<SPAN name="toc19" id="toc19"></SPAN>
<SPAN name="pdf20" id="pdf20"></SPAN>
<h2><span>Discourse VIII.</span></h2>
<h2><span>Knowledge Viewed In Relation To Religion.</span></h2>
<h3><span>1.</span></h3>
<p>
We shall be brought, Gentlemen, to-day, to the
termination of the investigation which I commenced
three Discourses back, and which, I was well
aware, from its length, if for no other reason, would make
demands upon the patience even of indulgent hearers.</p>
<p>
First I employed myself in establishing the principle
that Knowledge is its own reward; and I showed that,
when considered in this light, it is called Liberal Knowledge,
and is the scope of Academical Institutions.</p>
<p>
Next, I examined what is meant by Knowledge, when
it is said to be pursued for its own sake; and I showed
that, in order satisfactorily to fulfil this idea, Philosophy
must be its <em><span style="font-style: italic">form</span></em>; or, in other words, that its matter
must not be admitted into the mind passively, as so much
acquirement, but must be mastered and appropriated as a
system consisting of parts, related one to the other, and
interpretative of one another in the unity of a whole.</p>
<p>
Further, I showed that such a philosophical contemplation
of the field of Knowledge as a whole, leading, as
it did, to an understanding of its separate departments,
and an appreciation of them respectively, might in consequence
be rightly called an illumination; also, it was
rightly called an enlargement of mind, because it was a
distinct location of things one with another, as if in
space; while it was moreover its proper cultivation and
its best condition, both because it secured to the intellect
the sight of things as they are, or of truth, in opposition
to fancy, opinion, and theory; and again, because it presupposed
and involved the perfection of its various
powers.</p>
<p>
Such, I said, was that Knowledge, which deserves to
be sought for its own sake, even though it promised no
ulterior advantage. But, when I had got as far as this, I
went farther, and observed that, from the nature of the
case, what was so good in itself could not but have a
number of external uses, though it did not promise them,
simply because it <em><span style="font-style: italic">was</span></em> good; and that it was necessarily
the source of benefits to society, great and diversified in
proportion to its own intrinsic excellence. Just as in
morals, honesty is the best policy, as being profitable in
a secular aspect, though such profit is not the measure
of its worth, so too as regards what may be called the
virtues of the Intellect, their very possession indeed is a
substantial good, and is enough, yet still that substance
has a shadow, inseparable from it, viz., its social and
political usefulness. And this was the subject to which
I devoted the preceding Discourse.</p>
<p>
One portion of the subject remains:—this intellectual
culture, which is so exalted in itself, not only has a
bearing upon social and active duties, but upon Religion
also. The educated mind may be said to be in a certain
sense religious; that is, it has what may be considered a
religion of its own, independent of Catholicism, partly co-operating
with it, partly thwarting it; at once a defence
yet a disturbance to the Church in Catholic countries,—and
in countries beyond her pale, at one time in open
warfare with her, at another in defensive alliance. The
history of Schools and Academies, and of Literature and
Science generally, will, I think, justify me in thus speaking.
Since, then, my aim in these Discourses is to
ascertain the function and the action of a University,
viewed in itself, and its relations to the various instruments
of teaching and training which are round about it,
my survey of it would not be complete unless I attempted,
as I now propose to do, to exhibit its general bearings
upon Religion.</p>
<h3><span>2.</span></h3>
<p>
Right Reason, that is, Reason rightly exercised, leads
the mind to the Catholic Faith, and plants it there, and
teaches it in all its religious speculations to act under its
guidance. But Reason, considered as a real agent in the
world, and as an operative principle in man's nature, with
an historical course and with definite results, is far from
taking so straight and satisfactory a direction. It
considers itself from first to last independent and
supreme; it requires no external authority; it makes a
religion for itself. Even though it accepts Catholicism,
it does not go to sleep; it has an action and development
of its own, as the passions have, or the moral sentiments,
or the principle of self-interest. Divine grace, to use the
language of Theology, does not by its presence supersede
nature; nor is nature at once brought into simple concurrence
and coalition with grace. Nature pursues its course,
now coincident with that of grace, now parallel to it, now
across, now divergent, now counter, in proportion to its
own imperfection and to the attraction and influence
which grace exerts over it. And what takes place as
regards other principles of our nature and their developments
is found also as regards the Reason. There is, we
know, a Religion of enthusiasm, of superstitious ignorance
of statecraft; and each has that in it which resembles
Catholicism, and that again which contradicts Catholicism.
There is the Religion of a warlike people, and
of a pastoral people; there is a Religion of rude times,
and in like manner there is a Religion of civilized times,
of the cultivated intellect, of the philosopher, scholar,
and gentleman. This is that Religion of Reason, of
which I speak. Viewed in itself, however near it comes
to Catholicism, it is of course simply distinct from it; for
Catholicism is one whole, and admits of no compromise
or modification. Yet this is to view it in the abstract;
in matter of fact, and in reference to individuals, we
can have no difficulty in conceiving this philosophical
Religion present in a Catholic country, as a spirit influencing
men to a certain extent, for good or for bad
or for both,—a spirit of the age, which again may be
found, as among Catholics, so with still greater sway
and success in a country not Catholic, yet specifically
the same in such a country as it exists in a Catholic
community. The problem then before us to-day, is to
set down some portions of the outline, if we can ascertain
them, of the Religion of Civilization, and to determine
how they lie relatively to those principles, doctrines, and
rules, which Heaven has given us in the Catholic
Church.</p>
<p>
And here again, when I speak of Revealed Truth, it
is scarcely necessary to say that I am not referring to
the main articles and prominent points of faith, as contained
in the Creed. Had I undertaken to delineate a
philosophy, which directly interfered with the Creed, I
could not have spoken of it as compatible with the profession
of Catholicism. The philosophy I speak of,
whether it be viewed within or outside the Church, does
not necessarily take cognizance of the Creed. Where
the country is Catholic, the educated mind takes its
articles for granted, by a sort of implicit faith; where
it is not, it simply ignores them and the whole subject-matter
to which they relate, as not affecting social and
political interests. Truths about God's Nature, about
His dealings towards the human race, about the
Economy of Redemption,—in the one case it humbly
accepts them, and passes on; in the other it passes them
over, as matters of simple opinion, which never can be
decided, and which can have no power over us to make
us morally better or worse. I am not speaking then of
belief in the great objects of faith, when I speak of
Catholicism, but I am contemplating Catholicism chiefly
as a system of pastoral instruction and moral duty; and
I have to do with its doctrines mainly as they are subservient
to its direction of the conscience and the conduct.
I speak of it, for instance, as teaching the ruined
state of man; his utter inability to gain Heaven by any
thing he can do himself; the moral certainty of his
losing his soul if left to himself; the simple absence of
all rights and claims on the part of the creature in the
presence of the Creator; the illimitable claims of the
Creator on the service of the creature; the imperative
and obligatory force of the voice of conscience; and
the inconceivable evil of sensuality. I speak of it as
teaching, that no one gains Heaven except by the free
grace of God, or without a regeneration of nature; that
no one can please Him without faith; that the heart is
the seat both of sin and of obedience; that charity is
the fulfilling of the Law; and that incorporation into
the Catholic Church is the ordinary instrument of salvation.
These are the lessons which distinguish Catholicism
as a popular religion, and these are the subjects to
which the cultivated intellect will practically be turned;—I
have to compare and contrast, not the doctrinal, but
the moral and social teaching of Philosophy on the one
hand, and Catholicism on the other.</p>
<h3><span>3.</span></h3>
<p>
Now, on opening the subject, we see at once a momentous
benefit which the philosopher is likely to confer on
the pastors of the Church. It is obvious that the first
step which they have to effect in the conversion of man
and the renovation of his nature, is his rescue from that
fearful subjection to sense which is his ordinary state.
To be able to break through the meshes of that thraldom,
and to disentangle and to disengage its ten thousand
holds upon the heart, is to bring it, I might almost
say, half way to Heaven. Here, even divine grace, to
speak of things according to their appearances, is ordinarily
baffled, and retires, without expedient or resource,
before this giant fascination. Religion seems too high
and unearthly to be able to exert a continued influence
upon us: its effort to rouse the soul, and the soul's effort
to co-operate, are too violent to last. It is like holding
out the arm at full length, or supporting some great
weight, which we manage to do for a time, but soon are
exhausted and succumb. Nothing can act beyond its
own nature; when then we are called to what is supernatural,
though those extraordinary aids from Heaven
are given us, with which obedience becomes possible, yet
even with them it is of transcendent difficulty. We are
drawn down to earth every moment with the ease and
certainty of a natural gravitation, and it is only by
sudden impulses and, as it were, forcible plunges that we
attempt to mount upwards. Religion indeed enlightens,
terrifies, subdues; it gives faith, it inflicts remorse, it inspires
resolutions, it draws tears, it inflames devotion, but
only for the occasion. I repeat, it imparts an inward
power which ought to effect more than this; I am not
forgetting either the real sufficiency of its aids, nor the
responsibility of those in whom they fail. I am not
discussing theological questions at all, I am looking at
phenomena as they lie before me, and I say that, in
matter of fact, the sinful spirit repents, and protests it
will never sin again, and for a while is protected by disgust
and abhorrence from the malice of its foe. But that foe
knows too well that such seasons of repentance are wont
to have their end: he patiently waits, till nature faints
with the effort of resistance, and lies passive and hopeless
under the next access of temptation. What we
need then is some expedient or instrument, which at least
will obstruct and stave off the approach of our spiritual
enemy, and which is sufficiently congenial and level
with our nature to maintain as firm a hold upon us as
the inducements of sensual gratification. It will be our
wisdom to employ nature against itself. Thus sorrow,
sickness, and care are providential antagonists to our
inward disorders; they come upon us as years pass on,
and generally produce their natural effects on us, in proportion
as we are subjected to their influence. These,
however, are God's instruments, not ours; we need a
similar remedy, which we can make our own, the object
of some legitimate faculty, or the aim of some natural
affection, which is capable of resting on the mind, and
taking up its familiar lodging with it, and engrossing it,
and which thus becomes a match for the besetting power
of sensuality, and a sort of homœopathic medicine for the
disease. Here then I think is the important aid which
intellectual cultivation furnishes to us in rescuing the
victims of passion and self-will. It does not supply religious
motives; it is not the cause or proper antecedent
of any thing supernatural; it is not meritorious of
heavenly aid or reward; but it does a work, at least
<em><span style="font-style: italic">materially</span></em> good (as theologians speak), whatever be its
real and formal character. It expels the excitements of
sense by the introduction of those of the intellect.</p>
<p>
This then is the <span lang="la" class="tei tei-foreign" xml:lang="la"><span style="font-style: italic">primâ
facie</span></span> advantage of the pursuit
of Knowledge; it is the drawing the mind off from
things which will harm it to subjects which are worthy
a rational being; and, though it does not raise it above
nature, nor has any tendency to make us pleasing to our
Maker, yet is it nothing to substitute what is in itself
harmless for what is, to say the least, inexpressibly
dangerous? is it a little thing to exchange a circle of
ideas which are certainly sinful, for others which are
certainly not so? You will say, perhaps, in the words
of the Apostle, <span class="tei tei-q">“Knowledge puffeth up:”</span> and doubtless
this mental cultivation, even when it is successful for the
purpose for which I am applying it, may be from the
first nothing more than the substitution of pride for
sensuality. I grant it, I think I shall have something to
say on this point presently; but this is not a necessary
result, it is but an incidental evil, a danger which may
be realized or may be averted, whereas we may in most
cases predicate guilt, and guilt of a heinous kind, where
the mind is suffered to run wild and indulge its thoughts
without training or law of any kind; and surely to turn
away a soul from mortal sin is a good and a gain so
far, whatever comes of it. And therefore, if a friend in
need is twice a friend, I conceive that intellectual employments,
though they do no more than occupy the mind
with objects naturally noble or innocent, have a special
claim upon our consideration and gratitude.</p>
<h3><span>4.</span></h3>
<p>
Nor is this all: Knowledge, the discipline by which it
is gained, and the tastes which it forms, have a natural
tendency to refine the mind, and to give it an indisposition,
simply natural, yet real, nay, more than this, a
disgust and abhorrence, towards excesses and enormities
of evil, which are often or ordinarily reached at
length by those who are not careful from the first to
set themselves against what is vicious and criminal. It
generates within the mind a fastidiousness, analogous to
the delicacy or daintiness which good nurture or a sickly
habit induces in respect of food; and this fastidiousness,
though arguing no high principle, though no protection
in the case of violent temptation, nor sure in its operation,
yet will often or generally be lively enough to create
an absolute loathing of certain offences, or a detestation
and scorn of them as ungentlemanlike, to which ruder
natures, nay, such as have far more of real religion in
them, are tempted, or even betrayed. Scarcely can we
exaggerate the value, in its place, of a safeguard such as
this, as regards those multitudes who are thrown upon
the open field of the world, or are withdrawn from its
eye and from the restraint of public opinion. In many
cases, where it exists, sins, familiar to those who are
otherwise circumstanced, will not even occur to the
mind: in others, the sense of shame and the quickened
apprehension of detection will act as a sufficient obstacle
to them, when they do present themselves before it.
Then, again, the fastidiousness I am speaking of will
create a simple hatred of that miserable tone of conversation
which, obtaining as it does in the world, is a constant
fuel of evil, heaped up round about the soul: moreover,
it will create an irresolution and indecision in doing
wrong, which will act as a <em><span style="font-style: italic">remora</span></em> till the danger is past
away. And though it has no tendency, I repeat, to
mend the heart, or to secure it from the dominion in
other shapes of those very evils which it repels in the
particular modes of approach by which they prevail over
others, yet cases may occur when it gives birth, after sins
have been committed, to so keen a remorse and so intense
a self-hatred, as are even sufficient to cure the particular
moral disorder, and to prevent its accesses ever afterwards;—as
the spendthrift in the story, who, after gazing
on his lost acres from the summit of an eminence, came
down a miser, and remained a miser to the end of his
days.</p>
<p>
And all this holds good in a special way, in an age
such as ours, when, although pain of body and mind
may be rife as heretofore, yet other counteractions of evil,
of a penal character, which are present at other times, are
away. In rude and semi-barbarous periods, at least in a
climate such as our own, it is the daily, nay, the principal
business of the senses, to convey feelings of discomfort
to the mind, as far as they convey feelings at all. Exposure
to the elements, social disorder and lawlessness, the
tyranny of the powerful, and the inroads of enemies, are
a stern discipline, allowing brief intervals, or awarding a
sharp penance, to sloth and sensuality. The rude food,
the scanty clothing, the violent exercise, the vagrant life,
the military constraint, the imperfect pharmacy, which
now are the trials of only particular classes of the
community, were once the lot more or less of all. In the
deep woods or the wild solitudes of the medieval era,
feelings of religion or superstition were naturally present
to the population, which in various ways co-operated
with the missionary or pastor, in retaining it in a noble
simplicity of manners. But, when in the advancement
of society men congregate in towns, and multiply in contracted
spaces, and law gives them security, and art
gives them comforts, and good government robs them of
courage and manliness, and monotony of life throws
them back upon themselves, who does not see that
diversion or protection from evil they have none, that
vice is the mere reaction of unhealthy toil, and sensual
excess the holyday of resourceless ignorance? This is
so well understood by the practical benevolence of the
day, that it has especially busied itself in plans for supplying
the masses of our town population with intellectual
and honourable recreations. Cheap literature,
libraries of useful and entertaining knowledge, scientific
lectureships, museums, zoological collections, buildings
and gardens to please the eye and to give repose to the
feelings, external objects of whatever kind, which may
take the mind off itself, and expand and elevate it in
liberal contemplations, these are the human means, wisely
suggested, and good as far as they go, for at least parrying
the assaults of moral evil, and keeping at bay the enemies,
not only of the individual soul, but of society at large.</p>
<p>
Such are the instruments by which an age of advanced
civilization combats those moral disorders, which Reason
as well as Revelation denounces; and I have not been
backward to express my sense of their serviceableness
to Religion. Moreover, they are but the foremost of a
series of influences, which intellectual culture exerts
upon our moral nature, and all upon the type of Christianity,
manifesting themselves in veracity, probity,
equity, fairness, gentleness, benevolence, and amiableness;
so much so, that a character more noble to look
at, more beautiful, more winning, in the various relations
of life and in personal duties, is hardly conceivable, than
may, or might be, its result, when that culture is bestowed
upon a soil naturally adapted to virtue. If you would
obtain a picture for contemplation which may seem to
fulfil the ideal, which the Apostle has delineated under
the name of charity, in its sweetness and harmony, its
generosity, its courtesy to others, and its depreciation of
self, you could not have recourse to a better furnished
<em><span style="font-style: italic">studio</span></em> than to that of Philosophy, with the specimens of
it, which with greater or less exactness are scattered
through society in a civilized age. It is enough to refer
you, Gentlemen, to the various Biographies and Remains
of contemporaries and others, which from time to time
issue from the press, to see how striking is the action of
our intellectual upon our moral nature, where the moral
material is rich, and the intellectual cast is perfect.
Individuals will occur to all of us, who deservedly attract
our love and admiration, and whom the world almost
worships as the work of its own hands. Religious
principle, indeed,—that is, faith,—is, to all appearance,
simply away; the work is as certainly not supernatural
as it is certainly noble and beautiful. This must be
insisted on, that the Intellect may have its due; but
it also must be insisted on for the sake of conclusions
to which I wish to conduct our investigation. The
radical difference indeed of this mental refinement from
genuine religion, in spite of its seeming relationship, is
the very cardinal point on which my present discussion
turns; yet, on the other hand, such refinement may
readily be assigned to a Christian origin by hasty or
distant observers, or by those who view it in a particular
light. And as this is the case, I think it advisable,
before proceeding with the delineation of its characteristic
features, to point out to you distinctly the elementary
principles on which its morality is based.</p>
<h3><span>5.</span></h3>
<p>
You will bear in mind then, Gentlemen, that I spoke
just now of the scorn and hatred which a cultivated mind
feels for some kinds of vice, and the utter disgust and
profound humiliation which may come over it, if it
should happen in any degree to be betrayed into them.
Now this feeling may have its root in faith and love, but
it may not; there is nothing really religious in it, considered
by itself. Conscience indeed is implanted in the
breast by nature, but it inflicts upon us fear as well as
shame; when the mind is simply angry with itself and
nothing more, surely the true import of the voice of
nature and the depth of its intimations have been
forgotten, and a false philosophy has misinterpreted
emotions which ought to lead to God. Fear implies
the transgression of a law, and a law implies a lawgiver
and judge; but the tendency of intellectual culture is to
swallow up the fear in the self-reproach, and self-reproach
is directed and limited to our mere sense of what is fitting
and becoming. Fear carries us out of ourselves, whereas
shame may act upon us only within the round of our
own thoughts. Such, I say, is the danger which awaits
a civilized age; such is its besetting sin (not inevitable,
God forbid! or we must abandon the use of God's own
gifts), but still the ordinary sin of the Intellect; conscience
tends to become what is called a moral sense;
the command of duty is a sort of taste; sin is not an
offence against God, but against human nature.</p>
<p>
The less amiable specimens of this spurious religion
are those which we meet not unfrequently in my own
country. I can use with all my heart the poet's words,</p>
<br/><span class="tei tei-q" style="text-align: left">“England, with all thy faults, I love thee still;”</span>
<p>
but to those faults no Catholic can be blind. We find
there men possessed of many virtues, but proud, bashful,
fastidious, and reserved. Why is this? it is because
they think and act as if there were really nothing
objective in their religion; it is because conscience to
them is not the word of a lawgiver, as it ought to be,
but the dictate of their own minds and nothing more;
it is because they do not look out of themselves, because
they do not look through and beyond their own minds
to their Maker, but are engrossed in notions of what is
due to themselves, to their own dignity and their own
consistency. Their conscience has become a mere self-respect.
Instead of doing one thing and then another,
as each is called for, in faith and obedience, careless of
what may be called the <em><span style="font-style: italic">keeping</span></em> of deed with deed, and
leaving Him who gives the command to blend the portions
of their conduct into a whole, their one object,
however unconscious to themselves, is to paint a smooth
and perfect surface, and to be able to say to themselves
that they have done their duty. When they do wrong,
they feel, not contrition, of which God is the object, but
remorse, and a sense of degradation. They call themselves
fools, not sinners; they are angry and impatient,
not humble. They shut themselves up in themselves;
it is misery to them to think or to speak of their own
feelings; it is misery to suppose that others see them, and
their shyness and sensitiveness often become morbid. As
to confession, which is so natural to the Catholic, to them
it is impossible; unless indeed, in cases where they have
been guilty, an apology is due to their own character, is
expected of them, and will be satisfactory to look back
upon. They are victims of an intense self-contemplation.</p>
<p>
There are, however, far more pleasing and interesting
forms of this moral malady than that which I have been
depicting: I have spoken of the effect of intellectual
culture on proud natures; but it will show to greater
advantage, yet with as little approximation to religious
faith, in amiable and unaffected minds. Observe, Gentlemen,
the heresy, as it may be called, of which I speak,
is the substitution of a moral sense or taste for conscience
in the true meaning of the word; now this error
may be the foundation of a character of far more
elasticity and grace than ever adorned the persons whom
I have been describing. It is especially congenial to men
of an imaginative and poetical cast of mind, who will
readily accept the notion that virtue is nothing more
than the graceful in conduct. Such persons, far from
tolerating fear, as a principle, in their apprehension of
religious and moral truth, will not be slow to call it
simply gloom and superstition. Rather a philosopher's,
a gentleman's religion, is of a liberal and generous
character; it is based upon honour; vice is evil, because
it is unworthy, despicable, and odious. This was the
quarrel of the ancient heathen with Christianity, that,
instead of simply fixing the mind on the fair and the
pleasant, it intermingled other ideas with them of a sad
and painful nature; that it spoke of tears before joy, a
cross before a crown; that it laid the foundation of
heroism in penance; that it made the soul tremble with
the news of Purgatory and Hell; that it insisted on views
and a worship of the Deity, which to their minds was
nothing else than mean, servile, and cowardly. The
notion of an All-perfect, Ever-present God, in whose
sight we are less than atoms, and who, while He deigns
to visit us, can punish as well as bless, was abhorrent to
them; they made their own minds their sanctuary, their
own ideas their oracle, and conscience in morals was but
parallel to genius in art, and wisdom in philosophy.</p>
<h3><span>6.</span></h3>
<p>
Had I room for all that might be said upon the subject,
I might illustrate this intellectual religion from the history
of the Emperor Julian, the apostate from Christian Truth,
the foe of Christian education. He, in whom every
Catholic sees the shadow of the future Anti-Christ, was
all but the pattern-man of philosophical virtue. Weak
points in his character he had, it is true, even in a merely
poetical standard; but, take him all in all, and I cannot
but recognize in him a specious beauty and nobleness of
moral deportment, which combines in it the rude greatness
of Fabricius or Regulus with the accomplishments
of Pliny or Antoninus. His simplicity of manners, his
frugality, his austerity of life, his singular disdain of
sensual pleasure, his military heroism, his application to
business, his literary diligence, his modesty, his clemency,
his accomplishments, as I view them, go to make him
one of the most eminent specimens of pagan virtue
which the world has ever seen.<SPAN id="noteref_24" name="noteref_24" href="#note_24"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">24</span></span></SPAN> Yet how shallow, how
meagre, nay, how unamiable is that virtue after all, when
brought upon its critical trial by his sudden summons
into the presence of his Judge! His last hours form a
<em><span style="font-style: italic">unique</span></em> passage in history, both as illustrating the helplessness
of philosophy under the stern realities of our
being, and as being reported to us on the evidence of an
eye-witness. <span class="tei tei-q">“Friends and fellow-soldiers,”</span> he said, to
use the words of a writer, well fitted, both from his
literary tastes and from his hatred of Christianity, to be
his panegyrist, <span class="tei tei-q">“the seasonable period of my departure
is now arrived, and I discharge, with the cheerfulness of
a ready debtor, the demands of nature.… I die without
remorse, as I have lived without guilt. I am pleased
to reflect on the innocence of my private life; and I can
affirm with confidence that the supreme authority, that
emanation of the divine Power, has been preserved in
my hands pure and immaculate.… I now offer my
tribute of gratitude to the Eternal Being, who has not
suffered me to perish by the cruelty of a tyrant, by the
secret dagger of conspiracy, or by the slow tortures of
lingering disease. He has given me, in the midst of an
honourable career, a splendid and glorious departure
from this world, and I hold it equally absurd, equally
base, to solicit, or to decline, the stroke of fate.…</span></p>
<p>
<span class="tei tei-q">“He reproved the immoderate grief of the spectators,
and conjured them not to disgrace, by unmanly tears,
the fate of a prince who in a few moments would be
united with Heaven and with the stars. The spectators
were silent; and Julian entered into a metaphysical
argument with the philosophers Priscus and Maximus
on the nature of the soul. The efforts which he made,
of mind as well as body, most probably hastened his
death. His wound began to bleed with great violence;
his respiration was embarrassed by the swelling of the
veins; he called for a draught of cold water, and as soon
as he had drank it expired without pain, about the
hour of midnight.”</span><SPAN id="noteref_25" name="noteref_25" href="#note_25"><span class="tei tei-noteref"><span style="font-size: 60%; vertical-align: super">25</span></span></SPAN> Such, Gentlemen, is the final
exhibition of the Religion of Reason: in the insensibility
of conscience, in the ignorance of the very idea of sin, in
the contemplation of his own moral consistency, in the
simple absence of fear, in the cloudless self-confidence,
in the serene self-possession, in the cold self-satisfaction,
we recognize the mere Philosopher.</p>
<h3><span>7.</span></h3>
<p>
Gibbon paints with pleasure what, conformably with
the sentiments of a godless intellectualism, was an historical
fulfilment of his own idea of moral perfection;
Lord Shaftesbury had already drawn out that idea in a
theoretical form, in his celebrated collection of Treatises
which he has called <span class="tei tei-q">“Characteristics of men, manners,
opinions, views;”</span> and it will be a further illustration of
the subject before us, if you will allow me, Gentlemen, to
make some extracts from this work.</p>
<p>
One of his first attacks is directed against the doctrine
of reward and punishment, as if it introduced a notion
into religion inconsistent with the true apprehension of
the beauty of virtue, and with the liberality and nobleness
of spirit in which it should be pursued. <span class="tei tei-q">“Men
have not been content,”</span> he says, <span class="tei tei-q">“to show the natural
advantages of honesty and virtue. They have rather
lessened these, the better, as they thought, to advance
another foundation. They have made virtue so mercenary
a thing, and have talked so much of its rewards,
that one can hardly tell what there is in it, after all, which
can be worth rewarding. For to be <em><span style="font-style: italic">bribed</span></em> only or
<em><span style="font-style: italic">terrified</span></em> into an honest practice, bespeaks little of real
honesty or worth.”</span> <span class="tei tei-q">“If,”</span> he says elsewhere, insinuating
what he dare not speak out, <span class="tei tei-q">“if through hope merely of
reward, or fear of punishment, the creature be inclined
to do the good he hates, or restrained from doing the ill
to which he is not otherwise in the least degree averse
there is in this case no virtue or goodness whatever.
There is no more of rectitude, piety, or sanctity, in a
creature thus reformed, than there is meekness or
gentleness in a tiger strongly chained, or innocence and
sobriety in a monkey under the discipline of the whip.…
While the will is neither gained, nor the inclination
wrought upon, but awe alone prevails and forces obedience,
the obedience is servile, and all which is done
through it merely servile.”</span> That is, he says that
Christianity is the enemy of moral virtue, as influencing
the mind by fear of God, not by love of good.</p>
<p>
The motives then of hope and fear being, to say the
least, put far into the background, and nothing being
morally good but what springs simply or mainly from a
love of virtue for its own sake, this love-inspiring quality
in virtue is its beauty, while a bad conscience is not
much more than the sort of feeling which makes us
shrink from an instrument out of tune. <span class="tei tei-q">“Some by mere
nature,”</span> he says, <span class="tei tei-q">“others by art and practice, are masters
of an ear in music, an eye in painting, a fancy in the
ordinary things of ornament and grace, a judgment in
proportions of all kinds, and a general good taste in
most of those subjects which make the amusement and
delight of the ingenious people of the world. Let such
gentlemen as these be as extravagant as they please, or
as irregular in their morals, they must at the same time
discover their <em><span style="font-style: italic">inconsistency</span></em>, live at <em><span style="font-style: italic">variance</span></em> with themselves,
and in <em><span style="font-style: italic">contradiction</span></em> to that principle on which
they ground their highest pleasure and entertainment.
Of all other <em><span style="font-style: italic">beauties</span></em> which virtuosos pursue, poets
celebrate, musicians sing, and architects or artists of
whatever kind describe or form, the most delightful,
the most engaging and pathetic, is that which is drawn
from real life and from the passions. Nothing affects
the heart like that which is purely from itself, and
of its own nature: such as the beauty of sentiments,
the grace of actions, the turn of characters, and the
<em><span style="font-style: italic">proportions and features</span></em> of a human mind. This lesson
of philosophy, even a romance, a poem, or a play may
teach us.… Let poets or the men of harmony deny,
if they can, this force of nature, or withstand this <em><span style="font-style: italic">moral
magic</span></em>.… Every one is a virtuoso of a higher or
lower degree; every one pursues a grace … of one
kind or other. The <span class="tei tei-hi"><span style="font-style: italic">venustum</span></span>, the
<span class="tei tei-hi"><span style="font-style: italic">honestum</span></span>, the <span class="tei tei-hi"><span style="font-style: italic">decorum</span></span>
of things will force its way.… The most natural
beauty in the world is honesty and moral truth; for all
beauty is truth.”</span></p>
<p>
Accordingly, virtue being only one kind of beauty, the
principle which determines what is virtuous is, not conscience,
but <em><span style="font-style: italic">taste</span></em>. <span class="tei tei-q">“Could we once convince ourselves,”</span>
he says, <span class="tei tei-q">“of what is in itself so evident, viz., that in the
very nature of things there must of necessity be the
foundation of a right and wrong <em><span style="font-style: italic">taste</span></em>, as well in respect
of inward character of features as of outward person, behaviour,
and action, we should be far more ashamed of
ignorance and wrong judgment in the former than in
the latter of these subjects.… One who aspires to the
character of a man of breeding and politeness is careful
to form his judgment of arts and sciences upon right
models of perfection.… He takes particular care to
turn his eye from every thing which is gaudy, luscious,
and of false taste. Nor is he less careful to turn his ear
from every sort of music, besides that which is of the
best manner and truest harmony. 'Twere to be wished
we had the same regard to a <em><span style="font-style: italic">right taste in life and
manners</span></em>.… If civility and humanity be a taste; if
brutality, insolence, riot, be in the same manner a taste, …
who would not endeavour to force nature as well
in this respect as in what relates to a taste or judgment
in other arts and sciences?”</span></p>
<p>
Sometimes he distinctly contrasts this taste with principle
and conscience, and gives it the preference over
them. <span class="tei tei-q">“After all,”</span> he says, <span class="tei tei-q">“<em><span style="font-style: italic">'tis not merely what we
call principle</span></em>, but <em><span style="font-style: italic">a taste</span></em>, which governs men. They
may think for certain, <span class="tei tei-q">‘This is right,’</span> or <span class="tei tei-q">‘that wrong;’</span>
they may believe <span class="tei tei-q">‘this is a virtue,’</span> or <span class="tei tei-q">‘that a sin;’</span> <span class="tei tei-q">‘this
is punishable by man,’</span> or <span class="tei tei-q">‘that by God;’</span> yet if the
savour of things lies cross to honesty, if the fancy be
florid, and the appetite high towards the subaltern
beauties and lower orders of worldly symmetries and
proportions, the conduct will infallibly turn this latter
way.”</span> Thus, somewhat like a Jansenist, he makes the
superior pleasure infallibly conquer, and implies that,
neglecting principle, we have but to train the taste to a
kind of beauty higher than sensual. He adds: <span class="tei tei-q">“<em><span style="font-style: italic">Even
conscience</span></em>, I fear, such as is owing to religious discipline,
will make but a slight figure, when this taste is set
amiss.”</span></p>
<p>
And hence the well-known doctrine of this author,
that ridicule is the test of truth; for truth and virtue
being beauty, and falsehood and vice deformity, and the
feeling inspired by deformity being that of derision, as
that inspired by beauty is admiration, it follows that
vice is not a thing to weep about, but to laugh at.
<span class="tei tei-q">“Nothing is ridiculous,”</span> he says, <span class="tei tei-q">“but what is deformed;
nor is any thing proof against raillery but what is handsome
and just. And therefore 'tis the hardest thing in
the world to deny fair honesty the use of this weapon,
which can never bear an edge against herself, and bears
against every thing contrary.”</span></p>
<p>
And hence again, conscience, which intimates a Law-giver,
being superseded by a moral taste or sentiment,
which has no sanction beyond the constitution of our
nature, it follows that our great rule is to contemplate
ourselves, if we would gain a standard of life and morals.
Thus he has entitled one of his Treatises a <span class="tei tei-q">“Soliloquy,”</span>
with the motto, <span class="tei tei-q">“Nec te quæsiveris extra;”</span> and he
observes, <span class="tei tei-q">“The chief interest of ambition, avarice,
corruption, and every sly insinuating vice, is to prevent
this interview and familiarity of discourse, which is
consequent upon close retirement and inward recess.
'Tis the grand artifice of villainy and lewdness, <em><span style="font-style: italic">as well
as of superstition and bigotry</span></em>, to put us upon terms of
greater distance and formality with ourselves, and evade
our <em><span style="font-style: italic">proving</span></em> method of soliloquy.… A passionate
lover, whatever solitude he may affect, can never be truly
by himself.… 'Tis the same reason which keeps the
imaginary saint or mystic from being capable of this
entertainment. Instead of looking narrowly into his own
nature and mind, that he may be no longer a mystery to
himself, he is taken up with <em><span style="font-style: italic">the contemplation of other
mysterious natures</span></em>, which he never can explain or
comprehend.”</span></p>
<h3><span>8.</span></h3>
<p>
Taking these passages as specimens of what I call the
Religion of Philosophy, it is obvious to observe that
there is no doctrine contained in them which is not in a
certain sense true; yet, on the other hand, that almost
every statement is perverted and made false, because it
is not the whole truth. They are exhibitions of truth
under one aspect, and therefore insufficient; conscience
is most certainly a moral sense, but it is more; vice
again, is a deformity, but it is worse. Lord Shaftesbury
may insist, if he will, that simple and solitary fear cannot
effect a moral conversion, and we are not concerned to
answer him; but he will have a difficulty in proving that
any real conversion follows from a doctrine which makes
virtue a mere point of good taste, and vice vulgar and
ungentlemanlike.</p>
<p>
Such a doctrine is essentially superficial, and such will
be its effects. It has no better measure of right and
wrong than that of visible beauty and tangible fitness.
Conscience indeed inflicts an acute pang, but that pang,
forsooth, is irrational, and to reverence it is an illiberal
superstition. But, if we will make light of what is deepest
within us, nothing is left but to pay homage to what is
more upon the surface. To <em><span style="font-style: italic">seem</span></em> becomes to <em><span style="font-style: italic">be</span></em>; what
looks fair will be good, what causes offence will be evil;
virtue will be what pleases, vice what pains. As well
may we measure virtue by utility as by such a rule.
Nor is this an imaginary apprehension; we all must
recollect the celebrated sentiment into which a great and
wise man was betrayed, in the glowing eloquence of his
valediction to the spirit of chivalry. <span class="tei tei-q">“It is gone,”</span> cries
Mr. Burke; <span class="tei tei-q">“that sensibility of principle, that chastity
of honour, which felt a stain like a wound; which inspired
courage, while it mitigated ferocity; which ennobled
whatever it touched, and under which <em><span style="font-style: italic">vice lost half its
evil by losing all its grossness</span></em>.”</span> In the last clause of this
beautiful sentence we have too apt an illustration of the
ethical temperament of a civilized age. It is detection,
not the sin, which is the crime; private life is sacred,
and inquiry into it is intolerable; and decency is virtue.
Scandals, vulgarities, whatever shocks, whatever disgusts,
are offences of the first order. Drinking and swearing,
squalid poverty, improvidence, laziness, slovenly disorder,
make up the idea of profligacy: poets may say any
thing, however wicked, with impunity; works of genius
may be read without danger or shame, whatever their
principles; fashion, celebrity, the beautiful, the heroic,
will suffice to force any evil upon the community. The
splendours of a court, and the charms of good society,
wit, imagination, taste, and high breeding, the <em><span style="font-style: italic">prestige</span></em>
of rank, and the resources of wealth, are a screen, an
instrument, and an apology for vice and irreligion. And
thus at length we find, surprising as the change may be,
that that very refinement of Intellectualism, which began
by repelling sensuality, ends by excusing it. Under the
shadow indeed of the Church, and in its due development,
Philosophy does service to the cause of morality; but,
when it is strong enough to have a will of its own, and is
lifted up with an idea of its own importance, and attempts
to form a theory, and to lay down a principle, and to
carry out a system of ethics, and undertakes the moral
education of the man, then it does but abet evils to
which at first it seemed instinctively opposed. True
Religion is slow in growth, and, when once planted, is
difficult of dislodgement; but its intellectual counterfeit
has no root in itself: it springs up suddenly, it suddenly
withers. It appeals to what is in nature, and it falls
under the dominion of the old Adam. Then, like
dethroned princes, it keeps up a state and majesty,
when it has lost the real power. Deformity is its abhorrence;
accordingly, since it cannot dissuade men from
vice, therefore in order to escape the sight of its deformity,
it embellishes it. It <span class="tei tei-q">“skins and films the ulcerous
place,”</span> which it cannot probe or heal,</p>
<br/><span class="tei tei-q" style="text-align: left">“Whiles rank corruption, mining all within,</span>
<br/><span class="tei tei-q" style="text-align: left">Infects unseen.”</span>
<p>
And from this shallowness of philosophical Religion
it comes to pass that its disciples seem able to fulfil certain
precepts of Christianity more readily and exactly than
Christians themselves. St. Paul, as I have said, gives us
a pattern of evangelical perfection; he draws the Christian
character in its most graceful form, and its most
beautiful hues. He discourses of that charity which is
patient and meek, humble and single-minded, disinterested,
contented, and persevering. He tells us to prefer
each the other before himself, to give way to each other,
to abstain from rude words and evil speech, to avoid self-conceit,
to be calm and grave, to be cheerful and happy, to
observe peace with all men, truth and justice, courtesy and
gentleness, all that is modest, amiable, virtuous, and of
good repute. Such is St. Paul's exemplar of the Christian
in his external relations; and, I repeat, the school of
the world seems to send out living copies of this typical
excellence with greater success than the Church. At
this day the <span class="tei tei-q">“gentleman”</span> is the creation, not of Christianity,
but of civilization. But the reason is obvious.
The world is content with setting right the surface of
things; the Church aims at regenerating the very depths
of the heart. She ever begins with the beginning; and,
as regards the multitude of her children, is never able
to get beyond the beginning, but is continually employed
in laying the foundation. She is engaged with what is
essential, as previous and as introductory to the ornamental
and the attractive. She is curing men and keeping
them clear of mortal sin; she is <span class="tei tei-q">“treating of justice
and chastity, and the judgment to come:”</span> she is insisting
on faith and hope, and devotion, and honesty,
and the elements of charity; and has so much to do with
precept, that she almost leaves it to inspirations from
Heaven to suggest what is of counsel and perfection.
She aims at what is necessary rather than at what is desirable.
She is for the many as well as for the few. She
is putting souls in the way of salvation, that they may
then be in a condition, if they shall be called upon, to
aspire to the heroic, and to attain the full proportions, as
well as the rudiments, of the beautiful.</p>
<h3><span>9.</span></h3>
<p>
Such is the method, or the policy (so to call it), of the
Church; but Philosophy looks at the matter from a very
different point of view: what have Philosophers to do
with the terror of judgment or the saving of the soul?
Lord Shaftesbury calls the former a sort of <span class="tei tei-q">“panic fear.”</span>
Of the latter he scoffingly complains that <span class="tei tei-q">“the saving of
souls is now the heroic passion of exalted spirits.”</span> Of
course he is at liberty, on his principles, to pick and
choose out of Christianity what he will; he discards the
theological, the mysterious, the spiritual; he makes
selection of the morally or esthetically beautiful. To
him it matters not at all that he begins his teaching
where he should end it; it matters not that, instead of
planting the tree, he merely crops its flowers for his banquet;
he only aims at the present life, his philosophy
dies with him; if his flowers do but last to the end of
his revel, he has nothing more to seek. When night
comes, the withered leaves may be mingled with his own
ashes; he and they will have done their work, he and
they will be no more. Certainly, it costs little to make
men virtuous on conditions such as these; it is like
teaching them a language or an accomplishment, to
write Latin or to play on an instrument,—the profession
of an artist, not the commission of an Apostle.</p>
<p>
This embellishment of the exterior is almost the beginning
and the end of philosophical morality. This is
why it aims at being modest rather than humble; this
is how it can be proud at the very time that it is unassuming.
To humility indeed it does not even aspire;
humility is one of the most difficult of virtues both to
attain and to ascertain. It lies close upon the heart
itself, and its tests are exceedingly delicate and subtle.
Its counterfeits abound; however, we are little concerned
with them here, for, I repeat, it is hardly professed even
by name in the code of ethics which we are reviewing.
As has been often observed, ancient civilization had
not the idea, and had no word to express it: or rather,
it had the idea, and considered it a defect of mind, not
a virtue, so that the word which denoted it conveyed a
reproach. As to the modern world, you may gather its
ignorance of it by its perversion of the somewhat
parallel term <span class="tei tei-q">“condescension.”</span> Humility or condescension,
viewed as a virtue of conduct, may be said to consist,
as in other things, so in our placing ourselves in our
thoughts on a level with our inferiors; it is not only a
voluntary relinquishment of the privileges of our own
station, but an actual participation or assumption of the
condition of those to whom we stoop. This is true
humility, to feel and to behave as if we were low; not, to
cherish a notion of our importance, while we affect a low
position. Such was St. Paul's humility, when he called
himself <span class="tei tei-q">“the least of the saints;”</span> such the humility of
those many holy men who have considered themselves
the greatest of sinners. It is an abdication, as far as their
own thoughts are concerned, of those prerogatives or
privileges to which others deem them entitled. Now it is
not a little instructive to contrast with this idea, Gentlemen,—with
this theological meaning of the word <span class="tei tei-q">“condescension,”</span>—its
proper English sense; put them in
juxta-position, and you will at once see the difference
between the world's humility and the humility of the
Gospel. As the world uses the word, <span class="tei tei-q">“condescension”</span>
is a stooping indeed of the person, but a bending forward,
unattended with any the slightest effort to leave by
a single inch the seat in which it is so firmly established.
It is the act of a superior, who protests to himself, while
he commits it, that he is superior still, and that he is doing
nothing else but an act of grace towards those on whose
level, in theory, he is placing himself. And this is the
nearest idea which the philosopher can form of the virtue
of self-abasement; to do more than this is to his mind a
meanness or an hypocrisy, and at once excites his suspicion
and disgust. What the world is, such it has ever
been; we know the contempt which the educated pagans
had for the martyrs and confessors of the Church; and
it is shared by the anti-Catholic bodies of this day.</p>
<p>
Such are the ethics of Philosophy, when faithfully represented;
but an age like this, not pagan, but professedly
Christian, cannot venture to reprobate humility in
set terms, or to make a boast of pride. Accordingly, it
looks out for some expedient by which it may blind
itself to the real state of the case. Humility, with
its grave and self-denying attributes, it cannot love;
but what is more beautiful, what more winning, than
modesty? what virtue, at first sight, simulates humility
so well? though what in fact is more radically distinct
from it? In truth, great as is its charm, modesty is not
the deepest or the most religious of virtues. Rather it is
the advanced guard or sentinel of the soul militant, and
watches continually over its nascent intercourse with the
world about it. It goes the round of the senses; it
mounts up into the countenance; it protects the eye and
ear; it reigns in the voice and gesture. Its province is
the outward deportment, as other virtues have relation
to matters theological, others to society, and others to
the mind itself. And being more superficial than other
virtues, it is more easily disjoined from their company; it
admits of being associated with principles or qualities
naturally foreign to it, and is often made the cloak of
feelings or ends for which it was never given to us. So
little is it the necessary index of humility, that it is even
compatible with pride. The better for the purpose of
Philosophy; humble it cannot be, so forthwith modesty
becomes its humility.</p>
<p>
Pride, under such training, instead of running to waste
in the education of the mind, is turned to account; it
gets a new name; it is called self-respect; and ceases to
be the disagreeable, uncompanionable quality which it is
in itself. Though it be the motive principle of the soul,
it seldom comes to view; and when it shows itself, then
delicacy and gentleness are its attire, and good sense
and sense of honour direct its motions. It is no longer
a restless agent, without definite aim; it has a large field
of exertion assigned to it, and it subserves those social
interests which it would naturally trouble. It is directed
into the channel of industry, frugality, honesty, and obedience;
and it becomes the very staple of the religion
and morality held in honour in a day like our own. It
becomes the safeguard of chastity, the guarantee of veracity,
in high and low; it is the very household god of
society, as at present constituted, inspiring neatness and
decency in the servant girl, propriety of carriage and refined
manners in her mistress, uprightness, manliness, and
generosity in the head of the family. It diffuses a light
over town and country; it covers the soil with handsome
edifices and smiling gardens; it tills the field, it stocks
and embellishes the shop. It is the stimulating principle
of providence on the one hand, and of free expenditure on
the other; of an honourable ambition, and of elegant enjoyment.
It breathes upon the face of the community, and
the hollow sepulchre is forthwith beautiful to look upon.</p>
<p>
Refined by the civilization which has brought it into
activity, this self-respect infuses into the mind an intense
horror of exposure, and a keen sensitiveness of notoriety
and ridicule. It becomes the enemy of extravagances of
any kind; it shrinks from what are called scenes; it has
no mercy on the mock-heroic, on pretence or egotism, on
verbosity in language, or what is called prosiness in conversation.
It detests gross adulation; not that it tends
at all to the eradication of the appetite to which the
flatterer ministers, but it sees the absurdity of indulging
it, it understands the annoyance thereby given to others,
and if a tribute must be paid to the wealthy or the powerful,
it demands greater subtlety and art in the preparation.
Thus vanity is changed into a more dangerous
self-conceit, as being checked in its natural eruption.
It teaches men to suppress their feelings, and to control
their tempers, and to mitigate both the severity and the
tone of their judgments. As Lord Shaftesbury would
desire, it prefers playful wit and satire in putting down
what is objectionable, as a more refined and good-natured,
as well as a more effectual method, than the
expedient which is natural to uneducated minds. It is
from this impatience of the tragic and the bombastic
that it is now quietly but energetically opposing itself to
the unchristian practice of duelling, which it brands as
simply out of taste, and as the remnant of a barbarous
age; and certainly it seems likely to effect what Religion
has aimed at abolishing in vain.</p>
<h3><span>10.</span></h3>
<p>
Hence it is that it is almost a definition of a gentleman
to say he is one who never inflicts pain. This
description is both refined and, as far as it goes, accurate.
He is mainly occupied in merely removing the
obstacles which hinder the free and unembarrassed
action of those about him; and he concurs with their
movements rather than takes the initiative himself. His
benefits may be considered as parallel to what are called
comforts or conveniences in arrangements of a personal
nature: like an easy chair or a good fire, which do their
part in dispelling cold and fatigue, though nature provides
both means of rest and animal heat without them.
The true gentleman in like manner carefully avoids
whatever may cause a jar or a jolt in the minds of those
with whom he is cast;—all clashing of opinion, or
collision of feeling, all restraint, or suspicion, or gloom,
or resentment; his great concern being to make every
one at their ease and at home. He has his eyes on all
his company; he is tender towards the bashful, gentle
towards the distant, and merciful towards the absurd;
he can recollect to whom he is speaking; he guards
against unseasonable allusions, or topics which may
irritate; he is seldom prominent in conversation, and
never wearisome. He makes light of favours while he
does them, and seems to be receiving when he is conferring.
He never speaks of himself except when compelled,
never defends himself by a mere retort, he has no
ears for slander or gossip, is scrupulous in imputing
motives to those who interfere with him, and interprets
every thing for the best. He is never mean or little in
his disputes, never takes unfair advantage, never mistakes
personalities or sharp sayings for arguments, or insinuates
evil which he dare not say out. From a long-sighted
prudence, he observes the maxim of the ancient
sage, that we should ever conduct ourselves towards our
enemy as if he were one day to be our friend. He has
too much good sense to be affronted at insults, he is too
well employed to remember injuries, and too indolent to
bear malice. He is patient, forbearing, and resigned, on
philosophical principles; he submits to pain, because it
is inevitable, to bereavement, because it is irreparable,
and to death, because it is his destiny. If he engages in
controversy of any kind, his disciplined intellect preserves
him from the blundering discourtesy of better, perhaps,
but less educated minds; who, like blunt weapons,
tear and hack instead of cutting clean, who mistake the
point in argument, waste their strength on trifles, misconceive
their adversary, and leave the question more
involved than they find it. He may be right or wrong
in his opinion, but he is too clear-headed to be unjust;
he is as simple as he is forcible, and as brief as he is
decisive. Nowhere shall we find greater candour, consideration,
indulgence: he throws himself into the minds
of his opponents, he accounts for their mistakes. He
knows the weakness of human reason as well as its
strength, its province and its limits. If he be an unbeliever,
he will be too profound and large-minded to
ridicule religion or to act against it; he is too wise to be
a dogmatist or fanatic in his infidelity. He respects piety
and devotion; he even supports institutions as venerable,
beautiful, or useful, to which he does not assent;
he honours the ministers of religion, and it contents
him to decline its mysteries without assailing or denouncing
them. He is a friend of religious toleration,
and that, not only because his philosophy has taught
him to look on all forms of faith with an impartial eye,
but also from the gentleness and effeminacy of feeling,
which is the attendant on civilization.</p>
<p>
Not that he may not hold a religion too, in his own
way, even when he is not a Christian. In that case his
religion is one of imagination and sentiment; it is the
embodiment of those ideas of the sublime, majestic,
and beautiful, without which there can be no large
philosophy. Sometimes he acknowledges the being of
God, sometimes he invests an unknown principle or
quality with the attributes of perfection. And this deduction
of his reason, or creation of his fancy, he makes
the occasion of such excellent thoughts, and the starting-point
of so varied and systematic a teaching, that he
even seems like a disciple of Christianity itself. From
the very accuracy and steadiness of his logical powers,
he is able to see what sentiments are consistent in those
who hold any religious doctrine at all, and he appears to
others to feel and to hold a whole circle of theological
truths, which exist in his mind no otherwise than as a
number of deductions.</p>
<br>* * * * *
<p>
Such are some of the lineaments of the ethical character,
which the cultivated intellect will form, apart from
religious principle. They are seen within the pale of the
Church and without it, in holy men, and in profligate;
they form the <span class="tei tei-hi"><span style="font-style: italic">beau-ideal</span></span> of the world; they partly assist
and partly distort the development of the Catholic.
They may subserve the education of a St. Francis de
Sales or a Cardinal Pole; they may be the limits of the
contemplation of a Shaftesbury or a Gibbon. Basil and
Julian were fellow-students at the schools of Athens;
and one became the Saint and Doctor of the Church, the
other her scoffing and relentless foe.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />