<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0005" id="link2HCH0005"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER V. THE NATURAL HISTORY OF MORALS </h2>
<p>186. The moral sentiment in Europe at present is perhaps as subtle,
belated, diverse, sensitive, and refined, as the "Science of Morals"
belonging thereto is recent, initial, awkward, and coarse-fingered:—an
interesting contrast, which sometimes becomes incarnate and obvious in the
very person of a moralist. Indeed, the expression, "Science of Morals" is,
in respect to what is designated thereby, far too presumptuous and counter
to GOOD taste,—which is always a foretaste of more modest
expressions. One ought to avow with the utmost fairness WHAT is still
necessary here for a long time, WHAT is alone proper for the present:
namely, the collection of material, the comprehensive survey and
classification of an immense domain of delicate sentiments of worth, and
distinctions of worth, which live, grow, propagate, and perish—and
perhaps attempts to give a clear idea of the recurring and more common
forms of these living crystallizations—as preparation for a THEORY
OF TYPES of morality. To be sure, people have not hitherto been so modest.
All the philosophers, with a pedantic and ridiculous seriousness, demanded
of themselves something very much higher, more pretentious, and
ceremonious, when they concerned themselves with morality as a science:
they wanted to GIVE A BASIC to morality—and every philosopher
hitherto has believed that he has given it a basis; morality itself,
however, has been regarded as something "given." How far from their
awkward pride was the seemingly insignificant problem—left in dust
and decay—of a description of forms of morality, notwithstanding
that the finest hands and senses could hardly be fine enough for it! It
was precisely owing to moral philosophers' knowing the moral facts
imperfectly, in an arbitrary epitome, or an accidental abridgement—perhaps
as the morality of their environment, their position, their church, their
Zeitgeist, their climate and zone—it was precisely because they were
badly instructed with regard to nations, eras, and past ages, and were by
no means eager to know about these matters, that they did not even come in
sight of the real problems of morals—problems which only disclose
themselves by a comparison of MANY kinds of morality. In every "Science of
Morals" hitherto, strange as it may sound, the problem of morality itself
has been OMITTED: there has been no suspicion that there was anything
problematic there! That which philosophers called "giving a basis to
morality," and endeavoured to realize, has, when seen in a right light,
proved merely a learned form of good FAITH in prevailing morality, a new
means of its EXPRESSION, consequently just a matter-of-fact within the
sphere of a definite morality, yea, in its ultimate motive, a sort of
denial that it is LAWFUL for this morality to be called in question—and
in any case the reverse of the testing, analyzing, doubting, and
vivisecting of this very faith. Hear, for instance, with what innocence—almost
worthy of honour—Schopenhauer represents his own task, and draw your
conclusions concerning the scientificness of a "Science" whose latest
master still talks in the strain of children and old wives: "The
principle," he says (page 136 of the Grundprobleme der Ethik), [Footnote:
Pages 54-55 of Schopenhauer's Basis of Morality, translated by Arthur B.
Bullock, M.A. (1903).] "the axiom about the purport of which all moralists
are PRACTICALLY agreed: neminem laede, immo omnes quantum potes juva—is
REALLY the proposition which all moral teachers strive to establish, ...
the REAL basis of ethics which has been sought, like the philosopher's
stone, for centuries."—The difficulty of establishing the
proposition referred to may indeed be great—it is well known that
Schopenhauer also was unsuccessful in his efforts; and whoever has
thoroughly realized how absurdly false and sentimental this proposition
is, in a world whose essence is Will to Power, may be reminded that
Schopenhauer, although a pessimist, ACTUALLY—played the flute...
daily after dinner: one may read about the matter in his biography. A
question by the way: a pessimist, a repudiator of God and of the world,
who MAKES A HALT at morality—who assents to morality, and plays the
flute to laede-neminem morals, what? Is that really—a pessimist?</p>
<p>187. Apart from the value of such assertions as "there is a categorical
imperative in us," one can always ask: What does such an assertion
indicate about him who makes it? There are systems of morals which are
meant to justify their author in the eyes of other people; other systems
of morals are meant to tranquilize him, and make him self-satisfied; with
other systems he wants to crucify and humble himself, with others he
wishes to take revenge, with others to conceal himself, with others to
glorify himself and gave superiority and distinction,—this system of
morals helps its author to forget, that system makes him, or something of
him, forgotten, many a moralist would like to exercise power and creative
arbitrariness over mankind, many another, perhaps, Kant especially, gives
us to understand by his morals that "what is estimable in me, is that I
know how to obey—and with you it SHALL not be otherwise than with
me!" In short, systems of morals are only a SIGN-LANGUAGE OF THE EMOTIONS.</p>
<p>188. In contrast to laisser-aller, every system of morals is a sort of
tyranny against "nature" and also against "reason", that is, however, no
objection, unless one should again decree by some system of morals, that
all kinds of tyranny and unreasonableness are unlawful What is essential
and invaluable in every system of morals, is that it is a long constraint.
In order to understand Stoicism, or Port Royal, or Puritanism, one should
remember the constraint under which every language has attained to
strength and freedom—the metrical constraint, the tyranny of rhyme
and rhythm. How much trouble have the poets and orators of every nation
given themselves!—not excepting some of the prose writers of today,
in whose ear dwells an inexorable conscientiousness—"for the sake of
a folly," as utilitarian bunglers say, and thereby deem themselves wise—"from
submission to arbitrary laws," as the anarchists say, and thereby fancy
themselves "free," even free-spirited. The singular fact remains, however,
that everything of the nature of freedom, elegance, boldness, dance, and
masterly certainty, which exists or has existed, whether it be in thought
itself, or in administration, or in speaking and persuading, in art just
as in conduct, has only developed by means of the tyranny of such
arbitrary law, and in all seriousness, it is not at all improbable that
precisely this is "nature" and "natural"—and not laisser-aller!
Every artist knows how different from the state of letting himself go, is
his "most natural" condition, the free arranging, locating, disposing, and
constructing in the moments of "inspiration"—and how strictly and
delicately he then obeys a thousand laws, which, by their very rigidness
and precision, defy all formulation by means of ideas (even the most
stable idea has, in comparison therewith, something floating, manifold,
and ambiguous in it). The essential thing "in heaven and in earth" is,
apparently (to repeat it once more), that there should be long OBEDIENCE
in the same direction, there thereby results, and has always resulted in
the long run, something which has made life worth living; for instance,
virtue, art, music, dancing, reason, spirituality—anything whatever
that is transfiguring, refined, foolish, or divine. The long bondage of
the spirit, the distrustful constraint in the communicability of ideas,
the discipline which the thinker imposed on himself to think in accordance
with the rules of a church or a court, or conformable to Aristotelian
premises, the persistent spiritual will to interpret everything that
happened according to a Christian scheme, and in every occurrence to
rediscover and justify the Christian God:—all this violence,
arbitrariness, severity, dreadfulness, and unreasonableness, has proved
itself the disciplinary means whereby the European spirit has attained its
strength, its remorseless curiosity and subtle mobility; granted also that
much irrecoverable strength and spirit had to be stifled, suffocated, and
spoilt in the process (for here, as everywhere, "nature" shows herself as
she is, in all her extravagant and INDIFFERENT magnificence, which is
shocking, but nevertheless noble). That for centuries European thinkers
only thought in order to prove something—nowadays, on the contrary,
we are suspicious of every thinker who "wishes to prove something"—that
it was always settled beforehand what WAS TO BE the result of their
strictest thinking, as it was perhaps in the Asiatic astrology of former
times, or as it is still at the present day in the innocent,
Christian-moral explanation of immediate personal events "for the glory of
God," or "for the good of the soul":—this tyranny, this
arbitrariness, this severe and magnificent stupidity, has EDUCATED the spirit;
slavery, both in the coarser and the finer sense, is apparently an
indispensable means even of spiritual education and discipline. One may
look at every system of morals in this light: it is "nature" therein which
teaches to hate the laisser-aller, the too great freedom, and implants the
need for limited horizons, for immediate duties—it teaches the
NARROWING OF PERSPECTIVES, and thus, in a certain sense, that stupidity is
a condition of life and development. "Thou must obey some one, and for a
long time; OTHERWISE thou wilt come to grief, and lose all respect for
thyself"—this seems to me to be the moral imperative of nature,
which is certainly neither "categorical," as old Kant wished (consequently
the "otherwise"), nor does it address itself to the individual (what does
nature care for the individual!), but to nations, races, ages, and ranks;
above all, however, to the animal "man" generally, to MANKIND.</p>
<p>189. Industrious races find it a great hardship to be idle: it was a
master stroke of ENGLISH instinct to hallow and begloom Sunday to such an
extent that the Englishman unconsciously hankers for his week—and
work-day again:—as a kind of cleverly devised, cleverly intercalated
FAST, such as is also frequently found in the ancient world (although, as
is appropriate in southern nations, not precisely with respect to work).
Many kinds of fasts are necessary; and wherever powerful influences and
habits prevail, legislators have to see that intercalary days are
appointed, on which such impulses are fettered, and learn to hunger anew.
Viewed from a higher standpoint, whole generations and epochs, when they
show themselves infected with any moral fanaticism, seem like those
intercalated periods of restraint and fasting, during which an impulse
learns to humble and submit itself—at the same time also to PURIFY
and SHARPEN itself; certain philosophical sects likewise admit of a
similar interpretation (for instance, the Stoa, in the midst of Hellenic
culture, with the atmosphere rank and overcharged with Aphrodisiacal
odours).—Here also is a hint for the explanation of the paradox, why
it was precisely in the most Christian period of European history, and in
general only under the pressure of Christian sentiments, that the sexual
impulse sublimated into love (amour-passion).</p>
<p>190. There is something in the morality of Plato which does not really
belong to Plato, but which only appears in his philosophy, one might say,
in spite of him: namely, Socratism, for which he himself was too noble.
"No one desires to injure himself, hence all evil is done unwittingly. The
evil man inflicts injury on himself; he would not do so, however, if he
knew that evil is evil. The evil man, therefore, is only evil through
error; if one free him from error one will necessarily make him—good."—This
mode of reasoning savours of the POPULACE, who perceive only the
unpleasant consequences of evil-doing, and practically judge that "it is
STUPID to do wrong"; while they accept "good" as identical with "useful
and pleasant," without further thought. As regards every system of
utilitarianism, one may at once assume that it has the same origin, and
follow the scent: one will seldom err.—Plato did all he could to
interpret something refined and noble into the tenets of his teacher, and
above all to interpret himself into them—he, the most daring of all
interpreters, who lifted the entire Socrates out of the street, as a
popular theme and song, to exhibit him in endless and impossible
modifications—namely, in all his own disguises and multiplicities.
In jest, and in Homeric language as well, what is the Platonic Socrates,
if not—[Greek words inserted here.]</p>
<p>191. The old theological problem of "Faith" and "Knowledge," or more
plainly, of instinct and reason—the question whether, in respect to
the valuation of things, instinct deserves more authority than
rationality, which wants to appreciate and act according to motives,
according to a "Why," that is to say, in conformity to purpose and utility—it
is always the old moral problem that first appeared in the person of
Socrates, and had divided men's minds long before Christianity. Socrates
himself, following, of course, the taste of his talent—that of a
surpassing dialectician—took first the side of reason; and, in fact,
what did he do all his life but laugh at the awkward incapacity of the
noble Athenians, who were men of instinct, like all noble men, and could
never give satisfactory answers concerning the motives of their actions?
In the end, however, though silently and secretly, he laughed also at
himself: with his finer conscience and introspection, he found in himself
the same difficulty and incapacity. "But why"—he said to himself—"should
one on that account separate oneself from the instincts! One must set them
right, and the reason ALSO—one must follow the instincts, but at the
same time persuade the reason to support them with good arguments." This
was the real FALSENESS of that great and mysterious ironist; he brought
his conscience up to the point that he was satisfied with a kind of
self-outwitting: in fact, he perceived the irrationality in the moral
judgment.—Plato, more innocent in such matters, and without the
craftiness of the plebeian, wished to prove to himself, at the expenditure
of all his strength—the greatest strength a philosopher had ever
expended—that reason and instinct lead spontaneously to one goal, to
the good, to "God"; and since Plato, all theologians and philosophers have
followed the same path—which means that in matters of morality,
instinct (or as Christians call it, "Faith," or as I call it, "the herd")
has hitherto triumphed. Unless one should make an exception in the case of
Descartes, the father of rationalism (and consequently the grandfather of
the Revolution), who recognized only the authority of reason: but reason
is only a tool, and Descartes was superficial.</p>
<p>192. Whoever has followed the history of a single science, finds in its
development a clue to the understanding of the oldest and commonest
processes of all "knowledge and cognizance": there, as here, the premature
hypotheses, the fictions, the good stupid will to "belief," and the lack
of distrust and patience are first developed—our senses learn late,
and never learn completely, to be subtle, reliable, and cautious organs of
knowledge. Our eyes find it easier on a given occasion to produce a
picture already often produced, than to seize upon the divergence and
novelty of an impression: the latter requires more force, more "morality."
It is difficult and painful for the ear to listen to anything new; we hear
strange music badly. When we hear another language spoken, we
involuntarily attempt to form the sounds into words with which we are more
familiar and conversant—it was thus, for example, that the Germans
modified the spoken word ARCUBALISTA into ARMBRUST (cross-bow). Our senses
are also hostile and averse to the new; and generally, even in the
"simplest" processes of sensation, the emotions DOMINATE—such as
fear, love, hatred, and the passive emotion of indolence.—As little
as a reader nowadays reads all the single words (not to speak of
syllables) of a page—he rather takes about five out of every twenty
words at random, and "guesses" the probably appropriate sense to them—just
as little do we see a tree correctly and completely in respect to its
leaves, branches, colour, and shape; we find it so much easier to fancy
the chance of a tree. Even in the midst of the most remarkable
experiences, we still do just the same; we fabricate the greater part of
the experience, and can hardly be made to contemplate any event, EXCEPT as
"inventors" thereof. All this goes to prove that from our fundamental
nature and from remote ages we have been—ACCUSTOMED TO LYING. Or, to
express it more politely and hypocritically, in short, more pleasantly—one
is much more of an artist than one is aware of.—In an animated
conversation, I often see the face of the person with whom I am speaking
so clearly and sharply defined before me, according to the thought he
expresses, or which I believe to be evoked in his mind, that the degree of
distinctness far exceeds the STRENGTH of my visual faculty—the
delicacy of the play of the muscles and of the expression of the eyes MUST
therefore be imagined by me. Probably the person put on quite a different
expression, or none at all.</p>
<p>193. Quidquid luce fuit, tenebris agit: but also contrariwise. What we
experience in dreams, provided we experience it often, pertains at last
just as much to the general belongings of our soul as anything "actually"
experienced; by virtue thereof we are richer or poorer, we have a
requirement more or less, and finally, in broad daylight, and even in the
brightest moments of our waking life, we are ruled to some extent by the
nature of our dreams. Supposing that someone has often flown in his
dreams, and that at last, as soon as he dreams, he is conscious of the
power and art of flying as his privilege and his peculiarly enviable
happiness; such a person, who believes that on the slightest impulse, he
can actualize all sorts of curves and angles, who knows the sensation of a
certain divine levity, an "upwards" without effort or constraint, a
"downwards" without descending or lowering—without TROUBLE!—how
could the man with such dream-experiences and dream-habits fail to find
"happiness" differently coloured and defined, even in his waking hours!
How could he fail—to long DIFFERENTLY for happiness? "Flight," such
as is described by poets, must, when compared with his own "flying," be
far too earthly, muscular, violent, far too "troublesome" for him.</p>
<p>194. The difference among men does not manifest itself only in the
difference of their lists of desirable things—in their regarding
different good things as worth striving for, and being disagreed as to the
greater or less value, the order of rank, of the commonly recognized
desirable things:—it manifests itself much more in what they regard
as actually HAVING and POSSESSING a desirable thing. As regards a woman,
for instance, the control over her body and her sexual gratification
serves as an amply sufficient sign of ownership and possession to the more
modest man; another with a more suspicious and ambitious thirst for
possession, sees the "questionableness," the mere apparentness of such
ownership, and wishes to have finer tests in order to know especially
whether the woman not only gives herself to him, but also gives up for his
sake what she has or would like to have—only THEN does he look upon
her as "possessed." A third, however, has not even here got to the limit
of his distrust and his desire for possession: he asks himself whether the
woman, when she gives up everything for him, does not perhaps do so for a
phantom of him; he wishes first to be thoroughly, indeed, profoundly well
known; in order to be loved at all he ventures to let himself be found
out. Only then does he feel the beloved one fully in his possession, when
she no longer deceives herself about him, when she loves him just as much
for the sake of his devilry and concealed insatiability, as for his
goodness, patience, and spirituality. One man would like to possess a
nation, and he finds all the higher arts of Cagliostro and Catalina
suitable for his purpose. Another, with a more refined thirst for
possession, says to himself: "One may not deceive where one desires to
possess"—he is irritated and impatient at the idea that a mask of
him should rule in the hearts of the people: "I must, therefore, MAKE
myself known, and first of all learn to know myself!" Among helpful and
charitable people, one almost always finds the awkward craftiness which
first gets up suitably him who has to be helped, as though, for instance,
he should "merit" help, seek just THEIR help, and would show himself
deeply grateful, attached, and subservient to them for all help. With
these conceits, they take control of the needy as a property, just as in
general they are charitable and helpful out of a desire for property. One
finds them jealous when they are crossed or forestalled in their charity.
Parents involuntarily make something like themselves out of their children—they
call that "education"; no mother doubts at the bottom of her heart that
the child she has borne is thereby her property, no father hesitates about
his right to HIS OWN ideas and notions of worth. Indeed, in former times
fathers deemed it right to use their discretion concerning the life or
death of the newly born (as among the ancient Germans). And like the
father, so also do the teacher, the class, the priest, and the prince
still see in every new individual an unobjectionable opportunity for a new
possession. The consequence is...</p>
<p>195. The Jews—a people "born for slavery," as Tacitus and the whole
ancient world say of them; "the chosen people among the nations," as they
themselves say and believe—the Jews performed the miracle of the
inversion of valuations, by means of which life on earth obtained a new
and dangerous charm for a couple of millenniums. Their prophets fused into
one the expressions "rich," "godless," "wicked," "violent," "sensual," and
for the first time coined the word "world" as a term of reproach. In this
inversion of valuations (in which is also included the use of the word
"poor" as synonymous with "saint" and "friend") the significance of the
Jewish people is to be found; it is with THEM that the SLAVE-INSURRECTION
IN MORALS commences.</p>
<p>196. It is to be INFERRED that there are countless dark bodies near the
sun—such as we shall never see. Among ourselves, this is an
allegory; and the psychologist of morals reads the whole star-writing
merely as an allegorical and symbolic language in which much may be
unexpressed.</p>
<p>197. The beast of prey and the man of prey (for instance, Caesar Borgia)
are fundamentally misunderstood, "nature" is misunderstood, so long as one
seeks a "morbidness" in the constitution of these healthiest of all
tropical monsters and growths, or even an innate "hell" in them—as
almost all moralists have done hitherto. Does it not seem that there is a
hatred of the virgin forest and of the tropics among moralists? And that
the "tropical man" must be discredited at all costs, whether as disease
and deterioration of mankind, or as his own hell and self-torture? And
why? In favour of the "temperate zones"? In favour of the temperate men?
The "moral"? The mediocre?—This for the chapter: "Morals as
Timidity."</p>
<p>198. All the systems of morals which address themselves with a view to
their "happiness," as it is called—what else are they but
suggestions for behaviour adapted to the degree of DANGER from themselves
in which the individuals live; recipes for their passions, their good and
bad propensities, insofar as such have the Will to Power and would like to
play the master; small and great expediencies and elaborations, permeated
with the musty odour of old family medicines and old-wife wisdom; all of
them grotesque and absurd in their form—because they address
themselves to "all," because they generalize where generalization is not
authorized; all of them speaking unconditionally, and taking themselves
unconditionally; all of them flavoured not merely with one grain of salt,
but rather endurable only, and sometimes even seductive, when they are
over-spiced and begin to smell dangerously, especially of "the other
world." That is all of little value when estimated intellectually, and is
far from being "science," much less "wisdom"; but, repeated once more, and
three times repeated, it is expediency, expediency, expediency, mixed with
stupidity, stupidity, stupidity—whether it be the indifference and
statuesque coldness towards the heated folly of the emotions, which the
Stoics advised and fostered; or the no-more-laughing and no-more-weeping
of Spinoza, the destruction of the emotions by their analysis and
vivisection, which he recommended so naively; or the lowering of the
emotions to an innocent mean at which they may be satisfied, the
Aristotelianism of morals; or even morality as the enjoyment of the
emotions in a voluntary attenuation and spiritualization by the symbolism
of art, perhaps as music, or as love of God, and of mankind for God's sake—for
in religion the passions are once more enfranchised, provided that...; or,
finally, even the complaisant and wanton surrender to the emotions, as has
been taught by Hafis and Goethe, the bold letting-go of the reins, the
spiritual and corporeal licentia morum in the exceptional cases of wise
old codgers and drunkards, with whom it "no longer has much danger."—This
also for the chapter: "Morals as Timidity."</p>
<p>199. Inasmuch as in all ages, as long as mankind has existed, there have
also been human herds (family alliances, communities, tribes, peoples,
states, churches), and always a great number who obey in proportion to the
small number who command—in view, therefore, of the fact that
obedience has been most practiced and fostered among mankind hitherto, one
may reasonably suppose that, generally speaking, the need thereof is now
innate in every one, as a kind of FORMAL CONSCIENCE which gives the
command "Thou shalt unconditionally do something, unconditionally refrain
from something", in short, "Thou shalt". This need tries to satisfy itself
and to fill its form with a content, according to its strength,
impatience, and eagerness, it at once seizes as an omnivorous appetite
with little selection, and accepts whatever is shouted into its ear by all
sorts of commanders—parents, teachers, laws, class prejudices, or
public opinion. The extraordinary limitation of human development, the
hesitation, protractedness, frequent retrogression, and turning thereof,
is attributable to the fact that the herd-instinct of obedience is
transmitted best, and at the cost of the art of command. If one imagine
this instinct increasing to its greatest extent, commanders and
independent individuals will finally be lacking altogether, or they will
suffer inwardly from a bad conscience, and will have to impose a deception
on themselves in the first place in order to be able to command just as if
they also were only obeying. This condition of things actually exists in
Europe at present—I call it the moral hypocrisy of the commanding
class. They know no other way of protecting themselves from their bad
conscience than by playing the role of executors of older and higher
orders (of predecessors, of the constitution, of justice, of the law, or
of God himself), or they even justify themselves by maxims from the
current opinions of the herd, as "first servants of their people," or
"instruments of the public weal". On the other hand, the gregarious
European man nowadays assumes an air as if he were the only kind of man
that is allowable, he glorifies his qualities, such as public spirit,
kindness, deference, industry, temperance, modesty, indulgence, sympathy,
by virtue of which he is gentle, endurable, and useful to the herd, as the
peculiarly human virtues. In cases, however, where it is believed that the
leader and bell-wether cannot be dispensed with, attempt after attempt is
made nowadays to replace commanders by the summing together of clever
gregarious men all representative constitutions, for example, are of this
origin. In spite of all, what a blessing, what a deliverance from a weight
becoming unendurable, is the appearance of an absolute ruler for these
gregarious Europeans—of this fact the effect of the appearance of
Napoleon was the last great proof the history of the influence of Napoleon
is almost the history of the higher happiness to which the entire century
has attained in its worthiest individuals and periods.</p>
<p>200. The man of an age of dissolution which mixes the races with one
another, who has the inheritance of a diversified descent in his body—that
is to say, contrary, and often not only contrary, instincts and standards
of value, which struggle with one another and are seldom at peace—such
a man of late culture and broken lights, will, on an average, be a weak
man. His fundamental desire is that the war which is IN HIM should come to
an end; happiness appears to him in the character of a soothing medicine
and mode of thought (for instance, Epicurean or Christian); it is above
all things the happiness of repose, of undisturbedness, of repletion, of
final unity—it is the "Sabbath of Sabbaths," to use the expression
of the holy rhetorician, St. Augustine, who was himself such a man.—Should,
however, the contrariety and conflict in such natures operate as an
ADDITIONAL incentive and stimulus to life—and if, on the other hand,
in addition to their powerful and irreconcilable instincts, they have also
inherited and indoctrinated into them a proper mastery and subtlety for
carrying on the conflict with themselves (that is to say, the faculty of
self-control and self-deception), there then arise those marvelously
incomprehensible and inexplicable beings, those enigmatical men,
predestined for conquering and circumventing others, the finest examples
of which are Alcibiades and Caesar (with whom I should like to associate
the FIRST of Europeans according to my taste, the Hohenstaufen, Frederick
the Second), and among artists, perhaps Leonardo da Vinci. They appear
precisely in the same periods when that weaker type, with its longing for
repose, comes to the front; the two types are complementary to each other,
and spring from the same causes.</p>
<p>201. As long as the utility which determines moral estimates is only
gregarious utility, as long as the preservation of the community is only
kept in view, and the immoral is sought precisely and exclusively in what
seems dangerous to the maintenance of the community, there can be no
"morality of love to one's neighbour." Granted even that there is already
a little constant exercise of consideration, sympathy, fairness,
gentleness, and mutual assistance, granted that even in this condition of
society all those instincts are already active which are latterly
distinguished by honourable names as "virtues," and eventually almost
coincide with the conception "morality": in that period they do not as yet
belong to the domain of moral valuations—they are still ULTRA-MORAL.
A sympathetic action, for instance, is neither called good nor bad, moral
nor immoral, in the best period of the Romans; and should it be praised, a
sort of resentful disdain is compatible with this praise, even at the
best, directly the sympathetic action is compared with one which
contributes to the welfare of the whole, to the RES PUBLICA. After all,
"love to our neighbour" is always a secondary matter, partly conventional
and arbitrarily manifested in relation to our FEAR OF OUR NEIGHBOUR. After
the fabric of society seems on the whole established and secured against
external dangers, it is this fear of our neighbour which again creates new
perspectives of moral valuation. Certain strong and dangerous instincts,
such as the love of enterprise, foolhardiness, revengefulness, astuteness,
rapacity, and love of power, which up till then had not only to be
honoured from the point of view of general utility—under other
names, of course, than those here given—but had to be fostered and
cultivated (because they were perpetually required in the common danger
against the common enemies), are now felt in their dangerousness to be
doubly strong—when the outlets for them are lacking—and are
gradually branded as immoral and given over to calumny. The contrary
instincts and inclinations now attain to moral honour, the gregarious
instinct gradually draws its conclusions. How much or how little
dangerousness to the community or to equality is contained in an opinion,
a condition, an emotion, a disposition, or an endowment—that is now
the moral perspective, here again fear is the mother of morals. It is by
the loftiest and strongest instincts, when they break out passionately and
carry the individual far above and beyond the average, and the low level
of the gregarious conscience, that the self-reliance of the community is
destroyed, its belief in itself, its backbone, as it were, breaks,
consequently these very instincts will be most branded and defamed. The
lofty independent spirituality, the will to stand alone, and even the
cogent reason, are felt to be dangers, everything that elevates the
individual above the herd, and is a source of fear to the neighbour, is
henceforth called EVIL, the tolerant, unassuming, self-adapting,
self-equalizing disposition, the MEDIOCRITY of desires, attains to moral
distinction and honour. Finally, under very peaceful circumstances, there
is always less opportunity and necessity for training the feelings to
severity and rigour, and now every form of severity, even in justice,
begins to disturb the conscience, a lofty and rigorous nobleness and
self-responsibility almost offends, and awakens distrust, "the lamb," and
still more "the sheep," wins respect. There is a point of diseased
mellowness and effeminacy in the history of society, at which society
itself takes the part of him who injures it, the part of the CRIMINAL, and
does so, in fact, seriously and honestly. To punish, appears to it to be
somehow unfair—it is certain that the idea of "punishment" and "the
obligation to punish" are then painful and alarming to people. "Is it not
sufficient if the criminal be rendered HARMLESS? Why should we still
punish? Punishment itself is terrible!"—with these questions
gregarious morality, the morality of fear, draws its ultimate conclusion.
If one could at all do away with danger, the cause of fear, one would have
done away with this morality at the same time, it would no longer be
necessary, it WOULD NOT CONSIDER ITSELF any longer necessary!—Whoever
examines the conscience of the present-day European, will always elicit
the same imperative from its thousand moral folds and hidden recesses, the
imperative of the timidity of the herd "we wish that some time or other
there may be NOTHING MORE TO FEAR!" Some time or other—the will and
the way THERETO is nowadays called "progress" all over Europe.</p>
<p>202. Let us at once say again what we have already said a hundred times,
for people's ears nowadays are unwilling to hear such truths—OUR
truths. We know well enough how offensive it sounds when any one plainly,
and without metaphor, counts man among the animals, but it will be
accounted to us almost a CRIME, that it is precisely in respect to men of
"modern ideas" that we have constantly applied the terms "herd,"
"herd-instincts," and such like expressions. What avail is it? We cannot
do otherwise, for it is precisely here that our new insight is. We have
found that in all the principal moral judgments, Europe has become
unanimous, including likewise the countries where European influence
prevails in Europe people evidently KNOW what Socrates thought he did not
know, and what the famous serpent of old once promised to teach—they
"know" today what is good and evil. It must then sound hard and be
distasteful to the ear, when we always insist that that which here thinks
it knows, that which here glorifies itself with praise and blame, and
calls itself good, is the instinct of the herding human animal, the
instinct which has come and is ever coming more and more to the front, to
preponderance and supremacy over other instincts, according to the
increasing physiological approximation and resemblance of which it is the
symptom. MORALITY IN EUROPE AT PRESENT IS HERDING-ANIMAL MORALITY, and
therefore, as we understand the matter, only one kind of human morality,
beside which, before which, and after which many other moralities, and
above all HIGHER moralities, are or should be possible. Against such a
"possibility," against such a "should be," however, this morality defends
itself with all its strength, it says obstinately and inexorably "I am
morality itself and nothing else is morality!" Indeed, with the help of a
religion which has humoured and flattered the sublimest desires of the
herding-animal, things have reached such a point that we always find a
more visible expression of this morality even in political and social
arrangements: the DEMOCRATIC movement is the inheritance of the Christian
movement. That its TEMPO, however, is much too slow and sleepy for the
more impatient ones, for those who are sick and distracted by the
herding-instinct, is indicated by the increasingly furious howling, and
always less disguised teeth-gnashing of the anarchist dogs, who are now
roving through the highways of European culture. Apparently in opposition
to the peacefully industrious democrats and Revolution-ideologues, and
still more so to the awkward philosophasters and fraternity-visionaries
who call themselves Socialists and want a "free society," those are really
at one with them all in their thorough and instinctive hostility to every
form of society other than that of the AUTONOMOUS herd (to the extent even
of repudiating the notions "master" and "servant"—ni dieu ni maitre,
says a socialist formula); at one in their tenacious opposition to every
special claim, every special right and privilege (this means ultimately
opposition to EVERY right, for when all are equal, no one needs "rights"
any longer); at one in their distrust of punitive justice (as though it
were a violation of the weak, unfair to the NECESSARY consequences of all
former society); but equally at one in their religion of sympathy, in
their compassion for all that feels, lives, and suffers (down to the very
animals, up even to "God"—the extravagance of "sympathy for God"
belongs to a democratic age); altogether at one in the cry and impatience
of their sympathy, in their deadly hatred of suffering generally, in their
almost feminine incapacity for witnessing it or ALLOWING it; at one in
their involuntary beglooming and heart-softening, under the spell of which
Europe seems to be threatened with a new Buddhism; at one in their belief
in the morality of MUTUAL sympathy, as though it were morality in itself,
the climax, the ATTAINED climax of mankind, the sole hope of the future,
the consolation of the present, the great discharge from all the
obligations of the past; altogether at one in their belief in the
community as the DELIVERER, in the herd, and therefore in "themselves."</p>
<p>203. We, who hold a different belief—we, who regard the democratic
movement, not only as a degenerating form of political organization, but
as equivalent to a degenerating, a waning type of man, as involving his
mediocrising and depreciation: where have WE to fix our hopes? In NEW
PHILOSOPHERS—there is no other alternative: in minds strong and
original enough to initiate opposite estimates of value, to transvalue and
invert "eternal valuations"; in forerunners, in men of the future, who in
the present shall fix the constraints and fasten the knots which will
compel millenniums to take NEW paths. To teach man the future of humanity
as his WILL, as depending on human will, and to make preparation for vast
hazardous enterprises and collective attempts in rearing and educating, in
order thereby to put an end to the frightful rule of folly and chance
which has hitherto gone by the name of "history" (the folly of the
"greatest number" is only its last form)—for that purpose a new type
of philosopher and commander will some time or other be needed, at the
very idea of which everything that has existed in the way of occult,
terrible, and benevolent beings might look pale and dwarfed. The image of
such leaders hovers before OUR eyes:—is it lawful for me to say it
aloud, ye free spirits? The conditions which one would partly have to
create and partly utilize for their genesis; the presumptive methods and
tests by virtue of which a soul should grow up to such an elevation and
power as to feel a CONSTRAINT to these tasks; a transvaluation of values,
under the new pressure and hammer of which a conscience should be steeled
and a heart transformed into brass, so as to bear the weight of such
responsibility; and on the other hand the necessity for such leaders, the
dreadful danger that they might be lacking, or miscarry and degenerate:—these
are OUR real anxieties and glooms, ye know it well, ye free spirits! these
are the heavy distant thoughts and storms which sweep across the heaven of
OUR life. There are few pains so grievous as to have seen, divined, or
experienced how an exceptional man has missed his way and deteriorated;
but he who has the rare eye for the universal danger of "man" himself
DETERIORATING, he who like us has recognized the extraordinary
fortuitousness which has hitherto played its game in respect to the future
of mankind—a game in which neither the hand, nor even a "finger of
God" has participated!—he who divines the fate that is hidden under
the idiotic unwariness and blind confidence of "modern ideas," and still
more under the whole of Christo-European morality—suffers from an
anguish with which no other is to be compared. He sees at a glance all
that could still BE MADE OUT OF MAN through a favourable accumulation and
augmentation of human powers and arrangements; he knows with all the
knowledge of his conviction how unexhausted man still is for the greatest
possibilities, and how often in the past the type man has stood in
presence of mysterious decisions and new paths:—he knows still
better from his painfulest recollections on what wretched obstacles
promising developments of the highest rank have hitherto usually gone to
pieces, broken down, sunk, and become contemptible. The UNIVERSAL
DEGENERACY OF MANKIND to the level of the "man of the future"—as
idealized by the socialistic fools and shallow-pates—this degeneracy
and dwarfing of man to an absolutely gregarious animal (or as they call
it, to a man of "free society"), this brutalizing of man into a pigmy with
equal rights and claims, is undoubtedly POSSIBLE! He who has thought out
this possibility to its ultimate conclusion knows ANOTHER loathing unknown
to the rest of mankind—and perhaps also a new MISSION!</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />