SPAN href="#Pg248">248–264</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">object of, <SPAN href="#Pg249">249–252</SPAN></span><br/>
Disposition, <SPAN href="#Pg041">41</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Habit">Habit</SPAN></span><br/>
Docility, <SPAN href="#Pg064">64</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg097">97</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Dualism" id="Dualism"></SPAN>Dualism, <SPAN href="#Pg008">8</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg012">12</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg040">40</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg055">55</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg067">67</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg071">71</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg147">147</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg275">275</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg309">309</SPAN></p>
<p>Economic man, <SPAN href="#Pg220">220</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Economics" id="Economics"></SPAN>Economics, <SPAN href="#Pg009">9</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg012">12</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg120">120–124</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg132">132</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg143">143–148</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg212">212–221</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg270">270–273</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg305">305</SPAN><br/>
Education, <SPAN href="#Pg064">64</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg072">72</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg091">91</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg107">107</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg270">270</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg320">320</SPAN><br/>
Egotism, <SPAN href="#Pg007">7</SPAN><br/>
Emerson, <SPAN href="#Pg100">100</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg144">144</SPAN><br/>
Emotion, <SPAN href="#Pg075">75</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg083">83</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg255">255</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg264">264</SPAN><br/>
<span class="pb" id="Pg334"></span>
<SPAN name="Ends" id="Ends"></SPAN>End, <SPAN href="#Pg028">28</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg034">34–37</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">knowledge as, <SPAN href="#Pg187">187</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg215">215</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">nature of, <SPAN href="#Pg223">223–237</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">of desire, <SPAN href="#Pg250">250</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg261">261</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">and means, <SPAN href="#Pg269">269–272</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Consequences">Consequences</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Means">Means</SPAN></span><br/>
<SPAN name="Environments" id="Environments"></SPAN>Environments, <SPAN href="#Pg002">2</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg010">10</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg015">15</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg018">18</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg021">21</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg051">51</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg151">151</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg159">159</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg179">179</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg316">316</SPAN><br/>
Epicureanism, <SPAN href="#Pg205">205</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg291">291</SPAN><br/>
Equilibration, <SPAN href="#Pg179">179</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg252">252</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Evolution" id="Evolution"></SPAN>Evolution, <SPAN href="#Pg284">284–287</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg297">297</SPAN><br/>
Execution, of desires, <SPAN href="#Pg033">33–35</SPAN><br/>
Expediency, <SPAN href="#Pg049">49</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg189">189</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg210">210</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Deliberation">Deliberation</SPAN></span><br/>
Experience, <SPAN href="#Pg031">31</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg245">245</SPAN><br/>
Experimentation, moral, <SPAN href="#Pg056">56</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg307">307</SPAN></p>
<p>Fallacy, philosophic, <SPAN href="#Pg175">175</SPAN><br/>
Fanaticism, <SPAN href="#Pg228">228</SPAN><br/>
<ins class="corr" title="Phantasies" id="Corr_334_">Fantasies</ins>, <SPAN href="#Pg158">158</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg164">164</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg236">236</SPAN><br/>
Fear, <SPAN href="#Pg111">111</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg132">132–133</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg154">154–155</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg237">237</SPAN><br/>
Fiat of will, <SPAN href="#Pg029">29</SPAN><br/>
Foresight, <SPAN href="#Pg204">204–206</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg238">238</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg265">265–270</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Deliberation">Deliberation</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Ends">Ends</SPAN></span><br/>
Freedom, <SPAN href="#Pg008">8</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg165">165</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">three phases of, <SPAN href="#Pg303">303–313</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Will">Will</SPAN></span><br/>
Functions, <SPAN href="#Pg018">18</SPAN></p>
<p>Gain, <SPAN href="#Pg117">117</SPAN><br/>
Goal, <SPAN href="#Pg260">260</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg265">265</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg274">274</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg281">281</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg287">287–289</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Evolution">Evolution</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Perfection">Perfection</SPAN></span><br/>
Good, <SPAN href="#Pg002">2</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg044">44</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg210">210–222</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg274">274</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg278">278</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Goodness" id="Goodness"></SPAN>Goodness, <SPAN href="#Pg004">4–8</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg016">16</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg043">43–45</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg048">48</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg067">67</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg227">227</SPAN><br/>
Good-will, <SPAN href="#Pg044">44</SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN name="Habit" id="Habit"></SPAN>Habits, place in conduct, <SPAN href="#Pg014">14–88</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">and desire, <SPAN href="#Pg024">24</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">as functions, <SPAN href="#Pg014">14</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">as arts or abilities, <SPAN href="#Pg015">15</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg064">64</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg066">66</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg071">71</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg170">170</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">and thought, <SPAN href="#Pg031">31–33</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg066">66–69</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg172">172–180</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg182">182</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">definition, <SPAN href="#Pg041">41</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">and impulses, <SPAN href="#Pg090">90–98</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg107">107–111</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">and principles, <SPAN href="#Pg238">238</SPAN></span><br/>
Harmony, natural, <SPAN href="#Pg159">159</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg167">167</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg298">298</SPAN><br/>
Hedonistic calculus, <SPAN href="#Pg204">204</SPAN><br/>
Hegel, <SPAN href="#Pg312">312</SPAN><br/>
Helvetius, <SPAN href="#Pg106">106</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg300">300</SPAN><br/>
Herd-instinct, <SPAN href="#Pg004">4</SPAN><br/>
History, <SPAN href="#Pg101">101</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg110">110</SPAN><br/>
Hobbes, <SPAN href="#Pg133">133</SPAN><br/>
Human nature, <SPAN href="#Pg001">1</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">and morals, <SPAN href="#Pg001">1–13</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg295">295</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">alterability, <SPAN href="#Pg106">106–124</SPAN></span><br/>
Humility, <SPAN href="#Pg289">289</SPAN><br/>
Hypocrisy, <SPAN href="#Pg006">6</SPAN><br/>
Hypothesis, moral, <SPAN href="#Pg239">239</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg243">243</SPAN></p>
<p>Ideas, <em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Ends">Ends</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Thought">Thought</SPAN><br/>
Ideals and Idealism, <SPAN href="#Pg002">2</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg008">8</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg050">50</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg068">68</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg077">77</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg081">81</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg099">99</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg157">157</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg166">166</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg184">184</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg233">233</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg236">236</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg255">255</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg259">259–264</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg274">274</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg282">282–288</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg301">301</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg331">331</SPAN><br/>
Imagination, <SPAN href="#Pg052">52</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg163">163</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg190">190–192</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg204">204</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg225">225</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg234">234</SPAN><br/>
Imitation, <SPAN href="#Pg066">66</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg097">97</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg132">132</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Impulse" id="Impulse"></SPAN>Impulse, place in conduct, <SPAN href="#Pg089">89–171</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">secondary, <SPAN href="#Pg089">89</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">intermediary, <SPAN href="#Pg169">169–170</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">as means of reorganization, <SPAN href="#Pg093">93</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg102">102</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg104">104</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg179">179</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">plastic, <SPAN href="#Pg095">95</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">same as human instincts, <SPAN href="#Footnote_5_">105n</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">and habit, <SPAN href="#Pg107">107–111</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">false simplification, <SPAN href="#Pg131">131–149</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">and reason, <SPAN href="#Pg196">196</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg254">254</SPAN></span><br/>
Individualism, <SPAN href="#Pg007">7</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg085">85</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg093">93</SPAN><br/>
Industry, <SPAN href="#Pg011">11</SPAN><br/>
Infantilisms, <SPAN href="#Pg098">98</SPAN><br/>
Instinct, not fixed, <SPAN href="#Pg149">149–168</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">and knowledge, <SPAN href="#Pg178">178</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Impulse">Impulse</SPAN></span><br/>
Institutions, <SPAN href="#Pg009">9</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg080">80</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg102">102</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg111">111</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg166">166</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Intelligence" id="Intelligence"></SPAN>Intelligence, <SPAN href="#Pg010">10</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg013">13</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg051">51</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg299">299</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg312">312</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">place of, in conduct, <SPAN href="#Pg172">172–277</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">relation to habits, <SPAN href="#Pg172">172–180</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg228">228</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">and desire, <SPAN href="#Pg248">248–264</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg276">276</SPAN></span><br/>
Interpenetration of habits, <SPAN href="#Pg037">37–39</SPAN><br/>
Intuitions, <SPAN href="#Pg033">33</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg188">188</SPAN></p>
<p>James, Wm., <SPAN href="#Pg112">112</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg179">179</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg195">195</SPAN><br/>
Justice, <SPAN href="#Pg018">18</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg052">52</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg198">198</SPAN></p>
<p>Kant, <SPAN href="#Pg044">44</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg049">49</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg055">55</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg245">245</SPAN><br/>
Knowledge, moral, <SPAN href="#Pg181">181–188</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Conscience">Conscience</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Intelligence">Intelligence</SPAN></span></p>
<p>Labor, <SPAN href="#Pg121">121</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg144">144</SPAN><br/>
Language, <SPAN href="#Pg058">58</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg079">79</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg095">95</SPAN><br/>
<span class="pb" id="Pg335"></span>
Le Bon, <SPAN href="#Pg061">61</SPAN><br/>
Liberalism, <SPAN href="#Pg305">305</SPAN><br/>
Locke, <SPAN href="#Pg106">106</SPAN></p>
<p>Marx, <SPAN href="#Pg154">154</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg273">273</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg300">300</SPAN><br/>
Magic, <SPAN href="#Pg020">20</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg026">26</SPAN><br/>
Meaning, <SPAN href="#Pg037">37</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg090">90</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg151">151</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg207">207</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg262">262</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg271">271</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg280">280</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Means" id="Means"></SPAN>Means, <SPAN href="#Pg020">20</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">relation to ends, <SPAN href="#Pg025">25–36</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg218">218–220</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg251">251</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Habit">Habit</SPAN></span><br/>
Mechanization, <SPAN href="#Pg028">28</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg070">70</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg096">96</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg144">144</SPAN><br/>
Mediation, <SPAN href="#Pg197">197</SPAN><br/>
Mind, <SPAN href="#Pg061">61</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg095">95</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">and habit, <SPAN href="#Pg175">175–180</SPAN></span><br/>
Mind and body, <SPAN href="#Pg030">30</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg067">67</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg071">71</SPAN><br/>
Mitchell, W. C., <SPAN href="#Pg213">213</SPAN><br/>
Moore, G. E., <SPAN href="#Footnote_8_">241n</SPAN><br/>
Morals, introduction, <SPAN href="#Pg040">40</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">conclusion, as objective, <SPAN href="#Pg052">52</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">of art, <SPAN href="#Pg167">167</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">scope, <SPAN href="#Pg278">278–281</SPAN></span><br/>
Motives, <SPAN href="#Pg043">43–45</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg118">118–122</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg213">213</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg231">231</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg329">329</SPAN></p>
<p>Natural law and morals, <SPAN href="#Pg296">296–300</SPAN><br/>
Necessity, <SPAN href="#Pg312">312</SPAN><br/>
Nirvana, <SPAN href="#Pg175">175</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg286">286</SPAN><br/>
Non-moral, <SPAN href="#Pg008">8</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg027">27</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg040">40</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg188">188</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg230">230</SPAN></p>
<p>Occult, <SPAN href="#Pg011">11</SPAN><br/>
Oligarchy, <SPAN href="#Pg002">2–3</SPAN><br/>
Optimism, <SPAN href="#Pg286">286–288</SPAN><br/>
Organization, <SPAN href="#Pg306">306</SPAN></p>
<p>Passion, <SPAN href="#Pg009">9</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg193">193–196</SPAN><br/>
Pathology, <SPAN href="#Pg004">4</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg050">50</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Perfection" id="Perfection"></SPAN>Perfection, <SPAN href="#Pg173">173–175</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg223">223</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg282">282</SPAN><br/>
Pessimism, <SPAN href="#Pg286">286</SPAN><br/>
Plato, <SPAN href="#Pg050">50</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg078">78</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg134">134</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg290">290</SPAN><br/>
Play, <SPAN href="#Pg159">159–164</SPAN><br/>
Pleasure, <SPAN href="#Pg158">158</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg200">200–205</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg250">250</SPAN><br/>
Posture, <SPAN href="#Pg032">32</SPAN><br/>
Potentiality, <SPAN href="#Pg037">37</SPAN><br/>
Power, will to, <SPAN href="#Pg140">140–142</SPAN><br/>
Pragmatic knowing, <SPAN href="#Pg181">181–188</SPAN><br/>
Principles, <SPAN href="#Pg002">2</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">and tendencies, <SPAN href="#Pg049">49</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">nature of, <SPAN href="#Pg238">238–247</SPAN></span><br/>
Private, <SPAN href="#Pg009">9</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg016">16</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg043">43</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg085">85</SPAN><br/>
Process and product, <SPAN href="#Pg142">142–143</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg280">280</SPAN><br/>
Progress, <SPAN href="#Pg010">10</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg021">21</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg093">93</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg096">96</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg101">101</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Footnote_5_">105n</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">in science, <SPAN href="#Pg149">149</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">nature of, <SPAN href="#Pg281">281–288</SPAN></span><br/>
Property, <SPAN href="#Pg116">116–118</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Economics">Economics</SPAN></span><br/>
Psycho-analysis, <SPAN href="#Pg034">34</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg086">86</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg133">133</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg153">153</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg252">252</SPAN><br/>
Psychology and moral theory, <SPAN href="#Pg012">12</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg046">46</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg091">91</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">social, <SPAN href="#Pg060">60–63</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg084">84–88</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">current, <SPAN href="#Pg118">118</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg135">135</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg147">147</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg155">155</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">and scientific method, <SPAN href="#Pg150">150</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg322">322–324</SPAN></span><br/>
Punishment, <SPAN href="#Pg018">18</SPAN><br/>
Puritanism, <SPAN href="#Pg005">5</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg157">157</SPAN><br/>
Purpose, <em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Ends">Ends</SPAN></p>
<p>Radicalism, <SPAN href="#Pg168">168</SPAN><br/>
Reactions, <SPAN href="#Pg157">157</SPAN><br/>
Realism, <SPAN href="#Pg176">176</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg256">256</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg298">298</SPAN><br/>
Reason, pure, <SPAN href="#Pg031">31</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">reasonableness, <SPAN href="#Pg067">67</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg077">77</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg193">193–198</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg215">215</SPAN></span><br/>
Rebellion, <SPAN href="#Pg166">166</SPAN><br/>
Reconstruction, <SPAN href="#Pg164">164</SPAN><br/>
Religion, <SPAN href="#Pg005">5</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg263">263</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg330">330–332</SPAN><br/>
Responsibility, <SPAN href="#Pg315">315</SPAN><br/>
Revolution, <SPAN href="#Pg010">10</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg108">108</SPAN><br/>
Right, <SPAN href="#Pg324">324–328</SPAN><br/>
Romanticism, <SPAN href="#Pg006">6</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg100">100</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg166">166</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg256">256</SPAN><br/>
Routine, <SPAN href="#Pg042">42</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg066">66</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg070">70</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg098">98</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg211">211</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg232">232</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg238">238</SPAN></p>
<p>Satisfaction, <SPAN href="#Pg140">140</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg158">158</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg175">175</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg210">210</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg213">213</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg265">265</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg285">285</SPAN><br/>
Savagery, <SPAN href="#Pg093">93</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg101">101</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg103">103</SPAN><br/>
Science of morals, <SPAN href="#Pg003">3</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg011">11–12</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg018">18</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg056">56</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg224">224</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg243">243</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg296">296</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg321">321</SPAN><br/>
Self, <SPAN href="#Pg016">16</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg055">55</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg085">85–87</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg136">136–139</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg217">217</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg292">292</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg314">314</SPAN><br/>
Self-deception, <SPAN href="#Pg152">152</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg252">252</SPAN><br/>
Self-love, <SPAN href="#Pg134">134–139</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg293">293</SPAN><br/>
Sensations, <SPAN href="#Pg018">18</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg031">31</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg189">189</SPAN><br/>
Sentimentalism, <SPAN href="#Pg017">17</SPAN><br/>
Sex, <SPAN href="#Pg133">133</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg150">150</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg153">153</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg164">164–165</SPAN><br/>
Social, <em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Environments">Environments</SPAN><br/>
Social mind, <SPAN href="#Pg060">60–63</SPAN><br/>
<span class="pb" id="Pg336"></span>
Socrates, <SPAN href="#Pg056">56</SPAN><br/>
Soul, <SPAN href="#Pg085">85</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg094">94</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg138">138</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg176">176</SPAN><br/>
Spencer, <SPAN href="#Pg175">175</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg297">297</SPAN><br/>
Standards, <SPAN href="#Pg075">75–82</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg241">241</SPAN><br/>
Stimulation, <SPAN href="#Pg157">157</SPAN><br/>
Stimulus and response, <SPAN href="#Pg199">199–207</SPAN><br/>
Stuart, H. W., <SPAN href="#Pg218">218</SPAN><br/>
Subjective, <SPAN href="#Pg016">16</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg022">22</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg027">27</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg052">52</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg054">54</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg085">85</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg202">202</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Dualism">Dualism</SPAN></span><br/>
Sublimation, <SPAN href="#Pg141">141</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg156">156</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg164">164</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg194">194</SPAN><br/>
Success, <SPAN href="#Pg006">6</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg173">173</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg254">254</SPAN><br/>
Sumner, <SPAN href="#Pg077">77</SPAN><br/>
Suppression, <SPAN href="#Pg156">156</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg166">166</SPAN><br/>
Synthesis, <SPAN href="#Pg183">183–184</SPAN></p>
<p>Tendency, <SPAN href="#Pg049">49</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Thought" id="Thought"></SPAN>Thought, <SPAN href="#Pg030">30</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg067">67</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg098">98</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg108">108</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg171">171</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg190">190</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg200">200</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg222">222</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg258">258</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">vices of, <SPAN href="#Pg197">197</SPAN></span><br/>
Tolstoi, <SPAN href="#Pg285">285</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg312">312</SPAN><br/>
Tools, <SPAN href="#Pg025">25</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg032">32</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">intellectual, <SPAN href="#Pg244">244</SPAN></span><br/>
Transcendentalism, <SPAN href="#Pg050">50–52</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg054">54</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg081">81</SPAN></p>
<p>Universality, <SPAN href="#Pg245">245–247</SPAN><br/>
Utilitarianism, <SPAN href="#Pg050">50</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg189">189</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg199">199–209</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg211">211</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg221">221–222</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg291">291</SPAN></p>
<p>Virtues, <SPAN href="#Pg004">4</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg016">16</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg022">22</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent"><em>see</em> <SPAN href="#Goodness">Goodness</SPAN></span></p>
<p>War, <SPAN href="#Pg110">110–115</SPAN><br/>
Westermarck, <SPAN href="#Pg076">76</SPAN><br/>
<SPAN name="Will" id="Will"></SPAN>Will, and habits, <SPAN href="#Pg025">25</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg029">29</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg040">40–44</SPAN>, <SPAN href="#Pg259">259</SPAN>;<br/>
<span class="indent">will to power, <SPAN href="#Pg140">140–143</SPAN>;</span><br/>
<span class="indent">freedom of, <SPAN href="#Pg009">9</SPAN></span><br/>
Williams, M., <SPAN href="#Footnote_9_">273n</SPAN></p>
<hr />
<p class="center"><big>FOOTNOTES:</big></p>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_1_" id="Footnote_1_"
href="#FNanchor_1_" class="label">[1]</SPAN> I refer
to Alexander, "Man's Supreme Inheritance."</p>
</div>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_2_" id="Footnote_2_"
href="#FNanchor_2_" class="label">[2]</SPAN> The technique of
this process is stated in the book of Mr. Alexander already referred to,
and the theoretical statement given is borrowed from Mr. Alexander's
analysis.</p>
</div>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_3_" id="Footnote_3_"
href="#FNanchor_3_" class="label">[3]</SPAN> Mob
psychology comes under the same principles, but in a
negative aspect. The crowd and mob express a disintegration of
habits which releases impulse and renders persons susceptible
to immediate stimuli, rather than such a functioning of habits
as is found in the mind of a club or school of thought or a
political party. Leaders of an organization, that is of an interaction
having settled habits, may, however, in order to put over
some schemes deliberately resort to stimuli which will break
through the crust of ordinary custom and release impulses on
such a scale as to create a mob psychology. Since fear is a
normal reaction to the unfamiliar, dread and suspicion are the
forces most played upon to accomplish this result, together with
vast vague contrary hopes. This is an ordinary technique in
excited political campaigns, in starting war, etc. But an assimilation
like that of Le Bon of the psychology of democracy to the
psychology of a crowd in overriding individual judgment shows
lack of psychological insight. A political democracy exhibits
an overriding of thought like that seen in any convention or institution.
That is, thought is submerged in habit. In the crowd
and mob, it is submerged in undefined emotion. China and Japan
exhibit crowd psychology more frequently than do western democratic
countries. Not in my judgment because of any essentially
Oriental psychology but because of a nearer background of rigid
and solid customs conjoined with the phenomena of a period of
transition. The introduction of many novel stimuli creates occasions
where habits afford no ballast. Hence great waves of emotion
easily sweep through masses. Sometimes they are waves of
enthusiasm for the new; sometimes of violent reaction against
it—both equally undiscriminating. The war has left behind it
a somewhat similar situation in western countries.</p>
</div>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_4_" id="Footnote_4_"
href="#FNanchor_4_" class="label">[4]</SPAN> "The Origin
and Development of Moral Ideas."</p>
</div>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_5_" id="Footnote_5_"
href="#FNanchor_5_" class="label">[5]</SPAN>
The use of the words instinct and impulse as practical equivalents
is intentional, even though it may grieve critical readers.
The word instinct taken alone is still too laden with the older
notion that an instinct is always definitely organized and adapted—which
for the most part is just what it is not in human beings.
The word impulse suggests something primitive, yet loose, undirected,
initial. Man can progress as beasts cannot, precisely
because he has so many 'instincts' that they cut across one
another, so that most serviceable actions must be <em>learned</em>. In
learning habits it is possible for man to learn the habit of
learning. Then betterment becomes a conscious principle of life.</p>
</div>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_6_" id="Footnote_6_"
href="#FNanchor_6_" class="label">[6]</SPAN> I owe the
suggestion of this mode of interpreting the
hedonistic calculus of utilitarianism to Dr. Wesley Mitchell.
See his articles in <cite>Journal of Political Economy</cite>, vol. 18. Compare
also his article in <cite>Political Science Quarterly</cite>, vol. 33.</p>
</div>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_7_" id="Footnote_7_"
href="#FNanchor_7_" class="label">[7]</SPAN> So far
as I am aware Dr. H. W. Stuart was the first to point
out this difference between economic and moral valuations in his
essay in <cite>Studies in Logical Theory</cite>.</p>
</div>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_8_" id="Footnote_8_"
href="#FNanchor_8_" class="label">[8]</SPAN> Among
contemporary moralists, Mr. G. E. Moore may be
cited as almost alone in having the courage of the convictions
shared by many. He insists that it is the true business of moral
theory to enable men to arrive at precise and sure judgments in
concrete cases of moral perplexity.</p>
</div>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_9_" id="Footnote_9_"
href="#FNanchor_9_" class="label">[9]</SPAN> Acknowledgment is due "The Social Interpretation of History"
by Maurice Williams.</p>
</div>
<hr />
<p class="center"><big>CORRECTIONS:<SPAN name="Corrections" id="Corrections"></SPAN></big></p>
<table cellpadding="4" summary="Corrections" >
<tr><td>page</td><td>original</td><td>correction</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_v_">v</SPAN></td><td>13</td><td>14</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_003_">003</SPAN></td><td>of</td><td>to</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_008_">008</SPAN></td><td>pleasureable</td><td>pleasurable</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_017_">017</SPAN></td><td>retibutive</td><td>retributive</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_041_">041</SPAN></td><td>some-counteracting</td><td>some counteracting</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_074_">074</SPAN></td><td>ungoing</td><td>ongoing</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_090_">090</SPAN></td><td>mudpuddle</td><td>mud puddle</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_092_">092</SPAN></td><td>southsea</td><td>Southsea</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_123_">123</SPAN></td><td>fulfillment</td><td>fulfilment</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_145_">145</SPAN></td><td>it</td><td>is</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_163_">163</SPAN></td><td>exitents</td><td>exigents</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_211_">211</SPAN></td><td>presentation</td><td>presentation.</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_212_">212</SPAN></td><td>only</td><td>only one</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_234_">234</SPAN></td><td>phantasy</td><td>fantasy</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_236_">236</SPAN></td><td>phantasy-building</td><td>fantasy-building</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_262_">262</SPAN></td><td>unreasonble</td><td>unreasonable</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_276_">276</SPAN></td><td>an</td><td>and</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_325_">325</SPAN></td><td>desire.</td><td>desire."</td></tr>
<tr><td><SPAN href="#Corr_334_">334</SPAN></td><td>Phantasies</td><td>Fantasies</td></tr>
</table>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />