<SPAN name="startofbook"></SPAN>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<h1> WHAT’S WRONG WITH THE WORLD </h1>
<p><br/></p>
<h2> By G.K. Chesterton </h2>
<p><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><br/></p>
<blockquote>
<p><big><b>CONTENTS</b></big></p>
<p><br/></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_PART1"> <b>PART ONE. THE HOMELESSNESS OF MAN</b> </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0002"> I. THE MEDICAL MISTAKE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0003"> II. WANTED, AN UNPRACTICAL MAN </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0004"> III. THE NEW HYPOCRITE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0005"> IV. THE FEAR OF THE PAST </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0006"> V. THE UNFINISHED TEMPLE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0007"> VI. THE ENEMIES OF PROPERTY </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0008"> VII. THE FREE FAMILY </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0009"> VIII. THE WILDNESS OF DOMESTICITY </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0010"> IX. HISTORY OF HUDGE AND GUDGE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0011"> X. OPPRESSION BY OPTIMISM </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0012"> XI. THE HOMELESSNESS OF JONES </SPAN></p>
<p><br/></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_PART2"> <b>PART TWO. IMPERIALISM, OR THE MISTAKE ABOUT
MAN</b> </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0014"> I. THE CHARM OF JINGOISM </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0015"> II. WISDOM AND THE WEATHER </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0016"> III. THE COMMON VISION </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0017"> IV. THE INSANE NECESSITY </SPAN></p>
<p><br/></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_PART3"> <b>PART THREE. FEMINISM, OR THE MISTAKE ABOUT
WOMAN</b> </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0019"> I. THE UNMILITARY SUFFRAGETTE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0020"> II. THE UNIVERSAL STICK </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0021"> III. THE EMANCIPATION OF DOMESTICITY </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0022"> IV. THE ROMANCE OF THRIFT </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0023"> V. THE COLDNESS OF CHLOE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0024"> VI. THE PEDANT AND THE SAVAGE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0025"> VII. THE MODERN SURRENDER OF WOMAN </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0026"> VIII. THE BRAND OF THE FLEUR-DE-LIS </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0027"> IX. SINCERITY AND THE GALLOWS </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0028"> X. THE HIGHER ANARCHY </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0029"> XI. THE QUEEN AND THE SUFFRAGETTES </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0030"> XII. THE MODERN SLAVE </SPAN></p>
<p><br/></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_PART4"> <b>PART FOUR. EDUCATION: OR THE MISTAKE ABOUT
THE CHILD</b> </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0032"> I. THE CALVINISM OF TO-DAY </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0033"> II. THE TRIBAL TERROR </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0034"> III. THE TRICKS OF ENVIRONMENT </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0035"> IV. THE TRUTH ABOUT EDUCATION </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0036"> V. AN EVIL CRY </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0037"> VI. AUTHORITY THE UNAVOIDABLE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0038"> VII. THE HUMILITY OF MRS. GRUNDY </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0039"> VIII. THE BROKEN RAINBOW </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0040"> IX. THE NEED FOR NARROWNESS </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0041"> X. THE CASE FOR THE PUBLIC SCHOOLS </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0042"> XI. THE SCHOOL FOR HYPOCRITES </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0043"> XII. THE STALENESS OF THE NEW SCHOOLS </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0044"> XIII. THE OUTLAWED PARENT </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0045"> XIV. FOLLY AND FEMALE EDUCATION </SPAN></p>
<p><br/></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_PART5"> <b>PART FIVE. THE HOME OF MAN</b> </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0047"> I. THE EMPIRE OF THE INSECT </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0048"> II. THE FALLACY OF THE UMBRELLA STAND </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0049"> III. THE DREADFUL DUTY OF GUDGE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0050"> IV. A LAST INSTANCE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0051"> V. CONCLUSION </SPAN></p>
<p><br/></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0052"> <b>THREE NOTES</b> </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0053"> I. ON FEMALE SUFFRAGE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0054"> II. ON CLEANLINESS IN EDUCATION </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_4_0055"> III. ON PEASANT PROPRIETORSHIP </SPAN></p>
</blockquote>
<p><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><br/></p>
<blockquote>
<p><big> <br/> </big><b>DEDICATION</b> <br/> To C. F G. Masterman, M. P.
<br/> My Dear Charles, <br/> I originally called this book “What is
Wrong,” and it would <br/> have satisfied your sardonic temper to note
the number of social <br/> misunderstandings that arose from the use of
the title. Many a mild lady <br/> visitor opened her eyes when I
remarked casually, “I have been doing <br/> ‘What is Wrong’ all this
morning.” And one minister of religion moved <br/> quite sharply in his
chair when I told him (as he understood it) that I <br/> had to run
upstairs and do what was wrong, but should be down again in <br/> a
minute. Exactly of what occult vice they silently accused me I cannot
<br/> conjecture, but I know of what I accuse myself; and that is, of
having <br/> written a very shapeless and inadequate book, and one quite
unworthy <br/> to be dedicated to you. As far as literature goes, this
book is what is <br/> wrong and no mistake. <br/><br/> It may seem a
refinement of insolence to present so wild a composition <br/> to one
who has recorded two or three of the really impressive visions of <br/>
the moving millions of England. You are the only man alive who can <br/>
make the map of England crawl with life; a most creepy and enviable
<br/> accomplishment. Why then should I trouble you with a book which,
even <br/> if it achieves its object (which is monstrously unlikely) can
only be a <br/> thundering gallop of theory? <br/><br/> Well, I do it
partly because I think you politicians are none the worse <br/> for a
few inconvenient ideals; but more because you will recognise the <br/>
many arguments we have had, those arguments which the most wonderful
<br/> ladies in the world can never endure for very long. And, perhaps,
you <br/> will agree with me that the thread of comradeship and
conversation must <br/> be protected because it is so frivolous. It must
be held sacred, it <br/> must not be snapped, because it is not worth
tying together again. It <br/> is exactly because argument is idle that
men (I mean males) must take it <br/> seriously; for when (we feel),
until the crack of doom, shall we have so <br/> delightful a difference
again? But most of all I offer it to you because <br/> there exists not
only comradeship, but a very different thing, called <br/> friendship;
an agreement under all the arguments and a thread which, <br/> please
God, will never break. <br/><br/> Yours always, <br/><br/> G. K.
Chesterton. <br/></p>
</blockquote>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_PART1" id="link2H_PART1"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> PART ONE. THE HOMELESSNESS OF MAN </h2>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0002" id="link2H_4_0002"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> I. THE MEDICAL MISTAKE </h2>
<p>A book of modern social inquiry has a shape that is somewhat sharply
defined. It begins as a rule with an analysis, with statistics, tables of
population, decrease of crime among Congregationalists, growth of hysteria
among policemen, and similar ascertained facts; it ends with a chapter
that is generally called “The Remedy.” It is almost wholly due to this
careful, solid, and scientific method that “The Remedy” is never found.
For this scheme of medical question and answer is a blunder; the first
great blunder of sociology. It is always called stating the disease before
we find the cure. But it is the whole definition and dignity of man that
in social matters we must actually find the cure before we find the
disease.</p>
<p>The fallacy is one of the fifty fallacies that come from the modern
madness for biological or bodily metaphors. It is convenient to speak of
the Social Organism, just as it is convenient to speak of the British
Lion. But Britain is no more an organism than Britain is a lion. The
moment we begin to give a nation the unity and simplicity of an animal, we
begin to think wildly. Because every man is a biped, fifty men are not a
centipede. This has produced, for instance, the gaping absurdity of
perpetually talking about “young nations” and “dying nations,” as if a
nation had a fixed and physical span of life. Thus people will say that
Spain has entered a final senility; they might as well say that Spain is
losing all her teeth. Or people will say that Canada should soon produce a
literature; which is like saying that Canada must soon grow a new
moustache. Nations consist of people; the first generation may be
decrepit, or the ten thousandth may be vigorous. Similar applications of
the fallacy are made by those who see in the increasing size of national
possessions, a simple increase in wisdom and stature, and in favor with
God and man. These people, indeed, even fall short in subtlety of the
parallel of a human body. They do not even ask whether an empire is
growing taller in its youth, or only growing fatter in its old age. But of
all the instances of error arising from this physical fancy, the worst is
that we have before us: the habit of exhaustively describing a social
sickness, and then propounding a social drug.</p>
<p>Now we do talk first about the disease in cases of bodily breakdown; and
that for an excellent reason. Because, though there may be doubt about the
way in which the body broke down, there is no doubt at all about the shape
in which it should be built up again. No doctor proposes to produce a new
kind of man, with a new arrangement of eyes or limbs. The hospital, by
necessity, may send a man home with one leg less: but it will not (in a
creative rapture) send him home with one leg extra. Medical science is
content with the normal human body, and only seeks to restore it.</p>
<p>But social science is by no means always content with the normal human
soul; it has all sorts of fancy souls for sale. Man as a social idealist
will say “I am tired of being a Puritan; I want to be a Pagan,” or “Beyond
this dark probation of Individualism I see the shining paradise of
Collectivism.” Now in bodily ills there is none of this difference about
the ultimate ideal. The patient may or may not want quinine; but he
certainly wants health. No one says “I am tired of this headache; I want
some toothache,” or “The only thing for this Russian influenza is a few
German measles,” or “Through this dark probation of catarrh I see the
shining paradise of rheumatism.” But exactly the whole difficulty in our
public problems is that some men are aiming at cures which other men would
regard as worse maladies; are offering ultimate conditions as states of
health which others would uncompromisingly call states of disease. Mr.
Belloc once said that he would no more part with the idea of property than
with his teeth; yet to Mr. Bernard Shaw property is not a tooth, but a
toothache. Lord Milner has sincerely attempted to introduce German
efficiency; and many of us would as soon welcome German measles. Dr.
Saleeby would honestly like to have Eugenics; but I would rather have
rheumatics.</p>
<p>This is the arresting and dominant fact about modern social discussion;
that the quarrel is not merely about the difficulties, but about the aim.
We agree about the evil; it is about the good that we should tear each
other’s eyes out. We all admit that a lazy aristocracy is a bad thing. We
should not by any means all admit that an active aristocracy would be a
good thing. We all feel angry with an irreligious priesthood; but some of
us would go mad with disgust at a really religious one. Everyone is
indignant if our army is weak, including the people who would be even more
indignant if it were strong. The social case is exactly the opposite of
the medical case. We do not disagree, like doctors, about the precise
nature of the illness, while agreeing about the nature of health. On the
contrary, we all agree that England is unhealthy, but half of us would not
look at her in what the other half would call blooming health. Public
abuses are so prominent and pestilent that they sweep all generous people
into a sort of fictitious unanimity. We forget that, while we agree about
the abuses of things, we should differ very much about the uses of them.
Mr. Cadbury and I would agree about the bad public house. It would be
precisely in front of the good public-house that our painful personal
fracas would occur.</p>
<p>I maintain, therefore, that the common sociological method is quite
useless: that of first dissecting abject poverty or cataloguing
prostitution. We all dislike abject poverty; but it might be another
business if we began to discuss independent and dignified poverty. We all
disapprove of prostitution; but we do not all approve of purity. The only
way to discuss the social evil is to get at once to the social ideal. We
can all see the national madness; but what is national sanity? I have
called this book “What Is Wrong with the World?” and the upshot of the
title can be easily and clearly stated. What is wrong is that we do not
ask what is right.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0003" id="link2H_4_0003"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> II. WANTED, AN UNPRACTICAL MAN </h2>
<p>There is a popular philosophical joke intended to typify the endless and
useless arguments of philosophers; I mean the joke about which came first,
the chicken or the egg? I am not sure that properly understood, it is so
futile an inquiry after all. I am not concerned here to enter on those
deep metaphysical and theological differences of which the chicken and egg
debate is a frivolous, but a very felicitous, type. The evolutionary
materialists are appropriately enough represented in the vision of all
things coming from an egg, a dim and monstrous oval germ that had laid
itself by accident. That other supernatural school of thought (to which I
personally adhere) would be not unworthily typified in the fancy that this
round world of ours is but an egg brooded upon by a sacred unbegotten
bird; the mystic dove of the prophets. But it is to much humbler functions
that I here call the awful power of such a distinction. Whether or no the
living bird is at the beginning of our mental chain, it is absolutely
necessary that it should be at the end of our mental chain. The bird is
the thing to be aimed at—not with a gun, but a life-bestowing wand.
What is essential to our right thinking is this: that the egg and the bird
must not be thought of as equal cosmic occurrences recurring alternatively
forever. They must not become a mere egg and bird pattern, like the egg
and dart pattern. One is a means and the other an end; they are in
different mental worlds. Leaving the complications of the human
breakfast-table out of account, in an elemental sense, the egg only exists
to produce the chicken. But the chicken does not exist only in order to
produce another egg. He may also exist to amuse himself, to praise God,
and even to suggest ideas to a French dramatist. Being a conscious life,
he is, or may be, valuable in himself. Now our modern politics are full of
a noisy forgetfulness; forgetfulness that the production of this happy and
conscious life is after all the aim of all complexities and compromises.
We talk of nothing but useful men and working institutions; that is, we
only think of the chickens as things that will lay more eggs. Instead of
seeking to breed our ideal bird, the eagle of Zeus or the Swan of Avon, or
whatever we happen to want, we talk entirely in terms of the process and
the embryo. The process itself, divorced from its divine object, becomes
doubtful and even morbid; poison enters the embryo of everything; and our
politics are rotten eggs.</p>
<p>Idealism is only considering everything in its practical essence. Idealism
only means that we should consider a poker in reference to poking before
we discuss its suitability for wife-beating; that we should ask if an egg
is good enough for practical poultry-rearing before we decide that the egg
is bad enough for practical politics. But I know that this primary pursuit
of the theory (which is but pursuit of the aim) exposes one to the cheap
charge of fiddling while Rome is burning. A school, of which Lord Rosebery
is representative, has endeavored to substitute for the moral or social
ideals which have hitherto been the motive of politics a general coherency
or completeness in the social system which has gained the nick-name of
“efficiency.” I am not very certain of the secret doctrine of this sect in
the matter. But, as far as I can make out, “efficiency” means that we
ought to discover everything about a machine except what it is for. There
has arisen in our time a most singular fancy: the fancy that when things
go very wrong we need a practical man. It would be far truer to say, that
when things go very wrong we need an unpractical man. Certainly, at least,
we need a theorist. A practical man means a man accustomed to mere daily
practice, to the way things commonly work. When things will not work, you
must have the thinker, the man who has some doctrine about why they work
at all. It is wrong to fiddle while Rome is burning; but it is quite right
to study the theory of hydraulics while Rome is burning.</p>
<p>It is then necessary to drop one’s daily agnosticism and attempt rerum
cognoscere causas. If your aeroplane has a slight indisposition, a handy
man may mend it. But, if it is seriously ill, it is all the more likely
that some absent-minded old professor with wild white hair will have to be
dragged out of a college or laboratory to analyze the evil. The more
complicated the smash, the whiter-haired and more absent-minded will be
the theorist who is needed to deal with it; and in some extreme cases, no
one but the man (probably insane) who invented your flying-ship could
possibly say what was the matter with it.</p>
<p>“Efficiency,” of course, is futile for the same reason that strong men,
will-power and the superman are futile. That is, it is futile because it
only deals with actions after they have been performed. It has no
philosophy for incidents before they happen; therefore it has no power of
choice. An act can only be successful or unsuccessful when it is over; if
it is to begin, it must be, in the abstract, right or wrong. There is no
such thing as backing a winner; for he cannot be a winner when he is
backed. There is no such thing as fighting on the winning side; one fights
to find out which is the winning side. If any operation has occurred, that
operation was efficient. If a man is murdered, the murder was efficient. A
tropical sun is as efficient in making people lazy as a Lancashire foreman
bully in making them energetic. Maeterlinck is as efficient in filling a
man with strange spiritual tremors as Messrs. Crosse and Blackwell are in
filling a man with jam. But it all depends on what you want to be filled
with. Lord Rosebery, being a modern skeptic, probably prefers the
spiritual tremors. I, being an orthodox Christian, prefer the jam. But
both are efficient when they have been effected; and inefficient until
they are effected. A man who thinks much about success must be the
drowsiest sentimentalist; for he must be always looking back. If he only
likes victory he must always come late for the battle. For the man of
action there is nothing but idealism.</p>
<p>This definite ideal is a far more urgent and practical matter in our
existing English trouble than any immediate plans or proposals. For the
present chaos is due to a sort of general oblivion of all that men were
originally aiming at. No man demands what he desires; each man demands
what he fancies he can get. Soon people forget what the man really wanted
first; and after a successful and vigorous political life, he forgets it
himself. The whole is an extravagant riot of second bests, a pandemonium
of pis-aller. Now this sort of pliability does not merely prevent any
heroic consistency, it also prevents any really practical compromise. One
can only find the middle distance between two points if the two points
will stand still. We may make an arrangement between two litigants who
cannot both get what they want; but not if they will not even tell us what
they want. The keeper of a restaurant would much prefer that each customer
should give his order smartly, though it were for stewed ibis or boiled
elephant, rather than that each customer should sit holding his head in
his hands, plunged in arithmetical calculations about how much food there
can be on the premises. Most of us have suffered from a certain sort of
ladies who, by their perverse unselfishness, give more trouble than the
selfish; who almost clamor for the unpopular dish and scramble for the
worst seat. Most of us have known parties or expeditions full of this
seething fuss of self-effacement. From much meaner motives than those of
such admirable women, our practical politicians keep things in the same
confusion through the same doubt about their real demands. There is
nothing that so much prevents a settlement as a tangle of small
surrenders. We are bewildered on every side by politicians who are in
favor of secular education, but think it hopeless to work for it; who
desire total prohibition, but are certain they should not demand it; who
regret compulsory education, but resignedly continue it; or who want
peasant proprietorship and therefore vote for something else. It is this
dazed and floundering opportunism that gets in the way of everything. If
our statesmen were visionaries something practical might be done. If we
ask for something in the abstract we might get something in the concrete.
As it is, it is not only impossible to get what one wants, but it is
impossible to get any part of it, because nobody can mark it out plainly
like a map. That clear and even hard quality that there was in the old
bargaining has wholly vanished. We forget that the word “compromise”
contains, among other things, the rigid and ringing word “promise.”
Moderation is not vague; it is as definite as perfection. The middle point
is as fixed as the extreme point.</p>
<p>If I am made to walk the plank by a pirate, it is vain for me to offer, as
a common-sense compromise, to walk along the plank for a reasonable
distance. It is exactly about the reasonable distance that the pirate and
I differ. There is an exquisite mathematical split second at which the
plank tips up. My common-sense ends just before that instant; the pirate’s
common-sense begins just beyond it. But the point itself is as hard as any
geometrical diagram; as abstract as any theological dogma.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0004" id="link2H_4_0004"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> III. THE NEW HYPOCRITE </h2>
<p>But this new cloudy political cowardice has rendered useless the old
English compromise. People have begun to be terrified of an improvement
merely because it is complete. They call it utopian and revolutionary that
anyone should really have his own way, or anything be really done, and
done with. Compromise used to mean that half a loaf was better than no
bread. Among modern statesmen it really seems to mean that half a loaf is
better than a whole loaf.</p>
<p>As an instance to sharpen the argument, I take the one case of our
everlasting education bills. We have actually contrived to invent a new
kind of hypocrite. The old hypocrite, Tartuffe or Pecksniff, was a man
whose aims were really worldly and practical, while he pretended that they
were religious. The new hypocrite is one whose aims are really religious,
while he pretends that they are worldly and practical. The Rev. Brown, the
Wesleyan minister, sturdily declares that he cares nothing for creeds, but
only for education; meanwhile, in truth, the wildest Wesleyanism is
tearing his soul. The Rev. Smith, of the Church of England, explains
gracefully, with the Oxford manner, that the only question for him is the
prosperity and efficiency of the schools; while in truth all the evil
passions of a curate are roaring within him. It is a fight of creeds
masquerading as policies. I think these reverend gentlemen do themselves
wrong; I think they are more pious than they will admit. Theology is not
(as some suppose) expunged as an error. It is merely concealed, like a
sin. Dr. Clifford really wants a theological atmosphere as much as Lord
Halifax; only it is a different one. If Dr. Clifford would ask plainly for
Puritanism and Lord Halifax ask plainly for Catholicism, something might
be done for them. We are all, one hopes, imaginative enough to recognize
the dignity and distinctness of another religion, like Islam or the cult
of Apollo. I am quite ready to respect another man’s faith; but it is too
much to ask that I should respect his doubt, his worldly hesitations and
fictions, his political bargain and make-believe. Most Nonconformists with
an instinct for English history could see something poetic and national
about the Archbishop of Canterbury as an Archbishop of Canterbury. It is
when he does the rational British statesman that they very justifiably get
annoyed. Most Anglicans with an eye for pluck and simplicity could admire
Dr. Clifford as a Baptist minister. It is when he says that he is simply a
citizen that nobody can possibly believe him.</p>
<p>But indeed the case is yet more curious than this. The one argument that
used to be urged for our creedless vagueness was that at least it saved us
from fanaticism. But it does not even do that. On the contrary, it creates
and renews fanaticism with a force quite peculiar to itself. This is at
once so strange and so true that I will ask the reader’s attention to it
with a little more precision.</p>
<p>Some people do not like the word “dogma.” Fortunately they are free, and
there is an alternative for them. There are two things, and two things
only, for the human mind, a dogma and a prejudice. The Middle Ages were a
rational epoch, an age of doctrine. Our age is, at its best, a poetical
epoch, an age of prejudice. A doctrine is a definite point; a prejudice is
a direction. That an ox may be eaten, while a man should not be eaten, is
a doctrine. That as little as possible of anything should be eaten is a
prejudice; which is also sometimes called an ideal. Now a direction is
always far more fantastic than a plan. I would rather have the most
archaic map of the road to Brighton than a general recommendation to turn
to the left. Straight lines that are not parallel must meet at last; but
curves may recoil forever. A pair of lovers might walk along the frontier
of France and Germany, one on the one side and one on the other, so long
as they were not vaguely told to keep away from each other. And this is a
strictly true parable of the effect of our modern vagueness in losing and
separating men as in a mist.</p>
<p>It is not merely true that a creed unites men. Nay, a difference of creed
unites men—so long as it is a clear difference. A boundary unites.
Many a magnanimous Moslem and chivalrous Crusader must have been nearer to
each other, because they were both dogmatists, than any two homeless
agnostics in a pew of Mr. Campbell’s chapel. “I say God is One,” and “I
say God is One but also Three,” that is the beginning of a good
quarrelsome, manly friendship. But our age would turn these creeds into
tendencies. It would tell the Trinitarian to follow multiplicity as such
(because it was his “temperament”), and he would turn up later with three
hundred and thirty-three persons in the Trinity. Meanwhile, it would turn
the Moslem into a Monist: a frightful intellectual fall. It would force
that previously healthy person not only to admit that there was one God,
but to admit that there was nobody else. When each had, for a long enough
period, followed the gleam of his own nose (like the Dong) they would
appear again; the Christian a Polytheist, and the Moslem a Panegoist, both
quite mad, and far more unfit to understand each other than before.</p>
<p>It is exactly the same with politics. Our political vagueness divides men,
it does not fuse them. Men will walk along the edge of a chasm in clear
weather, but they will edge miles away from it in a fog. So a Tory can
walk up to the very edge of Socialism, if he knows what is Socialism. But
if he is told that Socialism is a spirit, a sublime atmosphere, a noble,
indefinable tendency, why, then he keeps out of its way; and quite right
too. One can meet an assertion with argument; but healthy bigotry is the
only way in which one can meet a tendency. I am told that the Japanese
method of wrestling consists not of suddenly pressing, but of suddenly
giving way. This is one of my many reasons for disliking the Japanese
civilization. To use surrender as a weapon is the very worst spirit of the
East. But certainly there is no force so hard to fight as the force which
it is easy to conquer; the force that always yields and then returns. Such
is the force of a great impersonal prejudice, such as possesses the modern
world on so many points. Against this there is no weapon at all except a
rigid and steely sanity, a resolution not to listen to fads, and not to be
infected by diseases.</p>
<p>In short, the rational human faith must armor itself with prejudice in an
age of prejudices, just as it armoured itself with logic in an age of
logic. But the difference between the two mental methods is marked and
unmistakable. The essential of the difference is this: that prejudices are
divergent, whereas creeds are always in collision. Believers bump into
each other; whereas bigots keep out of each other’s way. A creed is a
collective thing, and even its sins are sociable. A prejudice is a private
thing, and even its tolerance is misanthropic. So it is with our existing
divisions. They keep out of each other’s way; the Tory paper and the
Radical paper do not answer each other; they ignore each other. Genuine
controversy, fair cut and thrust before a common audience, has become in
our special epoch very rare. For the sincere controversialist is above all
things a good listener. The really burning enthusiast never interrupts; he
listens to the enemy’s arguments as eagerly as a spy would listen to the
enemy’s arrangements. But if you attempt an actual argument with a modern
paper of opposite politics, you will find that no medium is admitted
between violence and evasion. You will have no answer except slanging or
silence. A modern editor must not have that eager ear that goes with the
honest tongue. He may be deaf and silent; and that is called dignity. Or
he may be deaf and noisy; and that is called slashing journalism. In
neither case is there any controversy; for the whole object of modern
party combatants is to charge out of earshot.</p>
<p>The only logical cure for all this is the assertion of a human ideal. In
dealing with this, I will try to be as little transcendental as is
consistent with reason; it is enough to say that unless we have some
doctrine of a divine man, all abuses may be excused, since evolution may
turn them into uses. It will be easy for the scientific plutocrat to
maintain that humanity will adapt itself to any conditions which we now
consider evil. The old tyrants invoked the past; the new tyrants will
invoke the future evolution has produced the snail and the owl; evolution
can produce a workman who wants no more space than a snail, and no more
light than an owl. The employer need not mind sending a Kaffir to work
underground; he will soon become an underground animal, like a mole. He
need not mind sending a diver to hold his breath in the deep seas; he will
soon be a deep-sea animal. Men need not trouble to alter conditions,
conditions will so soon alter men. The head can be beaten small enough to
fit the hat. Do not knock the fetters off the slave; knock the slave until
he forgets the fetters. To all this plausible modern argument for
oppression, the only adequate answer is, that there is a permanent human
ideal that must not be either confused or destroyed. The most important
man on earth is the perfect man who is not there. The Christian religion
has specially uttered the ultimate sanity of Man, says Scripture, who
shall judge the incarnate and human truth. Our lives and laws are not
judged by divine superiority, but simply by human perfection. It is man,
says Aristotle, who is the measure. It is the Son of Man, says Scripture,
who shall judge the quick and the dead.</p>
<p>Doctrine, therefore, does not cause dissensions; rather a doctrine alone
can cure our dissensions. It is necessary to ask, however, roughly, what
abstract and ideal shape in state or family would fulfil the human hunger;
and this apart from whether we can completely obtain it or not. But when
we come to ask what is the need of normal men, what is the desire of all
nations, what is the ideal house, or road, or rule, or republic, or king,
or priesthood, then we are confronted with a strange and irritating
difficulty peculiar to the present time; and we must call a temporary halt
and examine that obstacle.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0005" id="link2H_4_0005"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> IV. THE FEAR OF THE PAST </h2>
<p>The last few decades have been marked by a special cultivation of the
romance of the future. We seem to have made up our minds to misunderstand
what has happened; and we turn, with a sort of relief, to stating what
will happen—which is (apparently) much easier. The modern man no
longer presents the memoirs of his great grandfather; but is engaged in
writing a detailed and authoritative biography of his great-grandson.
Instead of trembling before the specters of the dead, we shudder abjectly
under the shadow of the babe unborn. This spirit is apparent everywhere,
even to the creation of a form of futurist romance. Sir Walter Scott
stands at the dawn of the nineteenth century for the novel of the past;
Mr. H. G. Wells stands at the dawn of the twentieth century for the novel
of the future. The old story, we know, was supposed to begin: “Late on a
winter’s evening two horsemen might have been seen—.” The new story
has to begin: “Late on a winter’s evening two aviators will be seen—.”
The movement is not without its elements of charm; there is something
spirited, if eccentric, in the sight of so many people fighting over again
the fights that have not yet happened; of people still glowing with the
memory of tomorrow morning. A man in advance of the age is a familiar
phrase enough. An age in advance of the age is really rather odd.</p>
<p>But when full allowance has been made for this harmless element of poetry
and pretty human perversity in the thing, I shall not hesitate to maintain
here that this cult of the future is not only a weakness but a cowardice
of the age. It is the peculiar evil of this epoch that even its pugnacity
is fundamentally frightened; and the Jingo is contemptible not because he
is impudent, but because he is timid. The reason why modern armaments do
not inflame the imagination like the arms and emblazonments of the
Crusades is a reason quite apart from optical ugliness or beauty. Some
battleships are as beautiful as the sea; and many Norman nosepieces were
as ugly as Norman noses. The atmospheric ugliness that surrounds our
scientific war is an emanation from that evil panic which is at the heart
of it. The charge of the Crusades was a charge; it was charging towards
God, the wild consolation of the braver. The charge of the modern
armaments is not a charge at all. It is a rout, a retreat, a flight from
the devil, who will catch the hindmost. It is impossible to imagine a
mediaeval knight talking of longer and longer French lances, with
precisely the quivering employed about larger and larger German ships The
man who called the Blue Water School the “Blue Funk School” uttered a
psychological truth which that school itself would scarcely essentially
deny. Even the two-power standard, if it be a necessity, is in a sense a
degrading necessity. Nothing has more alienated many magnanimous minds
from Imperial enterprises than the fact that they are always exhibited as
stealthy or sudden defenses against a world of cold rapacity and fear. The
Boer War, for instance, was colored not so much by the creed that we were
doing something right, as by the creed that Boers and Germans were
probably doing something wrong; driving us (as it was said) to the sea.
Mr. Chamberlain, I think, said that the war was a feather in his cap and
so it was: a white feather.</p>
<p>Now this same primary panic that I feel in our rush towards patriotic
armaments I feel also in our rush towards future visions of society. The
modern mind is forced towards the future by a certain sense of fatigue,
not unmixed with terror, with which it regards the past. It is propelled
towards the coming time; it is, in the exact words of the popular phrase,
knocked into the middle of next week. And the goad which drives it on thus
eagerly is not an affectation for futurity Futurity does not exist,
because it is still future. Rather it is a fear of the past; a fear not
merely of the evil in the past, but of the good in the past also. The
brain breaks down under the unbearable virtue of mankind. There have been
so many flaming faiths that we cannot hold; so many harsh heroisms that we
cannot imitate; so many great efforts of monumental building or of
military glory which seem to us at once sublime and pathetic. The future
is a refuge from the fierce competition of our forefathers. The older
generation, not the younger, is knocking at our door. It is agreeable to
escape, as Henley said, into the Street of By-and-Bye, where stands the
Hostelry of Never. It is pleasant to play with children, especially unborn
children. The future is a blank wall on which every man can write his own
name as large as he likes; the past I find already covered with illegible
scribbles, such as Plato, Isaiah, Shakespeare, Michael Angelo, Napoleon. I
can make the future as narrow as myself; the past is obliged to be as
broad and turbulent as humanity. And the upshot of this modern attitude is
really this: that men invent new ideals because they dare not attempt old
ideals. They look forward with enthusiasm, because they are afraid to look
back.</p>
<p>Now in history there is no Revolution that is not a Restoration. Among the
many things that leave me doubtful about the modern habit of fixing eyes
on the future, none is stronger than this: that all the men in history who
have really done anything with the future have had their eyes fixed upon
the past. I need not mention the Renaissance, the very word proves my
case. The originality of Michael Angelo and Shakespeare began with the
digging up of old vases and manuscripts. The mildness of poets absolutely
arose out of the mildness of antiquaries. So the great mediaeval revival
was a memory of the Roman Empire. So the Reformation looked back to the
Bible and Bible times. So the modern Catholic movement has looked back to
patristic times. But that modern movement which many would count the most
anarchic of all is in this sense the most conservative of all. Never was
the past more venerated by men than it was by the French Revolutionists.
They invoked the little republics of antiquity with the complete
confidence of one who invokes the gods. The Sans-culottes believed (as
their name might imply) in a return to simplicity. They believed most
piously in a remote past; some might call it a mythical past. For some
strange reason man must always thus plant his fruit trees in a graveyard.
Man can only find life among the dead. Man is a misshapen monster, with
his feet set forward and his face turned back. He can make the future
luxuriant and gigantic, so long as he is thinking about the past. When he
tries to think about the future itself, his mind diminishes to a pin point
with imbecility, which some call Nirvana. To-morrow is the Gorgon; a man
must only see it mirrored in the shining shield of yesterday. If he sees
it directly he is turned to stone. This has been the fate of all those who
have really seen fate and futurity as clear and inevitable. The
Calvinists, with their perfect creed of predestination, were turned to
stone. The modern sociological scientists (with their excruciating
Eugenics) are turned to stone. The only difference is that the Puritans
make dignified, and the Eugenists somewhat amusing, statues.</p>
<p>But there is one feature in the past which more than all the rest defies
and depresses the moderns and drives them towards this featureless future.
I mean the presence in the past of huge ideals, unfulfilled and sometimes
abandoned. The sight of these splendid failures is melancholy to a
restless and rather morbid generation; and they maintain a strange silence
about them—sometimes amounting to an unscrupulous silence. They keep
them entirely out of their newspapers and almost entirely out of their
history books. For example, they will often tell you (in their praises of
the coming age) that we are moving on towards a United States of Europe.
But they carefully omit to tell you that we are moving away from a United
States of Europe, that such a thing existed literally in Roman and
essentially in mediaeval times. They never admit that the international
hatreds (which they call barbaric) are really very recent, the mere
breakdown of the ideal of the Holy Roman Empire. Or again, they will tell
you that there is going to be a social revolution, a great rising of the
poor against the rich; but they never rub it in that France made that
magnificent attempt, unaided, and that we and all the world allowed it to
be trampled out and forgotten. I say decisively that nothing is so marked
in modern writing as the prediction of such ideals in the future combined
with the ignoring of them in the past. Anyone can test this for himself.
Read any thirty or forty pages of pamphlets advocating peace in Europe and
see how many of them praise the old Popes or Emperors for keeping the
peace in Europe. Read any armful of essays and poems in praise of social
democracy, and see how many of them praise the old Jacobins who created
democracy and died for it. These colossal ruins are to the modern only
enormous eyesores. He looks back along the valley of the past and sees a
perspective of splendid but unfinished cities. They are unfinished, not
always through enmity or accident, but often through fickleness, mental
fatigue, and the lust for alien philosophies. We have not only left undone
those things that we ought to have done, but we have even left undone
those things that we wanted to do</p>
<p>It is very currently suggested that the modern man is the heir of all the
ages, that he has got the good out of these successive human experiments.
I know not what to say in answer to this, except to ask the reader to look
at the modern man, as I have just looked at the modern man—in the
looking-glass. Is it really true that you and I are two starry towers
built up of all the most towering visions of the past? Have we really
fulfilled all the great historic ideals one after the other, from our
naked ancestor who was brave enough to kill a mammoth with a stone knife,
through the Greek citizen and the Christian saint to our own grandfather
or great-grandfather, who may have been sabred by the Manchester Yeomanry
or shot in the ‘48? Are we still strong enough to spear mammoths, but now
tender enough to spare them? Does the cosmos contain any mammoth that we
have either speared or spared? When we decline (in a marked manner) to fly
the red flag and fire across a barricade like our grandfathers, are we
really declining in deference to sociologists—or to soldiers? Have
we indeed outstripped the warrior and passed the ascetical saint? I fear
we only outstrip the warrior in the sense that we should probably run away
from him. And if we have passed the saint, I fear we have passed him
without bowing.</p>
<p>This is, first and foremost, what I mean by the narrowness of the new
ideas, the limiting effect of the future. Our modern prophetic idealism is
narrow because it has undergone a persistent process of elimination. We
must ask for new things because we are not allowed to ask for old things.
The whole position is based on this idea that we have got all the good
that can be got out of the ideas of the past. But we have not got all the
good out of them, perhaps at this moment not any of the good out of them.
And the need here is a need of complete freedom for restoration as well as
revolution.</p>
<p>We often read nowadays of the valor or audacity with which some rebel
attacks a hoary tyranny or an antiquated superstition. There is not really
any courage at all in attacking hoary or antiquated things, any more than
in offering to fight one’s grandmother. The really courageous man is he
who defies tyrannies young as the morning and superstitions fresh as the
first flowers. The only true free-thinker is he whose intellect is as much
free from the future as from the past. He cares as little for what will be
as for what has been; he cares only for what ought to be. And for my
present purpose I specially insist on this abstract independence. If I am
to discuss what is wrong, one of the first things that are wrong is this:
the deep and silent modern assumption that past things have become
impossible. There is one metaphor of which the moderns are very fond; they
are always saying, “You can’t put the clock back.” The simple and obvious
answer is “You can.” A clock, being a piece of human construction, can be
restored by the human finger to any figure or hour. In the same way
society, being a piece of human construction, can be reconstructed upon
any plan that has ever existed.</p>
<p>There is another proverb, “As you have made your bed, so you must lie on
it”; which again is simply a lie. If I have made my bed uncomfortable,
please God I will make it again. We could restore the Heptarchy or the
stage coaches if we chose. It might take some time to do, and it might be
very inadvisable to do it; but certainly it is not impossible as bringing
back last Friday is impossible. This is, as I say, the first freedom that
I claim: the freedom to restore. I claim a right to propose as a solution
the old patriarchal system of a Highland clan, if that should seem to
eliminate the largest number of evils. It certainly would eliminate some
evils; for instance, the unnatural sense of obeying cold and harsh
strangers, mere bureaucrats and policemen. I claim the right to propose
the complete independence of the small Greek or Italian towns, a sovereign
city of Brixton or Brompton, if that seems the best way out of our
troubles. It would be a way out of some of our troubles; we could not have
in a small state, for instance, those enormous illusions about men or
measures which are nourished by the great national or international
newspapers. You could not persuade a city state that Mr. Beit was an
Englishman, or Mr. Dillon a desperado, any more than you could persuade a
Hampshire Village that the village drunkard was a teetotaller or the
village idiot a statesman. Nevertheless, I do not as a fact propose that
the Browns and the Smiths should be collected under separate tartans. Nor
do I even propose that Clapham should declare its independence. I merely
declare my independence. I merely claim my choice of all the tools in the
universe; and I shall not admit that any of them are blunted merely
because they have been used.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0006" id="link2H_4_0006"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> V. THE UNFINISHED TEMPLE </h2>
<p>The task of modern idealists indeed is made much too easy for them by the
fact that they are always taught that if a thing has been defeated it has
been disproved. Logically, the case is quite clearly the other way. The
lost causes are exactly those which might have saved the world. If a man
says that the Young Pretender would have made England happy, it is hard to
answer him. If anyone says that the Georges made England happy, I hope we
all know what to answer. That which was prevented is always impregnable;
and the only perfect King of England was he who was smothered. Exactly be
cause Jacobitism failed we cannot call it a failure. Precisely because the
Commune collapsed as a rebellion we cannot say that it collapsed as a
system. But such outbursts were brief or incidental. Few people realize
how many of the largest efforts, the facts that will fill history, were
frustrated in their full design and come down to us as gigantic cripples.
I have only space to allude to the two largest facts of modern history:
the Catholic Church and that modern growth rooted in the French
Revolution.</p>
<p>When four knights scattered the blood and brains of St. Thomas of
Canterbury, it was not only a sign of anger but of a sort of black
admiration. They wished for his blood, but they wished even more for his
brains. Such a blow will remain forever unintelligible unless we realise
what the brains of St. Thomas were thinking about just before they were
distributed over the floor. They were thinking about the great mediaeval
conception that the church is the judge of the world. Becket objected to a
priest being tried even by the Lord Chief Justice. And his reason was
simple: because the Lord Chief Justice was being tried by the priest. The
judiciary was itself sub judice. The kings were themselves in the dock.
The idea was to create an invisible kingdom, without armies or prisons,
but with complete freedom to condemn publicly all the kingdoms of the
earth. Whether such a supreme church would have cured society we cannot
affirm definitely; because the church never was a supreme church. We only
know that in England at any rate the princes conquered the saints. What
the world wanted we see before us; and some of us call it a failure. But
we cannot call what the church wanted a failure, simply because the church
failed. Tracy struck a little too soon. England had not yet made the great
Protestant discovery that the king can do no wrong. The king was whipped
in the cathedral; a performance which I recommend to those who regret the
unpopularity of church-going. But the discovery was made; and Henry VIII
scattered Becket’s bones as easily as Tracy had scattered his brains.</p>
<p>Of course, I mean that Catholicism was not tried; plenty of Catholics were
tried, and found guilty. My point is that the world did not tire of the
church’s ideal, but of its reality. Monasteries were impugned not for the
chastity of monks, but for the unchastity of monks. Christianity was
unpopular not because of the humility, but of the arrogance of Christians.
Certainly, if the church failed it was largely through the churchmen. But
at the same time hostile elements had certainly begun to end it long
before it could have done its work. In the nature of things it needed a
common scheme of life and thought in Europe. Yet the mediaeval system
began to be broken to pieces intellectually, long before it showed the
slightest hint of falling to pieces morally. The huge early heresies, like
the Albigenses, had not the faintest excuse in moral superiority. And it
is actually true that the Reformation began to tear Europe apart before
the Catholic Church had had time to pull it together. The Prussians, for
instance, were not converted to Christianity at all until quite close to
the Reformation. The poor creatures hardly had time to become Catholics
before they were told to become Protestants. This explains a great deal of
their subsequent conduct. But I have only taken this as the first and most
evident case of the general truth: that the great ideals of the past
failed not by being outlived (which must mean over-lived), but by not
being lived enough. Mankind has not passed through the Middle Ages. Rather
mankind has retreated from the Middle Ages in reaction and rout. The
Christian ideal has not been tried and found wanting. It has been found
difficult; and left untried.</p>
<p>It is, of course, the same in the case of the French Revolution. A great
part of our present perplexity arises from the fact that the French
Revolution has half succeeded and half failed. In one sense, Valmy was the
decisive battle of the West, and in another Trafalgar. We have, indeed,
destroyed the largest territorial tyrannies, and created a free peasantry
in almost all Christian countries except England; of which we shall say
more anon. But representative government, the one universal relic, is a
very poor fragment of the full republican idea. The theory of the French
Revolution presupposed two things in government, things which it achieved
at the time, but which it has certainly not bequeathed to its imitators in
England, Germany, and America. The first of these was the idea of
honorable poverty; that a statesman must be something of a stoic; the
second was the idea of extreme publicity. Many imaginative English
writers, including Carlyle, seem quite unable to imagine how it was that
men like Robespierre and Marat were ardently admired. The best answer is
that they were admired for being poor—poor when they might have been
rich.</p>
<p>No one will pretend that this ideal exists at all in the haute politique
of this country. Our national claim to political incorruptibility is
actually based on exactly the opposite argument; it is based on the theory
that wealthy men in assured positions will have no temptation to financial
trickery. Whether the history of the English aristocracy, from the
spoliation of the monasteries to the annexation of the mines, entirely
supports this theory I am not now inquiring; but certainly it is our
theory, that wealth will be a protection against political corruption. The
English statesman is bribed not to be bribed. He is born with a silver
spoon in his mouth, so that he may never afterwards be found with the
silver spoons in his pocket. So strong is our faith in this protection by
plutocracy, that we are more and more trusting our empire in the hands of
families which inherit wealth without either blood or manners. Some of our
political houses are parvenue by pedigree; they hand on vulgarity like a
coat of-arms. In the case of many a modern statesman to say that he is
born with a silver spoon in his mouth, is at once inadequate and
excessive. He is born with a silver knife in his mouth. But all this only
illustrates the English theory that poverty is perilous for a politician.</p>
<p>It will be the same if we compare the conditions that have come about with
the Revolution legend touching publicity. The old democratic doctrine was
that the more light that was let in to all departments of State, the
easier it was for a righteous indignation to move promptly against wrong.
In other words, monarchs were to live in glass houses, that mobs might
throw stones. Again, no admirer of existing English politics (if there is
any admirer of existing English politics) will really pretend that this
ideal of publicity is exhausted, or even attempted. Obviously public life
grows more private every day. The French have, indeed, continued the
tradition of revealing secrets and making scandals; hence they are more
flagrant and palpable than we, not in sin but in the confession of sin.
The first trial of Dreyfus might have happened in England; it is exactly
the second trial that would have been legally impossible. But, indeed, if
we wish to realise how far we fall short of the original republican
outline, the sharpest way to test it is to note how far we fall short even
of the republican element in the older regime. Not only are we less
democratic than Danton and Condorcet, but we are in many ways less
democratic than Choiseul and Marie Antoinette. The richest nobles before
the revolt were needy middle-class people compared with our Rothschilds
and Roseberys. And in the matter of publicity the old French monarchy was
infinitely more democratic than any of the monarchies of today.
Practically anybody who chose could walk into the palace and see the king
playing with his children, or paring his nails. The people possessed the
monarch, as the people possess Primrose Hill; that is, they cannot move
it, but they can sprawl all over it. The old French monarchy was founded
on the excellent principle that a cat may look at a king. But nowadays a
cat may not look at a king; unless it is a very tame cat. Even where the
press is free for criticism it is only used for adulation. The substantial
difference comes to something uncommonly like this: Eighteenth century
tyranny meant that you could say “The K__ of Br__rd is a profligate.”
Twentieth century liberty really means that you are allowed to say “The
King of Brentford is a model family man.”</p>
<p>But we have delayed the main argument too long for the parenthetical
purpose of showing that the great democratic dream, like the great
mediaeval dream, has in a strict and practical sense been a dream
unfulfilled. Whatever is the matter with modern England it is not that we
have carried out too literally, or achieved with disappointing
completeness, either the Catholicism of Becket or the equality of Marat.
Now I have taken these two cases merely because they are typical of ten
thousand other cases; the world is full of these unfulfilled ideas, these
uncompleted temples. History does not consist of completed and crumbling
ruins; rather it consists of half-built villas abandoned by a
bankrupt-builder. This world is more like an unfinished suburb than a
deserted cemetery.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0007" id="link2H_4_0007"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> VI. THE ENEMIES OF PROPERTY </h2>
<p>But it is for this especial reason that such an explanation is necessary
on the very threshold of the definition of ideals. For owing to that
historic fallacy with which I have just dealt, numbers of readers will
expect me, when I propound an ideal, to propound a new ideal. Now I have
no notion at all of propounding a new ideal. There is no new ideal
imaginable by the madness of modern sophists, which will be anything like
so startling as fulfilling any one of the old ones. On the day that any
copybook maxim is carried out there will be something like an earthquake
on the earth. There is only one thing new that can be done under the sun;
and that is to look at the sun. If you attempt it on a blue day in June,
you will know why men do not look straight at their ideals. There is only
one really startling thing to be done with the ideal, and that is to do
it. It is to face the flaming logical fact, and its frightful
consequences. Christ knew that it would be a more stunning thunderbolt to
fulfil the law than to destroy it. It is true of both the cases I have
quoted, and of every case. The pagans had always adored purity: Athena,
Artemis, Vesta. It was when the virgin martyrs began defiantly to practice
purity that they rent them with wild beasts, and rolled them on red-hot
coals. The world had always loved the notion of the poor man uppermost; it
can be proved by every legend from Cinderella to Whittington, by every
poem from the Magnificat to the Marseillaise. The kings went mad against
France not because she idealized this ideal, but because she realized it.
Joseph of Austria and Catherine of Russia quite agreed that the people
should rule; what horrified them was that the people did. The French
Revolution, therefore, is the type of all true revolutions, because its
ideal is as old as the Old Adam, but its fulfilment almost as fresh, as
miraculous, and as new as the New Jerusalem.</p>
<p>But in the modern world we are primarily confronted with the extraordinary
spectacle of people turning to new ideals because they have not tried the
old. Men have not got tired of Christianity; they have never found enough
Christianity to get tired of. Men have never wearied of political justice;
they have wearied of waiting for it.</p>
<p>Now, for the purpose of this book, I propose to take only one of these old
ideals; but one that is perhaps the oldest. I take the principle of
domesticity: the ideal house; the happy family, the holy family of
history. For the moment it is only necessary to remark that it is like the
church and like the republic, now chiefly assailed by those who have never
known it, or by those who have failed to fulfil it. Numberless modern
women have rebelled against domesticity in theory because they have never
known it in practice. Hosts of the poor are driven to the workhouse
without ever having known the house. Generally speaking, the cultured
class is shrieking to be let out of the decent home, just as the working
class is shouting to be let into it.</p>
<p>Now if we take this house or home as a test, we may very generally lay the
simple spiritual foundations of the idea. God is that which can make
something out of nothing. Man (it may truly be said) is that which can
make something out of anything. In other words, while the joy of God be
unlimited creation, the special joy of man is limited creation, the
combination of creation with limits. Man’s pleasure, therefore, is to
possess conditions, but also to be partly possessed by them; to be
half-controlled by the flute he plays or by the field he digs. The
excitement is to get the utmost out of given conditions; the conditions
will stretch, but not indefinitely. A man can write an immortal sonnet on
an old envelope, or hack a hero out of a lump of rock. But hacking a
sonnet out of a rock would be a laborious business, and making a hero out
of an envelope is almost out of the sphere of practical politics. This
fruitful strife with limitations, when it concerns some airy entertainment
of an educated class, goes by the name of Art. But the mass of men have
neither time nor aptitude for the invention of invisible or abstract
beauty. For the mass of men the idea of artistic creation can only be
expressed by an idea unpopular in present discussions—the idea of
property. The average man cannot cut clay into the shape of a man; but he
can cut earth into the shape of a garden; and though he arranges it with
red geraniums and blue potatoes in alternate straight lines, he is still
an artist; because he has chosen. The average man cannot paint the sunset
whose colors be admires; but he can paint his own house with what color he
chooses, and though he paints it pea green with pink spots, he is still an
artist; because that is his choice. Property is merely the art of the
democracy. It means that every man should have something that he can shape
in his own image, as he is shaped in the image of heaven. But because he
is not God, but only a graven image of God, his self-expression must deal
with limits; properly with limits that are strict and even small.</p>
<p>I am well aware that the word “property” has been defied in our time by
the corruption of the great capitalists. One would think, to hear people
talk, that the Rothchilds and the Rockefellers were on the side of
property. But obviously they are the enemies of property; because they are
enemies of their own limitations. They do not want their own land; but
other people’s. When they remove their neighbor’s landmark, they also
remove their own. A man who loves a little triangular field ought to love
it because it is triangular; anyone who destroys the shape, by giving him
more land, is a thief who has stolen a triangle. A man with the true
poetry of possession wishes to see the wall where his garden meets Smith’s
garden; the hedge where his farm touches Brown’s. He cannot see the shape
of his own land unless he sees the edges of his neighbor’s. It is the
negation of property that the Duke of Sutherland should have all the farms
in one estate; just as it would be the negation of marriage if he had all
our wives in one harem.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0008" id="link2H_4_0008"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> VII. THE FREE FAMILY </h2>
<p>As I have said, I propose to take only one central instance; I will take
the institution called the private house or home; the shell and organ of
the family. We will consider cosmic and political tendencies simply as
they strike that ancient and unique roof. Very few words will suffice for
all I have to say about the family itself. I leave alone the speculations
about its animal origin and the details of its social reconstruction; I am
concerned only with its palpable omnipresence. It is a necessity far
mankind; it is (if you like to put it so) a trap for mankind. Only by the
hypocritical ignoring of a huge fact can any one contrive to talk of “free
love”; as if love were an episode like lighting a cigarette, or whistling
a tune. Suppose whenever a man lit a cigarette, a towering genie arose
from the rings of smoke and followed him everywhere as a huge slave.
Suppose whenever a man whistled a tune he “drew an angel down” and had to
walk about forever with a seraph on a string. These catastrophic images
are but faint parallels to the earthquake consequences that Nature has
attached to sex; and it is perfectly plain at the beginning that a man
cannot be a free lover; he is either a traitor or a tied man. The second
element that creates the family is that its consequences, though colossal,
are gradual; the cigarette produces a baby giant, the song only an infant
seraph. Thence arises the necessity for some prolonged system of
co-operation; and thence arises the family in its full educational sense.</p>
<p>It may be said that this institution of the home is the one anarchist
institution. That is to say, it is older than law, and stands outside the
State. By its nature it is refreshed or corrupted by indefinable forces of
custom or kinship. This is not to be understood as meaning that the State
has no authority over families; that State authority is invoked and ought
to be invoked in many abnormal cases. But in most normal cases of family
joys and sorrows, the State has no mode of entry. It is not so much that
the law should not interfere, as that the law cannot. Just as there are
fields too far off for law, so there are fields too near; as a man may see
the North Pole before he sees his own backbone. Small and near matters
escape control at least as much as vast and remote ones; and the real
pains and pleasures of the family form a strong instance of this. If a
baby cries for the moon, the policeman cannot procure the moon—but
neither can he stop the baby. Creatures so close to each other as husband
and wife, or a mother and children, have powers of making each other happy
or miserable with which no public coercion can deal. If a marriage could
be dissolved every morning it would not give back his night’s rest to a
man kept awake by a curtain lecture; and what is the good of giving a man
a lot of power where he only wants a little peace? The child must depend
on the most imperfect mother; the mother may be devoted to the most
unworthy children; in such relations legal revenges are vain. Even in the
abnormal cases where the law may operate, this difficulty is constantly
found; as many a bewildered magistrate knows. He has to save children from
starvation by taking away their breadwinner. And he often has to break a
wife’s heart because her husband has already broken her head. The State
has no tool delicate enough to deracinate the rooted habits and tangled
affections of the family; the two sexes, whether happy or unhappy, are
glued together too tightly for us to get the blade of a legal penknife in
between them. The man and the woman are one flesh—yes, even when
they are not one spirit. Man is a quadruped. Upon this ancient and
anarchic intimacy, types of government have little or no effect; it is
happy or unhappy, by its own sexual wholesomeness and genial habit, under
the republic of Switzerland or the despotism of Siam. Even a republic in
Siam would not have done much towards freeing the Siamese Twins.</p>
<p>The problem is not in marriage, but in sex; and would be felt under the
freest concubinage. Nevertheless, the overwhelming mass of mankind has not
believed in freedom in this matter, but rather in a more or less lasting
tie. Tribes and civilizations differ about the occasions on which we may
loosen the bond, but they all agree that there is a bond to be loosened,
not a mere universal detachment. For the purposes of this book I am not
concerned to discuss that mystical view of marriage in which I myself
believe: the great European tradition which has made marriage a sacrament.
It is enough to say here that heathen and Christian alike have regarded
marriage as a tie; a thing not normally to be sundered. Briefly, this
human belief in a sexual bond rests on a principle of which the modern
mind has made a very inadequate study. It is, perhaps, most nearly
paralleled by the principle of the second wind in walking.</p>
<p>The principle is this: that in everything worth having, even in every
pleasure, there is a point of pain or tedium that must be survived, so
that the pleasure may revive and endure. The joy of battle comes after the
first fear of death; the joy of reading Virgil comes after the bore of
learning him; the glow of the sea-bather comes after the icy shock of the
sea bath; and the success of the marriage comes after the failure of the
honeymoon. All human vows, laws, and contracts are so many ways of
surviving with success this breaking point, this instant of potential
surrender.</p>
<p>In everything on this earth that is worth doing, there is a stage when no
one would do it, except for necessity or honor. It is then that the
Institution upholds a man and helps him on to the firmer ground ahead.
Whether this solid fact of human nature is sufficient to justify the
sublime dedication of Christian marriage is quite an other matter, it is
amply sufficient to justify the general human feeling of marriage as a
fixed thing, dissolution of which is a fault or, at least, an ignominy.
The essential element is not so much duration as security. Two people must
be tied together in order to do themselves justice; for twenty minutes at
a dance, or for twenty years in a marriage In both cases the point is,
that if a man is bored in the first five minutes he must go on and force
himself to be happy. Coercion is a kind of encouragement; and anarchy (or
what some call liberty) is essentially oppressive, because it is
essentially discouraging. If we all floated in the air like bubbles, free
to drift anywhere at any instant, the practical result would be that no
one would have the courage to begin a conversation. It would be so
embarrassing to start a sentence in a friendly whisper, and then have to
shout the last half of it because the other party was floating away into
the free and formless ether. The two must hold each other to do justice to
each other. If Americans can be divorced for “incompatibility of temper” I
cannot conceive why they are not all divorced. I have known many happy
marriages, but never a compatible one. The whole aim of marriage is to
fight through and survive the instant when incompatibility becomes
unquestionable. For a man and a woman, as such, are incompatible.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0009" id="link2H_4_0009"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> VIII. THE WILDNESS OF DOMESTICITY </h2>
<p>In the course of this crude study we shall have to touch on what is called
the problem of poverty, especially the dehumanized poverty of modern
industrialism. But in this primary matter of the ideal the difficulty is
not the problem of poverty, but the problem of wealth. It is the special
psychology of leisure and luxury that falsifies life. Some experience of
modern movements of the sort called “advanced” has led me to the
conviction that they generally repose upon some experience peculiar to the
rich. It is so with that fallacy of free love of which I have already
spoken; the idea of sexuality as a string of episodes. That implies a long
holiday in which to get tired of one woman, and a motor car in which to
wander looking for others; it also implies money for maintenances. An
omnibus conductor has hardly time to love his own wife, let alone other
people’s. And the success with which nuptial estrangements are depicted in
modern “problem plays” is due to the fact that there is only one thing
that a drama cannot depict—that is a hard day’s work. I could give
many other instances of this plutocratic assumption behind progressive
fads. For instance, there is a plutocratic assumption behind the phrase
“Why should woman be economically dependent upon man?” The answer is that
among poor and practical people she isn’t; except in the sense in which he
is dependent upon her. A hunter has to tear his clothes; there must be
somebody to mend them. A fisher has to catch fish; there must be somebody
to cook them. It is surely quite clear that this modern notion that woman
is a mere “pretty clinging parasite,” “a plaything,” etc., arose through
the somber contemplation of some rich banking family, in which the banker,
at least, went to the city and pretended to do something, while the
banker’s wife went to the Park and did not pretend to do anything at all.
A poor man and his wife are a business partnership. If one partner in a
firm of publishers interviews the authors while the other interviews the
clerks, is one of them economically dependent? Was Hodder a pretty
parasite clinging to Stoughton? Was Marshall a mere plaything for
Snelgrove?</p>
<p>But of all the modern notions generated by mere wealth the worst is this:
the notion that domesticity is dull and tame. Inside the home (they say)
is dead decorum and routine; outside is adventure and variety. This is
indeed a rich man’s opinion. The rich man knows that his own house moves
on vast and soundless wheels of wealth, is run by regiments of servants,
by a swift and silent ritual. On the other hand, every sort of vagabondage
of romance is open to him in the streets outside. He has plenty of money
and can afford to be a tramp. His wildest adventure will end in a
restaurant, while the yokel’s tamest adventure may end in a police-court.
If he smashes a window he can pay for it; if he smashes a man he can
pension him. He can (like the millionaire in the story) buy an hotel to
get a glass of gin. And because he, the luxurious man, dictates the tone
of nearly all “advanced” and “progressive” thought, we have almost
forgotten what a home really means to the overwhelming millions of
mankind.</p>
<p>For the truth is, that to the moderately poor the home is the only place
of liberty. Nay, it is the only place of anarchy. It is the only spot on
the earth where a man can alter arrangements suddenly, make an experiment
or indulge in a whim. Everywhere else he goes he must accept the strict
rules of the shop, inn, club, or museum that he happens to enter. He can
eat his meals on the floor in his own house if he likes. I often do it
myself; it gives a curious, childish, poetic, picnic feeling. There would
be considerable trouble if I tried to do it in an A.B.C. tea-shop. A man
can wear a dressing gown and slippers in his house; while I am sure that
this would not be permitted at the Savoy, though I never actually tested
the point. If you go to a restaurant you must drink some of the wines on
the wine list, all of them if you insist, but certainly some of them. But
if you have a house and garden you can try to make hollyhock tea or
convolvulus wine if you like. For a plain, hard-working man the home is
not the one tame place in the world of adventure. It is the one wild place
in the world of rules and set tasks. The home is the one place where he
can put the carpet on the ceiling or the slates on the floor if he wants
to. When a man spends every night staggering from bar to bar or from
music-hall to music-hall, we say that he is living an irregular life. But
he is not; he is living a highly regular life, under the dull, and often
oppressive, laws of such places. Some times he is not allowed even to sit
down in the bars; and frequently he is not allowed to sing in the
music-halls. Hotels may be defined as places where you are forced to
dress; and theaters may be defined as places where you are forbidden to
smoke. A man can only picnic at home.</p>
<p>Now I take, as I have said, this small human omnipotence, this possession
of a definite cell or chamber of liberty, as the working model for the
present inquiry. Whether we can give every English man a free home of his
own or not, at least we should desire it; and he desires it. For the
moment we speak of what he wants, not of what he expects to get. He wants,
for instance, a separate house; he does not want a semi-detached house. He
may be forced in the commercial race to share one wall with another man.
Similarly he might be forced in a three-legged race to share one leg with
another man; but it is not so that he pictures himself in his dreams of
elegance and liberty. Again, he does not desire a flat. He can eat and
sleep and praise God in a flat; he can eat and sleep and praise God in a
railway train. But a railway train is not a house, because it is a house
on wheels. And a flat is not a house, because it is a house on stilts. An
idea of earthy contact and foundation, as well as an idea of separation
and independence, is a part of this instructive human picture.</p>
<p>I take, then, this one institution as a test. As every normal man desires
a woman, and children born of a woman, every normal man desires a house of
his own to put them into. He does not merely want a roof above him and a
chair below him; he wants an objective and visible kingdom; a fire at
which he can cook what food he likes, a door he can open to what friends
he chooses. This is the normal appetite of men; I do not say there are not
exceptions. There may be saints above the need and philanthropists below
it. Opalstein, now he is a duke, may have got used to more than this; and
when he was a convict may have got used to less. But the normality of the
thing is enormous. To give nearly everybody ordinary houses would please
nearly everybody; that is what I assert without apology. Now in modern
England (as you eagerly point out) it is very difficult to give nearly
everybody houses. Quite so; I merely set up the desideratum; and ask the
reader to leave it standing there while he turns with me to a
consideration of what really happens in the social wars of our time.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0010" id="link2H_4_0010"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> IX. HISTORY OF HUDGE AND GUDGE </h2>
<p>There is, let us say, a certain filthy rookery in Hoxton, dripping with
disease and honeycombed with crime and promiscuity. There are, let us say,
two noble and courageous young men, of pure intentions and (if you prefer
it) noble birth; let us call them Hudge and Gudge. Hudge, let us say, is
of a bustling sort; he points out that the people must at all costs be got
out of this den; he subscribes and collects money, but he finds (despite
the large financial interests of the Hudges) that the thing will have to
be done on the cheap if it is to be done on the spot. He therefore, runs
up a row of tall bare tenements like beehives; and soon has all the poor
people bundled into their little brick cells, which are certainly better
than their old quarters, in so far as they are weather proof, well
ventilated and supplied with clean water. But Gudge has a more delicate
nature. He feels a nameless something lacking in the little brick boxes;
he raises numberless objections; he even assails the celebrated Hudge
Report, with the Gudge Minority Report; and by the end of a year or so has
come to telling Hudge heatedly that the people were much happier where
they were before. As the people preserve in both places precisely the same
air of dazed amiability, it is very difficult to find out which is right.
But at least one might safely say that no people ever liked stench or
starvation as such, but only some peculiar pleasures en tangled with them.
Not so feels the sensitive Gudge. Long before the final quarrel (Hudge v.
Gudge and Another), Gudge has succeeded in persuading himself that slums
and stinks are really very nice things; that the habit of sleeping
fourteen in a room is what has made our England great; and that the smell
of open drains is absolutely essential to the rearing of a viking breed.</p>
<p>But, meanwhile, has there been no degeneration in Hudge? Alas, I fear
there has. Those maniacally ugly buildings which he originally put up as
unpretentious sheds barely to shelter human life, grow every day more and
more lovely to his deluded eye. Things he would never have dreamed of
defending, except as crude necessities, things like common kitchens or
infamous asbestos stoves, begin to shine quite sacredly before him, merely
because they reflect the wrath of Gudge. He maintains, with the aid of
eager little books by Socialists, that man is really happier in a hive
than in a house. The practical difficulty of keeping total strangers out
of your bedroom he describes as Brotherhood; and the necessity for
climbing twenty-three flights of cold stone stairs, I dare say he calls
Effort. The net result of their philanthropic adventure is this: that one
has come to defending indefensible slums and still more indefensible
slum-landlords, while the other has come to treating as divine the sheds
and pipes which he only meant as desperate. Gudge is now a corrupt and
apoplectic old Tory in the Carlton Club; if you mention poverty to him he
roars at you in a thick, hoarse voice something that is conjectured to be
“Do ‘em good!” Nor is Hudge more happy; for he is a lean vegetarian with a
gray, pointed beard and an unnaturally easy smile, who goes about telling
everybody that at last we shall all sleep in one universal bedroom; and he
lives in a Garden City, like one forgotten of God.</p>
<p>Such is the lamentable history of Hudge and Gudge; which I merely
introduce as a type of an endless and exasperating misunderstanding which
is always occurring in modern England. To get men out of a rookery men are
put into a tenement; and at the beginning the healthy human soul loathes
them both. A man’s first desire is to get away as far as possible from the
rookery, even should his mad course lead him to a model dwelling. The
second desire is, naturally, to get away from the model dwelling, even if
it should lead a man back to the rookery. But I am neither a Hudgian nor a
Gudgian; and I think the mistakes of these two famous and fascinating
persons arose from one simple fact. They arose from the fact that neither
Hudge nor Gudge had ever thought for an instant what sort of house a man
might probably like for himself. In short, they did not begin with the
ideal; and, therefore, were not practical politicians.</p>
<p>We may now return to the purpose of our awkward parenthesis about the
praise of the future and the failures of the past. A house of his own
being the obvious ideal for every man, we may now ask (taking this need as
typical of all such needs) why he hasn’t got it; and whether it is in any
philosophical sense his own fault. Now, I think that in some philosophical
sense it is his own fault, I think in a yet more philosophical sense it is
the fault of his philosophy. And this is what I have now to attempt to
explain.</p>
<p>Burke, a fine rhetorician, who rarely faced realities, said, I think, that
an Englishman’s house is his castle. This is honestly entertaining; for as
it happens the Englishman is almost the only man in Europe whose house is
not his castle. Nearly everywhere else exists the assumption of peasant
proprietorship; that a poor man may be a landlord, though he is only lord
of his own land. Making the landlord and the tenant the same person has
certain trivial advantages, as that the tenant pays no rent, while the
landlord does a little work. But I am not concerned with the defense of
small proprietorship, but merely with the fact that it exists almost
everywhere except in England. It is also true, however, that this estate
of small possession is attacked everywhere today; it has never existed
among ourselves, and it may be destroyed among our neighbors. We have,
therefore, to ask ourselves what it is in human affairs generally, and in
this domestic ideal in particular, that has really ruined the natural
human creation, especially in this country.</p>
<p>Man has always lost his way. He has been a tramp ever since Eden; but he
always knew, or thought he knew, what he was looking for. Every man has a
house somewhere in the elaborate cosmos; his house waits for him waist
deep in slow Norfolk rivers or sunning itself upon Sussex downs. Man has
always been looking for that home which is the subject matter of this
book. But in the bleak and blinding hail of skepticism to which he has
been now so long subjected, he has begun for the first time to be chilled,
not merely in his hopes, but in his desires. For the first time in history
he begins really to doubt the object of his wanderings on the earth. He
has always lost his way; but now he has lost his address.</p>
<p>Under the pressure of certain upper-class philosophies (or in other words,
under the pressure of Hudge and Gudge) the average man has really become
bewildered about the goal of his efforts; and his efforts, therefore, grow
feebler and feebler. His simple notion of having a home of his own is
derided as bourgeois, as sentimental, or as despicably Christian. Under
various verbal forms he is recommended to go on to the streets—which
is called Individualism; or to the work-house—which is called
Collectivism. We shall consider this process somewhat more carefully in a
moment. But it may be said here that Hudge and Gudge, or the governing
class generally, will never fail for lack of some modern phrase to cover
their ancient predominance. The great lords will refuse the English
peasant his three acres and a cow on advanced grounds, if they cannot
refuse it longer on reactionary grounds. They will deny him the three
acres on grounds of State Ownership. They will forbid him the cow on
grounds of humanitarianism.</p>
<p>And this brings us to the ultimate analysis of this singular influence
that has prevented doctrinal demands by the English people. There are, I
believe, some who still deny that England is governed by an oligarchy. It
is quite enough for me to know that a man might have gone to sleep some
thirty years ago over the day’s newspaper and woke up last week over the
later newspaper, and fancied he was reading about the same people. In one
paper he would have found a Lord Robert Cecil, a Mr. Gladstone, a Mr.
Lyttleton, a Churchill, a Chamberlain, a Trevelyan, an Acland. In the
other paper he would find a Lord Robert Cecil, a Mr. Gladstone, a Mr.
Lyttleton, a Churchill, a Chamberlain, a Trevelyan, an Acland. If this is
not being governed by families I cannot imagine what it is. I suppose it
is being governed by extraordinary democratic coincidences.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0011" id="link2H_4_0011"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> X. OPPRESSION BY OPTIMISM </h2>
<p>But we are not here concerned with the nature and existence of the
aristocracy, but with the origin of its peculiar power, why is it the last
of the true oligarchies of Europe; and why does there seem no very
immediate prospect of our seeing the end of it? The explanation is simple
though it remains strangely unnoticed. The friends of aristocracy often
praise it for preserving ancient and gracious traditions. The enemies of
aristocracy often blame it for clinging to cruel or antiquated customs.
Both its enemies and its friends are wrong. Generally speaking the
aristocracy does not preserve either good or bad traditions; it does not
preserve anything except game. Who would dream of looking among
aristocrats anywhere for an old custom? One might as well look for an old
costume! The god of the aristocrats is not tradition, but fashion, which
is the opposite of tradition. If you wanted to find an old-world Norwegian
head-dress, would you look for it in the Scandinavian Smart Set? No; the
aristocrats never have customs; at the best they have habits, like the
animals. Only the mob has customs.</p>
<p>The real power of the English aristocrats has lain in exactly the opposite
of tradition. The simple key to the power of our upper classes is this:
that they have always kept carefully on the side of what is called
Progress. They have always been up to date, and this comes quite easy to
an aristocracy. For the aristocracy are the supreme instances of that
frame of mind of which we spoke just now. Novelty is to them a luxury
verging on a necessity. They, above all, are so bored with the past and
with the present, that they gape, with a horrible hunger, for the future.</p>
<p>But whatever else the great lords forgot they never forgot that it was
their business to stand for the new things, for whatever was being most
talked about among university dons or fussy financiers. Thus they were on
the side of the Reformation against the Church, of the Whigs against the
Stuarts, of the Baconian science against the old philosophy, of the
manufacturing system against the operatives, and (to-day) of the increased
power of the State against the old-fashioned individualists. In short, the
rich are always modern; it is their business. But the immediate effect of
this fact upon the question we are studying is somewhat singular.</p>
<p>In each of the separate holes or quandaries in which the ordinary
Englishman has been placed, he has been told that his situation is, for
some particular reason, all for the best. He woke up one fine morning and
discovered that the public things, which for eight hundred years he had
used at once as inns and sanctuaries, had all been suddenly and savagely
abolished, to increase the private wealth of about six or seven men. One
would think he might have been annoyed at that; in many places he was, and
was put down by the soldiery. But it was not merely the army that kept him
quiet. He was kept quiet by the sages as well as the soldiers; the six or
seven men who took away the inns of the poor told him that they were not
doing it for themselves, but for the religion of the future, the great
dawn of Protestantism and truth. So whenever a seventeenth century noble
was caught pulling down a peasant’s fence and stealing his field, the
noble pointed excitedly at the face of Charles I or James II (which at
that moment, perhaps, wore a cross expression) and thus diverted the
simple peasant’s attention. The great Puritan lords created the
Commonwealth, and destroyed the common land. They saved their poorer
countrymen from the disgrace of paying Ship Money, by taking from them the
plow money and spade money which they were doubtless too weak to guard. A
fine old English rhyme has immortalized this easy aristocratic habit—</p>
<p>You prosecute the man or woman Who steals the goose from off the common,
But leave the larger felon loose Who steals the common from the goose.</p>
<p>But here, as in the case of the monasteries, we confront the strange
problem of submission. If they stole the common from the goose, one can
only say that he was a great goose to stand it. The truth is that they
reasoned with the goose; they explained to him that all this was needed to
get the Stuart fox over seas. So in the nineteenth century the great
nobles who became mine-owners and railway directors earnestly assured
everybody that they did not do this from preference, but owing to a newly
discovered Economic Law. So the prosperous politicians of our own
generation introduce bills to prevent poor mothers from going about with
their own babies; or they calmly forbid their tenants to drink beer in
public inns. But this insolence is not (as you would suppose) howled at by
everybody as outrageous feudalism. It is gently rebuked as Socialism. For
an aristocracy is always progressive; it is a form of going the pace.
Their parties grow later and later at night; for they are trying to live
to-morrow.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0012" id="link2H_4_0012"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> XI. THE HOMELESSNESS OF JONES </h2>
<p>Thus the Future of which we spoke at the beginning has (in England at
least) always been the ally of tyranny. The ordinary Englishman has been
duped out of his old possessions, such as they were, and always in the
name of progress. The destroyers of the abbeys took away his bread and
gave him a stone, assuring him that it was a precious stone, the white
pebble of the Lord’s elect. They took away his maypole and his original
rural life and promised him instead the Golden Age of Peace and Commerce
inaugurated at the Crystal Palace. And now they are taking away the little
that remains of his dignity as a householder and the head of a family,
promising him instead Utopias which are called (appropriately enough)
“Anticipations” or “News from Nowhere.” We come back, in fact, to the main
feature which has already been mentioned. The past is communal: the future
must be individualist. In the past are all the evils of democracy, variety
and violence and doubt, but the future is pure despotism, for the future
is pure caprice. Yesterday, I know I was a human fool, but to-morrow I can
easily be the Superman.</p>
<p>The modern Englishman, however, is like a man who should be perpetually
kept out, for one reason after another, from the house in which he had
meant his married life to begin. This man (Jones let us call him) has
always desired the divinely ordinary things; he has married for love, he
has chosen or built a small house that fits like a coat; he is ready to be
a great grandfather and a local god. And just as he is moving in,
something goes wrong. Some tyranny, personal or political, suddenly debars
him from the home; and he has to take his meals in the front garden. A
passing philosopher (who is also, by a mere coincidence, the man who
turned him out) pauses, and leaning elegantly on the railings, explains to
him that he is now living that bold life upon the bounty of nature which
will be the life of the sublime future. He finds life in the front garden
more bold than bountiful, and has to move into mean lodgings in the next
spring. The philosopher (who turned him out), happening to call at these
lodgings, with the probable intention of raising the rent, stops to
explain to him that he is now in the real life of mercantile endeavor; the
economic struggle between him and the landlady is the only thing out of
which, in the sublime future, the wealth of nations can come. He is
defeated in the economic struggle, and goes to the workhouse. The
philosopher who turned him out (happening at that very moment to be
inspecting the workhouse) assures him that he is now at last in that
golden republic which is the goal of mankind; he is in an equal,
scientific, Socialistic commonwealth, owned by the State and ruled by
public officers; in fact, the commonwealth of the sublime future.</p>
<p>Nevertheless, there are signs that the irrational Jones still dreams at
night of this old idea of having an ordinary home. He asked for so little,
and he has been offered so much. He has been offered bribes of worlds and
systems; he has been offered Eden and Utopia and the New Jerusalem, and he
only wanted a house; and that has been refused him.</p>
<p>Such an apologue is literally no exaggeration of the facts of English
history. The rich did literally turn the poor out of the old guest house
on to the road, briefly telling them that it was the road of progress.
They did literally force them into factories and the modern wage-slavery,
assuring them all the time that this was the only way to wealth and
civilization. Just as they had dragged the rustic from the convent food
and ale by saying that the streets of heaven were paved with gold, so now
they dragged him from the village food and ale by telling him that the
streets of London were paved with gold. As he entered the gloomy porch of
Puritanism, so he entered the gloomy porch of Industrialism, being told
that each of them was the gate of the future. Hitherto he has only gone
from prison to prison, nay, into darkening prisons, for Calvinism opened
one small window upon heaven. And now he is asked, in the same educated
and authoritative tones, to enter another dark porch, at which he has to
surrender, into unseen hands, his children, his small possessions and all
the habits of his fathers.</p>
<p>Whether this last opening be in truth any more inviting than the old
openings of Puritanism and Industrialism can be discussed later. But there
can be little doubt, I think, that if some form of Collectivism is imposed
upon England it will be imposed, as everything else has been, by an
instructed political class upon a people partly apathetic and partly
hypnotized. The aristocracy will be as ready to “administer” Collectivism
as they were to administer Puritanism or Manchesterism; in some ways such
a centralized political power is necessarily attractive to them. It will
not be so hard as some innocent Socialists seem to suppose to induce the
Honorable Tomnoddy to take over the milk supply as well as the stamp
supply—at an increased salary. Mr. Bernard Shaw has remarked that
rich men are better than poor men on parish councils because they are free
from “financial timidity.” Now, the English ruling class is quite free
from financial timidity. The Duke of Sussex will be quite ready to be
Administrator of Sussex at the same screw. Sir William Harcourt, that
typical aristocrat, put it quite correctly. “We” (that is, the
aristocracy) “are all Socialists now.”</p>
<p>But this is not the essential note on which I desire to end. My main
contention is that, whether necessary or not, both Industrialism and
Collectivism have been accepted as necessities—not as naked ideals
or desires. Nobody liked the Manchester School; it was endured as the only
way of producing wealth. Nobody likes the Marxian school; it is endured as
the only way of preventing poverty. Nobody’s real heart is in the idea of
preventing a free man from owning his own farm, or an old woman from
cultivating her own garden, any more than anybody’s real heart was in the
heartless battle of the machines. The purpose of this chapter is
sufficiently served in indicating that this proposal also is a pis aller,
a desperate second best—like teetotalism. I do not propose to prove
here that Socialism is a poison; it is enough if I maintain that it is a
medicine and not a wine.</p>
<p>The idea of private property universal but private, the idea of families
free but still families, of domesticity democratic but still domestic, of
one man one house—this remains the real vision and magnet of
mankind. The world may accept something more official and general, less
human and intimate. But the world will be like a broken-hearted woman who
makes a humdrum marriage because she may not make a happy one; Socialism
may be the world’s deliverance, but it is not the world’s desire.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_PART2" id="link2H_PART2"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> PART TWO. IMPERIALISM, OR THE MISTAKE ABOUT MAN </h2>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0014" id="link2H_4_0014"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> I. THE CHARM OF JINGOISM </h2>
<p>I have cast about widely to find a title for this section; and I confess
that the word “Imperialism” is a clumsy version of my meaning. But no
other word came nearer; “Militarism” would have been even more misleading,
and “The Superman” makes nonsense of any discussion that he enters.
Perhaps, upon the whole, the word “Caesarism” would have been better; but
I desire a popular word; and Imperialism (as the reader will perceive)
does cover for the most part the men and theories that I mean to discuss.</p>
<p>This small confusion is increased, however, by the fact that I do also
disbelieve in Imperialism in its popular sense, as a mode or theory of the
patriotic sentiment of this country. But popular Imperialism in England
has very little to do with the sort of Caesarean Imperialism I wish to
sketch. I differ from the Colonial idealism of Rhodes’ and Kipling; but I
do not think, as some of its opponents do, that it is an insolent creation
of English harshness and rapacity. Imperialism, I think, is a fiction
created, not by English hardness, but by English softness; nay, in a
sense, even by English kindness.</p>
<p>The reasons for believing in Australia are mostly as sentimental as the
most sentimental reasons for believing in heaven. New South Wales is quite
literally regarded as a place where the wicked cease from troubling and
the weary are at rest; that is, a paradise for uncles who have turned
dishonest and for nephews who are born tired. British Columbia is in
strict sense a fairyland, it is a world where a magic and irrational luck
is supposed to attend the youngest sons. This strange optimism about the
ends of the earth is an English weakness; but to show that it is not a
coldness or a harshness it is quite sufficient to say that no one shared
it more than that gigantic English sentimentalist—the great Charles
Dickens. The end of “David Copperfield” is unreal not merely because it is
an optimistic ending, but because it is an Imperialistic ending. The
decorous British happiness planned out for David Copperfield and Agnes
would be embarrassed by the perpetual presence of the hopeless tragedy of
Emily, or the more hopeless farce of Micawber. Therefore, both Emily and
Micawber are shipped off to a vague colony where changes come over them
with no conceivable cause, except the climate. The tragic woman becomes
contented and the comic man becomes responsible, solely as the result of a
sea voyage and the first sight of a kangaroo.</p>
<p>To Imperialism in the light political sense, therefore, my only objection
is that it is an illusion of comfort; that an Empire whose heart is
failing should be specially proud of the extremities, is to me no more
sublime a fact than that an old dandy whose brain is gone should still be
proud of his legs. It consoles men for the evident ugliness and apathy of
England with legends of fair youth and heroic strenuousness in distant
continents and islands. A man can sit amid the squalor of Seven Dials and
feel that life is innocent and godlike in the bush or on the veldt. Just
so a man might sit in the squalor of Seven Dials and feel that life was
innocent and godlike in Brixton and Surbiton. Brixton and Surbiton are
“new”; they are expanding; they are “nearer to nature,” in the sense that
they have eaten up nature mile by mile. The only objection is the
objection of fact. The young men of Brixton are not young giants. The
lovers of Surbiton are not all pagan poets, singing with the sweet energy
of the spring. Nor are the people of the Colonies when you meet them young
giants or pagan poets. They are mostly Cockneys who have lost their last
music of real things by getting out of the sound of Bow Bells. Mr. Rudyard
Kipling, a man of real though decadent genius, threw a theoretic glamour
over them which is already fading. Mr. Kipling is, in a precise and rather
startling sense, the exception that proves the rule. For he has
imagination, of an oriental and cruel kind, but he has it, not because he
grew up in a new country, but precisely because he grew up in the oldest
country upon earth. He is rooted in a past—an Asiatic past. He might
never have written “Kabul River” if he had been born in Melbourne.</p>
<p>I say frankly, therefore (lest there should be any air of evasion), that
Imperialism in its common patriotic pretensions appears to me both weak
and perilous. It is the attempt of a European country to create a kind of
sham Europe which it can dominate, instead of the real Europe, which it
can only share. It is a love of living with one’s inferiors. The notion of
restoring the Roman Empire by oneself and for oneself is a dream that has
haunted every Christian nation in a different shape and in almost every
shape as a snare. The Spanish are a consistent and conservative people;
therefore they embodied that attempt at Empire in long and lingering
dynasties. The French are a violent people, and therefore they twice
conquered that Empire by violence of arms. The English are above all a
poetical and optimistic people; and therefore their Empire is something
vague and yet sympathetic, something distant and yet dear. But this dream
of theirs of being powerful in the uttermost places, though a native
weakness, is still a weakness in them; much more of a weakness than gold
was to Spain or glory to Napoleon. If ever we were in collision with our
real brothers and rivals we should leave all this fancy out of account. We
should no more dream of pitting Australian armies against German than of
pitting Tasmanian sculpture against French. I have thus explained, lest
anyone should accuse me of concealing an unpopular attitude, why I do not
believe in Imperialism as commonly understood. I think it not merely an
occasional wrong to other peoples, but a continuous feebleness, a running
sore, in my own. But it is also true that I have dwelt on this Imperialism
that is an amiable delusion partly in order to show how different it is
from the deeper, more sinister and yet more persuasive thing that I have
been forced to call Imperialism for the convenience of this chapter. In
order to get to the root of this evil and quite un-English Imperialism we
must cast back and begin anew with a more general discussion of the first
needs of human intercourse.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0015" id="link2H_4_0015"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> II. WISDOM AND THE WEATHER </h2>
<p>It is admitted, one may hope, that common things are never commonplace.
Birth is covered with curtains precisely because it is a staggering and
monstrous prodigy. Death and first love, though they happen to everybody,
can stop one’s heart with the very thought of them. But while this is
granted, something further may be claimed. It is not merely true that
these universal things are strange; it is moreover true that they are
subtle. In the last analysis most common things will be found to be highly
complicated. Some men of science do indeed get over the difficulty by
dealing only with the easy part of it: thus, they will call first love the
instinct of sex, and the awe of death the instinct of self-preservation.
But this is only getting over the difficulty of describing peacock green
by calling it blue. There is blue in it. That there is a strong physical
element in both romance and the Memento Mori makes them if possible more
baffling than if they had been wholly intellectual. No man could say
exactly how much his sexuality was colored by a clean love of beauty, or
by the mere boyish itch for irrevocable adventures, like running away to
sea. No man could say how far his animal dread of the end was mixed up
with mystical traditions touching morals and religion. It is exactly
because these things are animal, but not quite animal, that the dance of
all the difficulties begins. The materialists analyze the easy part, deny
the hard part and go home to their tea.</p>
<p>It is complete error to suppose that because a thing is vulgar therefore
it is not refined; that is, subtle and hard to define. A drawing-room song
of my youth which began “In the gloaming, O, my darling,” was vulgar
enough as a song; but the connection between human passion and the
twilight is none the less an exquisite and even inscrutable thing. Or to
take another obvious instance: the jokes about a mother-in-law are
scarcely delicate, but the problem of a mother-in-law is extremely
delicate. A mother-in-law is subtle because she is a thing like the
twilight. She is a mystical blend of two inconsistent things—law and
a mother. The caricatures misrepresent her; but they arise out of a real
human enigma. “Comic Cuts” deals with the difficulty wrongly, but it would
need George Meredith at his best to deal with the difficulty rightly. The
nearest statement of the problem perhaps is this: it is not that a
mother-in-law must be nasty, but that she must be very nice.</p>
<p>But it is best perhaps to take in illustration some daily custom we have
all heard despised as vulgar or trite. Take, for the sake of argument, the
custom of talking about the weather. Stevenson calls it “the very nadir
and scoff of good conversationalists.” Now there are very deep reasons for
talking about the weather, reasons that are delicate as well as deep; they
lie in layer upon layer of stratified sagacity. First of all it is a
gesture of primeval worship. The sky must be invoked; and to begin
everything with the weather is a sort of pagan way of beginning everything
with prayer. Jones and Brown talk about the weather: but so do Milton and
Shelley. Then it is an expression of that elementary idea in politeness—equality.
For the very word politeness is only the Greek for citizenship. The word
politeness is akin to the word policeman: a charming thought. Properly
understood, the citizen should be more polite than the gentleman; perhaps
the policeman should be the most courtly and elegant of the three. But all
good manners must obviously begin with the sharing of something in a
simple style. Two men should share an umbrella; if they have not got an
umbrella, they should at least share the rain, with all its rich
potentialities of wit and philosophy. “For He maketh His sun to shine....”
This is the second element in the weather; its recognition of human
equality in that we all have our hats under the dark blue spangled
umbrella of the universe. Arising out of this is the third wholesome
strain in the custom; I mean that it begins with the body and with our
inevitable bodily brotherhood. All true friendliness begins with fire and
food and drink and the recognition of rain or frost. Those who will not
begin at the bodily end of things are already prigs and may soon be
Christian Scientists. Each human soul has in a sense to enact for itself
the gigantic humility of the Incarnation. Every man must descend into the
flesh to meet mankind.</p>
<p>Briefly, in the mere observation “a fine day” there is the whole great
human idea of comradeship. Now, pure comradeship is another of those broad
and yet bewildering things. We all enjoy it; yet when we come to talk
about it we almost always talk nonsense, chiefly because we suppose it to
be a simpler affair than it is. It is simple to conduct; but it is by no
means simple to analyze. Comradeship is at the most only one half of human
life; the other half is Love, a thing so different that one might fancy it
had been made for another universe. And I do not mean mere sex love; any
kind of concentrated passion, maternal love, or even the fiercer kinds of
friendship are in their nature alien to pure comradeship. Both sides are
essential to life; and both are known in differing degrees to everybody of
every age or sex. But very broadly speaking it may still be said that
women stand for the dignity of love and men for the dignity of
comradeship. I mean that the institution would hardly be expected if the
males of the tribe did not mount guard over it. The affections in which
women excel have so much more authority and intensity that pure
comradeship would be washed away if it were not rallied and guarded in
clubs, corps, colleges, banquets and regiments. Most of us have heard the
voice in which the hostess tells her husband not to sit too long over the
cigars. It is the dreadful voice of Love, seeking to destroy Comradeship.</p>
<p>All true comradeship has in it those three elements which I have remarked
in the ordinary exclamation about the weather. First, it has a sort of
broad philosophy like the common sky, emphasizing that we are all under
the same cosmic conditions. We are all in the same boat, the “winged rock”
of Mr. Herbert Trench. Secondly, it recognizes this bond as the essential
one; for comradeship is simply humanity seen in that one aspect in which
men are really equal. The old writers were entirely wise when they talked
of the equality of men; but they were also very wise in not mentioning
women. Women are always authoritarian; they are always above or below;
that is why marriage is a sort of poetical see-saw. There are only three
things in the world that women do not understand; and they are Liberty,
Equality, and Fraternity. But men (a class little understood in the modern
world) find these things the breath of their nostrils; and our most
learned ladies will not even begin to understand them until they make
allowance for this kind of cool camaraderie. Lastly, it contains the third
quality of the weather, the insistence upon the body and its indispensable
satisfaction. No one has even begun to understand comradeship who does not
accept with it a certain hearty eagerness in eating, drinking, or smoking,
an uproarious materialism which to many women appears only hoggish. You
may call the thing an orgy or a sacrament; it is certainly an essential.
It is at root a resistance to the superciliousness of the individual. Nay,
its very swaggering and howling are humble. In the heart of its rowdiness
there is a sort of mad modesty; a desire to melt the separate soul into
the mass of unpretentious masculinity. It is a clamorous confession of the
weakness of all flesh. No man must be superior to the things that are
common to men. This sort of equality must be bodily and gross and comic.
Not only are we all in the same boat, but we are all seasick.</p>
<p>The word comradeship just now promises to become as fatuous as the word
“affinity.” There are clubs of a Socialist sort where all the members, men
and women, call each other “Comrade.” I have no serious emotions, hostile
or otherwise, about this particular habit: at the worst it is
conventionality, and at the best flirtation. I am convinced here only to
point out a rational principle. If you choose to lump all flowers
together, lilies and dahlias and tulips and chrysanthemums and call them
all daisies, you will find that you have spoiled the very fine word daisy.
If you choose to call every human attachment comradeship, if you include
under that name the respect of a youth for a venerable prophetess, the
interest of a man in a beautiful woman who baffles him, the pleasure of a
philosophical old fogy in a girl who is impudent and innocent, the end of
the meanest quarrel or the beginning of the most mountainous love; if you
are going to call all these comradeship, you will gain nothing, you will
only lose a word. Daisies are obvious and universal and open; but they are
only one kind of flower. Comradeship is obvious and universal and open;
but it is only one kind of affection; it has characteristics that would
destroy any other kind. Anyone who has known true comradeship in a club or
in a regiment, knows that it is impersonal. There is a pedantic phrase
used in debating clubs which is strictly true to the masculine emotion;
they call it “speaking to the question.” Women speak to each other; men
speak to the subject they are speaking about. Many an honest man has sat
in a ring of his five best friends under heaven and forgotten who was in
the room while he explained some system. This is not peculiar to
intellectual men; men are all theoretical, whether they are talking about
God or about golf. Men are all impersonal; that is to say, republican. No
one remembers after a really good talk who has said the good things. Every
man speaks to a visionary multitude; a mystical cloud, that is called the
club.</p>
<p>It is obvious that this cool and careless quality which is essential to
the collective affection of males involves disadvantages and dangers. It
leads to spitting; it leads to coarse speech; it must lead to these things
so long as it is honorable; comradeship must be in some degree ugly. The
moment beauty is mentioned in male friendship, the nostrils are stopped
with the smell of abominable things. Friendship must be physically dirty
if it is to be morally clean. It must be in its shirt sleeves. The chaos
of habits that always goes with males when left entirely to themselves has
only one honorable cure; and that is the strict discipline of a monastery.
Anyone who has seen our unhappy young idealists in East End Settlements
losing their collars in the wash and living on tinned salmon will fully
understand why it was decided by the wisdom of St. Bernard or St.
Benedict, that if men were to live without women, they must not live
without rules. Something of the same sort of artificial exactitude, of
course, is obtained in an army; and an army also has to be in many ways
monastic; only that it has celibacy without chastity. But these things do
not apply to normal married men. These have a quite sufficient restraint
on their instinctive anarchy in the savage common-sense of the other sex.
There is only one very timid sort of man that is not afraid of women.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0016" id="link2H_4_0016"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> III. THE COMMON VISION </h2>
<p>Now this masculine love of an open and level camaraderie is the life
within all democracies and attempts to govern by debate; without it the
republic would be a dead formula. Even as it is, of course, the spirit of
democracy frequently differs widely from the letter, and a pothouse is
often a better test than a Parliament. Democracy in its human sense is not
arbitrament by the majority; it is not even arbitrament by everybody. It
can be more nearly defined as arbitrament by anybody. I mean that it rests
on that club habit of taking a total stranger for granted, of assuming
certain things to be inevitably common to yourself and him. Only the
things that anybody may be presumed to hold have the full authority of
democracy. Look out of the window and notice the first man who walks by.
The Liberals may have swept England with an over-whelming majority; but
you would not stake a button that the man is a Liberal. The Bible may be
read in all schools and respected in all law courts; but you would not bet
a straw that he believes in the Bible. But you would bet your week’s
wages, let us say, that he believes in wearing clothes. You would bet that
he believes that physical courage is a fine thing, or that parents have
authority over children. Of course, he might be the millionth man who does
not believe these things; if it comes to that, he might be the Bearded
Lady dressed up as a man. But these prodigies are quite a different thing
from any mere calculation of numbers. People who hold these views are not
a minority, but a monstrosity. But of these universal dogmas that have
full democratic authority the only test is this test of anybody. What you
would observe before any newcomer in a tavern—that is the real
English law. The first man you see from the window, he is the King of
England.</p>
<p>The decay of taverns, which is but a part of the general decay of
democracy, has undoubtedly weakened this masculine spirit of equality. I
remember that a roomful of Socialists literally laughed when I told them
that there were no two nobler words in all poetry than Public House. They
thought it was a joke. Why they should think it a joke, since they want to
make all houses public houses, I cannot imagine. But if anyone wishes to
see the real rowdy egalitarianism which is necessary (to males, at least)
he can find it as well as anywhere in the great old tavern disputes which
come down to us in such books as Boswell’s Johnson. It is worth while to
mention that one name especially because the modern world in its morbidity
has done it a strange injustice. The demeanor of Johnson, it is said, was
“harsh and despotic.” It was occasionally harsh, but it was never
despotic. Johnson was not in the least a despot; Johnson was a demagogue,
he shouted against a shouting crowd. The very fact that he wrangled with
other people is proof that other people were allowed to wrangle with him.
His very brutality was based on the idea of an equal scrimmage, like that
of football. It is strictly true that he bawled and banged the table
because he was a modest man. He was honestly afraid of being overwhelmed
or even overlooked. Addison had exquisite manners and was the king of his
company; he was polite to everybody; but superior to everybody; therefore
he has been handed down forever in the immortal insult of Pope—</p>
<p>“Like Cato, give his little Senate laws And sit attentive to his own
applause.”</p>
<p>Johnson, so far from being king of his company, was a sort of Irish Member
in his own Parliament. Addison was a courteous superior and was hated.
Johnson was an insolent equal and therefore was loved by all who knew him,
and handed down in a marvellous book, which is one of the mere miracles of
love.</p>
<p>This doctrine of equality is essential to conversation; so much may be
admitted by anyone who knows what conversation is. Once arguing at a table
in a tavern the most famous man on earth would wish to be obscure, so that
his brilliant remarks might blaze like the stars on the background of his
obscurity. To anything worth calling a man nothing can be conceived more
cold or cheerless than to be king of your company. But it may be said that
in masculine sports and games, other than the great game of debate, there
is definite emulation and eclipse. There is indeed emulation, but this is
only an ardent sort of equality. Games are competitive, because that is
the only way of making them exciting. But if anyone doubts that men must
forever return to the ideal of equality, it is only necessary to answer
that there is such a thing as a handicap. If men exulted in mere
superiority, they would seek to see how far such superiority could go;
they would be glad when one strong runner came in miles ahead of all the
rest. But what men like is not the triumph of superiors, but the struggle
of equals; and, therefore, they introduce even into their competitive
sports an artificial equality. It is sad to think how few of those who
arrange our sporting handicaps can be supposed with any probability to
realize that they are abstract and even severe republicans.</p>
<p>No; the real objection to equality and self-rule has nothing to do with
any of these free and festive aspects of mankind; all men are democrats
when they are happy. The philosophic opponent of democracy would
substantially sum up his position by saying that it “will not work.”
Before going further, I will register in passing a protest against the
assumption that working is the one test of humanity. Heaven does not work;
it plays. Men are most themselves when they are free; and if I find that
men are snobs in their work but democrats on their holidays, I shall take
the liberty to believe their holidays. But it is this question of work
which really perplexes the question of equality; and it is with that that
we must now deal. Perhaps the truth can be put most pointedly thus: that
democracy has one real enemy, and that is civilization. Those utilitarian
miracles which science has made are anti-democratic, not so much in their
perversion, or even in their practical result, as in their primary shape
and purpose. The Frame-Breaking Rioters were right; not perhaps in
thinking that machines would make fewer men workmen; but certainly in
thinking that machines would make fewer men masters. More wheels do mean
fewer handles; fewer handles do mean fewer hands. The machinery of science
must be individualistic and isolated. A mob can shout round a palace; but
a mob cannot shout down a telephone. The specialist appears and democracy
is half spoiled at a stroke.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0017" id="link2H_4_0017"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> IV. THE INSANE NECESSITY </h2>
<p>The common conception among the dregs of Darwinian culture is that men
have slowly worked their way out of inequality into a state of comparative
equality. The truth is, I fancy, almost exactly the opposite. All men have
normally and naturally begun with the idea of equality; they have only
abandoned it late and reluctantly, and always for some material reason of
detail. They have never naturally felt that one class of men was superior
to another; they have always been driven to assume it through certain
practical limitations of space and time.</p>
<p>For example, there is one element which must always tend to oligarchy—or
rather to despotism; I mean the element of hurry. If the house has caught
fire a man must ring up the fire engines; a committee cannot ring them up.
If a camp is surprised by night somebody must give the order to fire;
there is no time to vote it. It is solely a question of the physical
limitations of time and space; not at all of any mental limitations in the
mass of men commanded. If all the people in the house were men of destiny
it would still be better that they should not all talk into the telephone
at once; nay, it would be better that the silliest man of all should speak
uninterrupted. If an army actually consisted of nothing but Hanibals and
Napoleons, it would still be better in the case of a surprise that they
should not all give orders together. Nay, it would be better if the
stupidest of them all gave the orders. Thus, we see that merely military
subordination, so far from resting on the inequality of men, actually
rests on the equality of men. Discipline does not involve the Carlylean
notion that somebody is always right when everybody is wrong, and that we
must discover and crown that somebody. On the contrary, discipline means
that in certain frightfully rapid circumstances, one can trust anybody so
long as he is not everybody. The military spirit does not mean (as Carlyle
fancied) obeying the strongest and wisest man. On the contrary, the
military spirit means, if anything, obeying the weakest and stupidest man,
obeying him merely because he is a man, and not a thousand men. Submission
to a weak man is discipline. Submission to a strong man is only servility.</p>
<p>Now it can be easily shown that the thing we call aristocracy in Europe is
not in its origin and spirit an aristocracy at all. It is not a system of
spiritual degrees and distinctions like, for example, the caste system of
India, or even like the old Greek distinction between free men and slaves.
It is simply the remains of a military organization, framed partly to
sustain the sinking Roman Empire, partly to break and avenge the awful
onslaught of Islam. The word Duke simply means Colonel, just as the word
Emperor simply means Commander-in-Chief. The whole story is told in the
single title of Counts of the Holy Roman Empire, which merely means
officers in the European army against the contemporary Yellow Peril. Now
in an army nobody ever dreams of supposing that difference of rank
represents a difference of moral reality. Nobody ever says about a
regiment, “Your Major is very humorous and energetic; your Colonel, of
course, must be even more humorous and yet more energetic.” No one ever
says, in reporting a mess-room conversation, “Lieutenant Jones was very
witty, but was naturally inferior to Captain Smith.” The essence of an
army is the idea of official inequality, founded on unofficial equality.
The Colonel is not obeyed because he is the best man, but because he is
the Colonel. Such was probably the spirit of the system of dukes and
counts when it first arose out of the military spirit and military
necessities of Rome. With the decline of those necessities it has
gradually ceased to have meaning as a military organization, and become
honeycombed with unclean plutocracy. Even now it is not a spiritual
aristocracy—it is not so bad as all that. It is simply an army
without an enemy—billeted upon the people.</p>
<p>Man, therefore, has a specialist as well as comrade-like aspect; and the
case of militarism is not the only case of such specialist submission. The
tinker and tailor, as well as the soldier and sailor, require a certain
rigidity of rapidity of action: at least, if the tinker is not organized
that is largely why he does not tink on any large scale. The tinker and
tailor often represent the two nomadic races in Europe: the Gipsy and the
Jew; but the Jew alone has influence because he alone accepts some sort of
discipline. Man, we say, has two sides, the specialist side where he must
have subordination, and the social side where he must have equality. There
is a truth in the saying that ten tailors go to make a man; but we must
remember also that ten Poets Laureate or ten Astronomers Royal go to make
a man, too. Ten million tradesmen go to make Man himself; but humanity
consists of tradesmen when they are not talking shop. Now the peculiar
peril of our time, which I call for argument’s sake Imperialism or
Caesarism, is the complete eclipse of comradeship and equality by
specialism and domination.</p>
<p>There are only two kinds of social structure conceivable—personal
government and impersonal government. If my anarchic friends will not have
rules—they will have rulers. Preferring personal government, with
its tact and flexibility, is called Royalism. Preferring impersonal
government, with its dogmas and definitions, is called Republicanism.
Objecting broadmindedly both to kings and creeds is called Bosh; at least,
I know no more philosophic word for it. You can be guided by the
shrewdness or presence of mind of one ruler, or by the equality and
ascertained justice of one rule; but you must have one or the other, or
you are not a nation, but a nasty mess. Now men in their aspect of
equality and debate adore the idea of rules; they develop and complicate
them greatly to excess. A man finds far more regulations and definitions
in his club, where there are rules, than in his home, where there is a
ruler. A deliberate assembly, the House of Commons, for instance, carries
this mummery to the point of a methodical madness. The whole system is
stiff with rigid unreason; like the Royal Court in Lewis Carroll. You
would think the Speaker would speak; therefore he is mostly silent. You
would think a man would take off his hat to stop and put it on to go away;
therefore he takes off his hat to walk out and puts it on to stop in.
Names are forbidden, and a man must call his own father “my right
honorable friend the member for West Birmingham.” These are, perhaps,
fantasies of decay: but fundamentally they answer a masculine appetite.
Men feel that rules, even if irrational, are universal; men feel that law
is equal, even when it is not equitable. There is a wild fairness in the
thing—as there is in tossing up.</p>
<p>Again, it is gravely unfortunate that when critics do attack such cases as
the Commons it is always on the points (perhaps the few points) where the
Commons are right. They denounce the House as the Talking-Shop, and
complain that it wastes time in wordy mazes. Now this is just one respect
in which the Commons are actually like the Common People. If they love
leisure and long debate, it is because all men love it; that they really
represent England. There the Parliament does approach to the virile
virtues of the pothouse.</p>
<p>The real truth is that adumbrated in the introductory section when we
spoke of the sense of home and property, as now we speak of the sense of
counsel and community. All men do naturally love the idea of leisure,
laughter, loud and equal argument; but there stands a specter in our hall.
We are conscious of the towering modern challenge that is called
specialism or cut-throat competition—Business. Business will have
nothing to do with leisure; business will have no truck with comradeship;
business will pretend to no patience with all the legal fictions and
fantastic handicaps by which comradeship protects its egalitarian ideal.
The modern millionaire, when engaged in the agreeable and typical task of
sacking his own father, will certainly not refer to him as the right
honorable clerk from the Laburnum Road, Brixton. Therefore there has
arisen in modern life a literary fashion devoting itself to the romance of
business, to great demigods of greed and to fairyland of finance. This
popular philosophy is utterly despotic and anti-democratic; this fashion
is the flower of that Caesarism against which I am concerned to protest.
The ideal millionaire is strong in the possession of a brain of steel. The
fact that the real millionaire is rather more often strong in the
possession of a head of wood, does not alter the spirit and trend of the
idolatry. The essential argument is “Specialists must be despots; men must
be specialists. You cannot have equality in a soap factory; so you cannot
have it anywhere. You cannot have comradeship in a wheat corner; so you
cannot have it at all. We must have commercial civilization; therefore we
must destroy democracy.” I know that plutocrats have seldom sufficient
fancy to soar to such examples as soap or wheat. They generally confine
themselves, with fine freshness of mind, to a comparison between the state
and a ship. One anti-democratic writer remarked that he would not like to
sail in a vessel in which the cabin-boy had an equal vote with the
captain. It might easily be urged in answer that many a ship (the
Victoria, for instance) was sunk because an admiral gave an order which a
cabin-boy could see was wrong. But this is a debating reply; the essential
fallacy is both deeper and simpler. The elementary fact is that we were
all born in a state; we were not all born on a ship; like some of our
great British bankers. A ship still remains a specialist experiment, like
a diving-bell or a flying ship: in such peculiar perils the need for
promptitude constitutes the need for autocracy. But we live and die in the
vessel of the state; and if we cannot find freedom camaraderie and the
popular element in the state, we cannot find it at all. And the modern
doctrine of commercial despotism means that we shall not find it at all.
Our specialist trades in their highly civilized state cannot (it says) be
run without the whole brutal business of bossing and sacking, “too old at
forty” and all the rest of the filth. And they must be run, and therefore
we call on Caesar. Nobody but the Superman could descend to do such dirty
work.</p>
<p>Now (to reiterate my title) this is what is wrong. This is the huge modern
heresy of altering the human soul to fit its conditions, instead of
altering human conditions to fit the human soul. If soap boiling is really
inconsistent with brotherhood, so much the worst for soap-boiling, not for
brotherhood. If civilization really cannot get on with democracy, so much
the worse for civilization, not for democracy. Certainly, it would be far
better to go back to village communes, if they really are communes.
Certainly, it would be better to do without soap rather than to do without
society. Certainly, we would sacrifice all our wires, wheels, systems,
specialties, physical science and frenzied finance for one half-hour of
happiness such as has often come to us with comrades in a common tavern. I
do not say the sacrifice will be necessary; I only say it will be easy.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_PART3" id="link2H_PART3"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> PART THREE. FEMINISM, OR THE MISTAKE ABOUT WOMAN </h2>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0019" id="link2H_4_0019"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> I. THE UNMILITARY SUFFRAGETTE </h2>
<p>It will be better to adopt in this chapter the same process that appeared
a piece of mental justice in the last. My general opinions on the feminine
question are such as many suffragists would warmly approve; and it would
be easy to state them without any open reference to the current
controversy. But just as it seemed more decent to say first that I was not
in favor of Imperialism even in its practical and popular sense, so it
seems more decent to say the same of Female Suffrage, in its practical and
popular sense. In other words, it is only fair to state, however
hurriedly, the superficial objection to the Suffragettes before we go on
to the really subtle questions behind the Suffrage.</p>
<p>Well, to get this honest but unpleasant business over, the objection to
the Suffragettes is not that they are Militant Suffragettes. On the
contrary, it is that they are not militant enough. A revolution is a
military thing; it has all the military virtues; one of which is that it
comes to an end. Two parties fight with deadly weapons, but under certain
rules of arbitrary honor; the party that wins becomes the government and
proceeds to govern. The aim of civil war, like the aim of all war, is
peace. Now the Suffragettes cannot raise civil war in this soldierly and
decisive sense; first, because they are women; and, secondly, because they
are very few women. But they can raise something else; which is altogether
another pair of shoes. They do not create revolution; what they do create
is anarchy; and the difference between these is not a question of
violence, but a question of fruitfulness and finality. Revolution of its
nature produces government; anarchy only produces more anarchy. Men may
have what opinions they please about the beheading of King Charles or King
Louis, but they cannot deny that Bradshaw and Cromwell ruled, that Carnot
and Napoleon governed. Someone conquered; something occurred. You can only
knock off the King’s head once. But you can knock off the King’s hat any
number of times. Destruction is finite, obstruction is infinite: so long
as rebellion takes the form of mere disorder (instead of an attempt to
enforce a new order) there is no logical end to it; it can feed on itself
and renew itself forever. If Napoleon had not wanted to be a Consul, but
only wanted to be a nuisance, he could, possibly, have prevented any
government arising successfully out of the Revolution. But such a
proceeding would not have deserved the dignified name of rebellion.</p>
<p>It is exactly this unmilitant quality in the Suffragettes that makes their
superficial problem. The problem is that their action has none of the
advantages of ultimate violence; it does not afford a test. War is a
dreadful thing; but it does prove two points sharply and unanswerably—numbers,
and an unnatural valor. One does discover the two urgent matters; how many
rebels there are alive, and how many are ready to be dead. But a tiny
minority, even an interested minority, may maintain mere disorder forever.
There is also, of course, in the case of these women, the further falsity
that is introduced by their sex. It is false to state the matter as a mere
brutal question of strength. If his muscles give a man a vote, then his
horse ought to have two votes and his elephant five votes. The truth is
more subtle than that; it is that bodily outbreak is a man’s instinctive
weapon, like the hoofs to the horse or the tusks to the elephant. All riot
is a threat of war; but the woman is brandishing a weapon she can never
use. There are many weapons that she could and does use. If (for example)
all the women nagged for a vote they would get it in a month. But there
again, one must remember, it would be necessary to get all the women to
nag. And that brings us to the end of the political surface of the matter.
The working objection to the Suffragette philosophy is simply that
overmastering millions of women do not agree with it. I am aware that some
maintain that women ought to have votes whether the majority wants them or
not; but this is surely a strange and childish case of setting up formal
democracy to the destruction of actual democracy. What should the mass of
women decide if they do not decide their general place in the State? These
people practically say that females may vote about everything except about
Female Suffrage.</p>
<p>But having again cleared my conscience of my merely political and possibly
unpopular opinion, I will again cast back and try to treat the matter in a
slower and more sympathetic style; attempt to trace the real roots of
woman’s position in the western state, and the causes of our existing
traditions or perhaps prejudices upon the point. And for this purpose it
is again necessary to travel far from the modern topic, the mere
Suffragette of today, and to go back to subjects which, though much more
old, are, I think, considerably more fresh.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0020" id="link2H_4_0020"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> II. THE UNIVERSAL STICK </h2>
<p>Cast your eye round the room in which you sit, and select some three or
four things that have been with man almost since his beginning; which at
least we hear of early in the centuries and often among the tribes. Let me
suppose that you see a knife on the table, a stick in the corner, or a
fire on the hearth. About each of these you will notice one speciality;
that not one of them is special. Each of these ancestral things is a
universal thing; made to supply many different needs; and while tottering
pedants nose about to find the cause and origin of some old custom, the
truth is that it had fifty causes or a hundred origins. The knife is meant
to cut wood, to cut cheese, to cut pencils, to cut throats; for a myriad
ingenious or innocent human objects. The stick is meant partly to hold a
man up, partly to knock a man down; partly to point with like a
finger-post, partly to balance with like a balancing pole, partly to
trifle with like a cigarette, partly to kill with like a club of a giant;
it is a crutch and a cudgel; an elongated finger and an extra leg. The
case is the same, of course, with the fire; about which the strangest
modern views have arisen. A queer fancy seems to be current that a fire
exists to warm people. It exists to warm people, to light their darkness,
to raise their spirits, to toast their muffins, to air their rooms, to
cook their chestnuts, to tell stories to their children, to make checkered
shadows on their walls, to boil their hurried kettles, and to be the red
heart of a man’s house and that hearth for which, as the great heathens
said, a man should die.</p>
<p>Now it is the great mark of our modernity that people are always proposing
substitutes for these old things; and these substitutes always answer one
purpose where the old thing answered ten. The modern man will wave a
cigarette instead of a stick; he will cut his pencil with a little
screwing pencil-sharpener instead of a knife; and he will even boldly
offer to be warmed by hot water pipes instead of a fire. I have my doubts
about pencil-sharpeners even for sharpening pencils; and about hot water
pipes even for heat. But when we think of all those other requirements
that these institutions answered, there opens before us the whole horrible
harlequinade of our civilization. We see as in a vision a world where a
man tries to cut his throat with a pencil-sharpener; where a man must
learn single-stick with a cigarette; where a man must try to toast muffins
at electric lamps, and see red and golden castles in the surface of hot
water pipes.</p>
<p>The principle of which I speak can be seen everywhere in a comparison
between the ancient and universal things and the modern and specialist
things. The object of a theodolite is to lie level; the object of a stick
is to swing loose at any angle; to whirl like the very wheel of liberty.
The object of a lancet is to lance; when used for slashing, gashing,
ripping, lopping off heads and limbs, it is a disappointing instrument.
The object of an electric light is merely to light (a despicable modesty);
and the object of an asbestos stove... I wonder what is the object of an
asbestos stove? If a man found a coil of rope in a desert he could at
least think of all the things that can be done with a coil of rope; and
some of them might even be practical. He could tow a boat or lasso a
horse. He could play cat’s-cradle, or pick oakum. He could construct a
rope-ladder for an eloping heiress, or cord her boxes for a travelling
maiden aunt. He could learn to tie a bow, or he could hang himself. Far
otherwise with the unfortunate traveller who should find a telephone in
the desert. You can telephone with a telephone; you cannot do anything
else with it. And though this is one of the wildest joys of life, it falls
by one degree from its full delirium when there is nobody to answer you.
The contention is, in brief, that you must pull up a hundred roots, and
not one, before you uproot any of these hoary and simple expedients. It is
only with great difficulty that a modern scientific sociologist can be got
to see that any old method has a leg to stand on. But almost every old
method has four or five legs to stand on. Almost all the old institutions
are quadrupeds; and some of them are centipedes.</p>
<p>Consider these cases, old and new, and you will observe the operation of a
general tendency. Everywhere there was one big thing that served six
purposes; everywhere now there are six small things; or, rather (and there
is the trouble), there are just five and a half. Nevertheless, we will not
say that this separation and specialism is entirely useless or
inexcusable. I have often thanked God for the telephone; I may any day
thank God for the lancet; and there is none of these brilliant and narrow
inventions (except, of course, the asbestos stove) which might not be at
some moment necessary and lovely. But I do not think the most austere
upholder of specialism will deny that there is in these old, many-sided
institutions an element of unity and universality which may well be
preserved in its due proportion and place. Spiritually, at least, it will
be admitted that some all-round balance is needed to equalize the
extravagance of experts. It would not be difficult to carry the parable of
the knife and stick into higher regions. Religion, the immortal maiden,
has been a maid-of-all-work as well as a servant of mankind. She provided
men at once with the theoretic laws of an unalterable cosmos and also with
the practical rules of the rapid and thrilling game of morality. She
taught logic to the student and told fairy tales to the children; it was
her business to confront the nameless gods whose fears are on all flesh,
and also to see the streets were spotted with silver and scarlet, that
there was a day for wearing ribbons or an hour for ringing bells. The
large uses of religion have been broken up into lesser specialities, just
as the uses of the hearth have been broken up into hot water pipes and
electric bulbs. The romance of ritual and colored emblem has been taken
over by that narrowest of all trades, modern art (the sort called art for
art’s sake), and men are in modern practice informed that they may use all
symbols so long as they mean nothing by them. The romance of conscience
has been dried up into the science of ethics; which may well be called
decency for decency’s sake, decency unborn of cosmic energies and barren
of artistic flower. The cry to the dim gods, cut off from ethics and
cosmology, has become mere Psychical Research. Everything has been
sundered from everything else, and everything has grown cold. Soon we
shall hear of specialists dividing the tune from the words of a song, on
the ground that they spoil each other; and I did once meet a man who
openly advocated the separation of almonds and raisins. This world is all
one wild divorce court; nevertheless, there are many who still hear in
their souls the thunder of authority of human habit; those whom Man hath
joined let no man sunder.</p>
<p>This book must avoid religion, but there must (I say) be many, religious
and irreligious, who will concede that this power of answering many
purposes was a sort of strength which should not wholly die out of our
lives. As a part of personal character, even the moderns will agree that
many-sidedness is a merit and a merit that may easily be overlooked. This
balance and universality has been the vision of many groups of men in many
ages. It was the Liberal Education of Aristotle; the jack-of-all-trades
artistry of Leonardo da Vinci and his friends; the august amateurishness
of the Cavalier Person of Quality like Sir William Temple or the great
Earl of Dorset. It has appeared in literature in our time in the most
erratic and opposite shapes, set to almost inaudible music by Walter Pater
and enunciated through a foghorn by Walt Whitman. But the great mass of
men have always been unable to achieve this literal universality, because
of the nature of their work in the world. Not, let it be noted, because of
the existence of their work. Leonardo da Vinci must have worked pretty
hard; on the other hand, many a government office clerk, village constable
or elusive plumber may do (to all human appearance) no work at all, and
yet show no signs of the Aristotelian universalism. What makes it
difficult for the average man to be a universalist is that the average man
has to be a specialist; he has not only to learn one trade, but to learn
it so well as to uphold him in a more or less ruthless society. This is
generally true of males from the first hunter to the last electrical
engineer; each has not merely to act, but to excel. Nimrod has not only to
be a mighty hunter before the Lord, but also a mighty hunter before the
other hunters. The electrical engineer has to be a very electrical
engineer, or he is outstripped by engineers yet more electrical. Those
very miracles of the human mind on which the modern world prides itself,
and rightly in the main, would be impossible without a certain
concentration which disturbs the pure balance of reason more than does
religious bigotry. No creed can be so limiting as that awful adjuration
that the cobbler must not go beyond his last. So the largest and wildest
shots of our world are but in one direction and with a defined trajectory:
the gunner cannot go beyond his shot, and his shot so often falls short;
the astronomer cannot go beyond his telescope and his telescope goes such
a little way. All these are like men who have stood on the high peak of a
mountain and seen the horizon like a single ring and who then descend down
different paths towards different towns, traveling slow or fast. It is
right; there must be people traveling to different towns; there must be
specialists; but shall no one behold the horizon? Shall all mankind be
specialist surgeons or peculiar plumbers; shall all humanity be
monomaniac? Tradition has decided that only half of humanity shall be
monomaniac. It has decided that in every home there shall be a tradesman
and a Jack-of-all-trades. But it has also decided, among other things,
that the Jack-of-all-trades shall be a Jill-of-all-trades. It has decided,
rightly or wrongly, that this specialism and this universalism shall be
divided between the sexes. Cleverness shall be left for men and wisdom for
women. For cleverness kills wisdom; that is one of the few sad and certain
things.</p>
<p>But for women this ideal of comprehensive capacity (or common-sense) must
long ago have been washed away. It must have melted in the frightful
furnaces of ambition and eager technicality. A man must be partly a
one-idead man, because he is a one-weaponed man—and he is flung
naked into the fight. The world’s demand comes to him direct; to his wife
indirectly. In short, he must (as the books on Success say) give “his
best”; and what a small part of a man “his best” is! His second and third
best are often much better. If he is the first violin he must fiddle for
life; he must not remember that he is a fine fourth bagpipe, a fair
fifteenth billiard-cue, a foil, a fountain pen, a hand at whist, a gun,
and an image of God.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0021" id="link2H_4_0021"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> III. THE EMANCIPATION OF DOMESTICITY </h2>
<p>And it should be remarked in passing that this force upon a man to develop
one feature has nothing to do with what is commonly called our competitive
system, but would equally exist under any rationally conceivable kind of
Collectivism. Unless the Socialists are frankly ready for a fall in the
standard of violins, telescopes and electric lights, they must somehow
create a moral demand on the individual that he shall keep up his present
concentration on these things. It was only by men being in some degree
specialist that there ever were any telescopes; they must certainly be in
some degree specialist in order to keep them going. It is not by making a
man a State wage-earner that you can prevent him thinking principally
about the very difficult way he earns his wages. There is only one way to
preserve in the world that high levity and that more leisurely outlook
which fulfils the old vision of universalism. That is, to permit the
existence of a partly protected half of humanity; a half which the
harassing industrial demand troubles indeed, but only troubles indirectly.
In other words, there must be in every center of humanity one human being
upon a larger plan; one who does not “give her best,” but gives her all.</p>
<p>Our old analogy of the fire remains the most workable one. The fire need
not blaze like electricity nor boil like boiling water; its point is that
it blazes more than water and warms more than light. The wife is like the
fire, or to put things in their proper proportion, the fire is like the
wife. Like the fire, the woman is expected to cook: not to excel in
cooking, but to cook; to cook better than her husband who is earning the
coke by lecturing on botany or breaking stones. Like the fire, the woman
is expected to tell tales to the children, not original and artistic
tales, but tales—better tales than would probably be told by a
first-class cook. Like the fire, the woman is expected to illuminate and
ventilate, not by the most startling revelations or the wildest winds of
thought, but better than a man can do it after breaking stones or
lecturing. But she cannot be expected to endure anything like this
universal duty if she is also to endure the direct cruelty of competitive
or bureaucratic toil. Woman must be a cook, but not a competitive cook; a
school mistress, but not a competitive schoolmistress; a house-decorator
but not a competitive house-decorator; a dressmaker, but not a competitive
dressmaker. She should have not one trade but twenty hobbies; she, unlike
the man, may develop all her second bests. This is what has been really
aimed at from the first in what is called the seclusion, or even the
oppression, of women. Women were not kept at home in order to keep them
narrow; on the contrary, they were kept at home in order to keep them
broad. The world outside the home was one mass of narrowness, a maze of
cramped paths, a madhouse of monomaniacs. It was only by partly limiting
and protecting the woman that she was enabled to play at five or six
professions and so come almost as near to God as the child when he plays
at a hundred trades. But the woman’s professions, unlike the child’s, were
all truly and almost terribly fruitful; so tragically real that nothing
but her universality and balance prevented them being merely morbid. This
is the substance of the contention I offer about the historic female
position. I do not deny that women have been wronged and even tortured;
but I doubt if they were ever tortured so much as they are tortured now by
the absurd modern attempt to make them domestic empresses and competitive
clerks at the same time. I do not deny that even under the old tradition
women had a harder time than men; that is why we take off our hats. I do
not deny that all these various female functions were exasperating; but I
say that there was some aim and meaning in keeping them various. I do not
pause even to deny that woman was a servant; but at least she was a
general servant.</p>
<p>The shortest way of summarizing the position is to say that woman stands
for the idea of Sanity; that intellectual home to which the mind must
return after every excursion on extravagance. The mind that finds its way
to wild places is the poet’s; but the mind that never finds its way back
is the lunatic’s. There must in every machine be a part that moves and a
part that stands still; there must be in everything that changes a part
that is unchangeable. And many of the phenomena which moderns hastily
condemn are really parts of this position of the woman as the center and
pillar of health. Much of what is called her subservience, and even her
pliability, is merely the subservience and pliability of a universal
remedy; she varies as medicines vary, with the disease. She has to be an
optimist to the morbid husband, a salutary pessimist to the happy-go-lucky
husband. She has to prevent the Quixote from being put upon, and the bully
from putting upon others. The French King wrote—</p>
<p>“Toujours femme varie Bien fol qui s’y fie,”<br/></p>
<p>but the truth is that woman always varies, and that is exactly why we
always trust her. To correct every adventure and extravagance with its
antidote in common-sense is not (as the moderns seem to think) to be in
the position of a spy or a slave. It is to be in the position of Aristotle
or (at the lowest) Herbert Spencer, to be a universal morality, a complete
system of thought. The slave flatters; the complete moralist rebukes. It
is, in short, to be a Trimmer in the true sense of that honorable term;
which for some reason or other is always used in a sense exactly opposite
to its own. It seems really to be supposed that a Trimmer means a cowardly
person who always goes over to the stronger side. It really means a highly
chivalrous person who always goes over to the weaker side; like one who
trims a boat by sitting where there are few people seated. Woman is a
trimmer; and it is a generous, dangerous and romantic trade.</p>
<p>The final fact which fixes this is a sufficiently plain one. Supposing it
to be conceded that humanity has acted at least not unnaturally in
dividing itself into two halves, respectively typifying the ideals of
special talent and of general sanity (since they are genuinely difficult
to combine completely in one mind), it is not difficult to see why the
line of cleavage has followed the line of sex, or why the female became
the emblem of the universal and the male of the special and superior. Two
gigantic facts of nature fixed it thus: first, that the woman who
frequently fulfilled her functions literally could not be specially
prominent in experiment and adventure; and second, that the same natural
operation surrounded her with very young children, who require to be
taught not so much anything as everything. Babies need not to be taught a
trade, but to be introduced to a world. To put the matter shortly, woman
is generally shut up in a house with a human being at the time when he
asks all the questions that there are, and some that there aren’t. It
would be odd if she retained any of the narrowness of a specialist. Now if
anyone says that this duty of general enlightenment (even when freed from
modern rules and hours, and exercised more spontaneously by a more
protected person) is in itself too exacting and oppressive, I can
understand the view. I can only answer that our race has thought it worth
while to cast this burden on women in order to keep common-sense in the
world. But when people begin to talk about this domestic duty as not
merely difficult but trivial and dreary, I simply give up the question.
For I cannot with the utmost energy of imagination conceive what they
mean. When domesticity, for instance, is called drudgery, all the
difficulty arises from a double meaning in the word. If drudgery only
means dreadfully hard work, I admit the woman drudges in the home, as a
man might drudge at the Cathedral of Amiens or drudge behind a gun at
Trafalgar. But if it means that the hard work is more heavy because it is
trifling, colorless and of small import to the soul, then as I say, I give
it up; I do not know what the words mean. To be Queen Elizabeth within a
definite area, deciding sales, banquets, labors and holidays; to be
Whiteley within a certain area, providing toys, boots, sheets, cakes and
books, to be Aristotle within a certain area, teaching morals, manners,
theology, and hygiene; I can understand how this might exhaust the mind,
but I cannot imagine how it could narrow it. How can it be a large career
to tell other people’s children about the Rule of Three, and a small
career to tell one’s own children about the universe? How can it be broad
to be the same thing to everyone, and narrow to be everything to someone?
No; a woman’s function is laborious, but because it is gigantic, not
because it is minute. I will pity Mrs. Jones for the hugeness of her task;
I will never pity her for its smallness.</p>
<p>But though the essential of the woman’s task is universality, this does
not, of course, prevent her from having one or two severe though largely
wholesome prejudices. She has, on the whole, been more conscious than man
that she is only one half of humanity; but she has expressed it (if one
may say so of a lady) by getting her teeth into the two or three things
which she thinks she stands for. I would observe here in parenthesis that
much of the recent official trouble about women has arisen from the fact
that they transfer to things of doubt and reason that sacred stubbornness
only proper to the primary things which a woman was set to guard. One’s
own children, one’s own altar, ought to be a matter of principle—or
if you like, a matter of prejudice. On the other hand, who wrote Junius’s
Letters ought not to be a principle or a prejudice, it ought to be a
matter of free and almost indifferent inquiry. But take an energetic
modern girl secretary to a league to show that George III wrote Junius,
and in three months she will believe it, too, out of mere loyalty to her
employers. Modern women defend their office with all the fierceness of
domesticity. They fight for desk and typewriter as for hearth and home,
and develop a sort of wolfish wifehood on behalf of the invisible head of
the firm. That is why they do office work so well; and that is why they
ought not to do it.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0022" id="link2H_4_0022"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> IV. THE ROMANCE OF THRIFT </h2>
<p>The larger part of womankind, however, have had to fight for things
slightly more intoxicating to the eye than the desk or the typewriter; and
it cannot be denied that in defending these, women have developed the
quality called prejudice to a powerful and even menacing degree. But these
prejudices will always be found to fortify the main position of the woman,
that she is to remain a general overseer, an autocrat within small compass
but on all sides. On the one or two points on which she really
misunderstands the man’s position, it is almost entirely in order to
preserve her own. The two points on which woman, actually and of herself,
is most tenacious may be roughly summarized as the ideal of thrift and the
ideal of dignity.</p>
<p>Unfortunately for this book it is written by a male, and these two
qualities, if not hateful to a man, are at least hateful in a man. But if
we are to settle the sex question at all fairly, all males must make an
imaginative attempt to enter into the attitude of all good women toward
these two things. The difficulty exists especially, perhaps, in the thing
called thrift; we men have so much encouraged each other in throwing money
right and left, that there has come at last to be a sort of chivalrous and
poetical air about losing sixpence. But on a broader and more candid
consideration the case scarcely stands so.</p>
<p>Thrift is the really romantic thing; economy is more romantic than
extravagance. Heaven knows I for one speak disinterestedly in the matter;
for I cannot clearly remember saving a half-penny ever since I was born.
But the thing is true; economy, properly understood, is the more poetic.
Thrift is poetic because it is creative; waste is unpoetic because it is
waste. It is prosaic to throw money away, because it is prosaic to throw
anything away; it is negative; it is a confession of indifference, that
is, it is a confession of failure. The most prosaic thing about the house
is the dustbin, and the one great objection to the new fastidious and
aesthetic homestead is simply that in such a moral menage the dustbin must
be bigger than the house. If a man could undertake to make use of all
things in his dustbin he would be a broader genius than Shakespeare. When
science began to use by-products; when science found that colors could be
made out of coaltar, she made her greatest and perhaps her only claim on
the real respect of the human soul. Now the aim of the good woman is to
use the by-products, or, in other words, to rummage in the dustbin.</p>
<p>A man can only fully comprehend it if he thinks of some sudden joke or
expedient got up with such materials as may be found in a private house on
a rainy day. A man’s definite daily work is generally run with such rigid
convenience of modern science that thrift, the picking up of potential
helps here and there, has almost become unmeaning to him. He comes across
it most (as I say) when he is playing some game within four walls; when in
charades, a hearthrug will just do for a fur coat, or a tea-cozy just do
for a cocked hat; when a toy theater needs timber and cardboard, and the
house has just enough firewood and just enough bandboxes. This is the
man’s occasional glimpse and pleasing parody of thrift. But many a good
housekeeper plays the same game every day with ends of cheese and scraps
of silk, not because she is mean, but on the contrary, because she is
magnanimous; because she wishes her creative mercy to be over all her
works, that not one sardine should be destroyed, or cast as rubbish to the
void, when she has made the pile complete.</p>
<p>The modern world must somehow be made to understand (in theology and other
things) that a view may be vast, broad, universal, liberal and yet come
into conflict with another view that is vast, broad, universal and liberal
also. There is never a war between two sects, but only between two
universal Catholic Churches. The only possible collision is the collision
of one cosmos with another. So in a smaller way it must be first made
clear that this female economic ideal is a part of that female variety of
outlook and all-round art of life which we have already attributed to the
sex: thrift is not a small or timid or provincial thing; it is part of
that great idea of the woman watching on all sides out of all the windows
of the soul and being answerable for everything. For in the average human
house there is one hole by which money comes in and a hundred by which it
goes out; man has to do with the one hole, woman with the hundred. But
though the very stinginess of a woman is a part of her spiritual breadth,
it is none the less true that it brings her into conflict with the special
kind of spiritual breadth that belongs to the males of the tribe. It
brings her into conflict with that shapeless cataract of Comradeship, of
chaotic feasting and deafening debate, which we noted in the last section.
The very touch of the eternal in the two sexual tastes brings them the
more into antagonism; for one stands for a universal vigilance and the
other for an almost infinite output. Partly through the nature of his
moral weakness, and partly through the nature of his physical strength,
the male is normally prone to expand things into a sort of eternity; he
always thinks of a dinner party as lasting all night; and he always thinks
of a night as lasting forever. When the working women in the poor
districts come to the doors of the public houses and try to get their
husbands home, simple minded “social workers” always imagine that every
husband is a tragic drunkard and every wife a broken-hearted saint. It
never occurs to them that the poor woman is only doing under coarser
conventions exactly what every fashionable hostess does when she tries to
get the men from arguing over the cigars to come and gossip over the
teacups. These women are not exasperated merely at the amount of money
that is wasted in beer; they are exasperated also at the amount of time
that is wasted in talk. It is not merely what goeth into the mouth but
what cometh out the mouth that, in their opinion, defileth a man. They
will raise against an argument (like their sisters of all ranks) the
ridiculous objection that nobody is convinced by it; as if a man wanted to
make a body-slave of anybody with whom he had played single-stick. But the
real female prejudice on this point is not without a basis; the real
feeling is this, that the most masculine pleasures have a quality of the
ephemeral. A duchess may ruin a duke for a diamond necklace; but there is
the necklace. A coster may ruin his wife for a pot of beer; and where is
the beer? The duchess quarrels with another duchess in order to crush her,
to produce a result; the coster does not argue with another coster in
order to convince him, but in order to enjoy at once the sound of his own
voice, the clearness of his own opinions and the sense of masculine
society. There is this element of a fine fruitlessness about the male
enjoyments; wine is poured into a bottomless bucket; thought plunges into
a bottomless abyss. All this has set woman against the Public House—that
is, against the Parliament House. She is there to prevent waste; and the
“pub” and the parliament are the very palaces of waste. In the upper
classes the “pub” is called the club, but that makes no more difference to
the reason than it does to the rhyme. High and low, the woman’s objection
to the Public House is perfectly definite and rational, it is that the
Public House wastes the energies that could be used on the private house.</p>
<p>As it is about feminine thrift against masculine waste, so it is about
feminine dignity against masculine rowdiness. The woman has a fixed and
very well-founded idea that if she does not insist on good manners nobody
else will. Babies are not always strong on the point of dignity, and
grown-up men are quite unpresentable. It is true that there are many very
polite men, but none that I ever heard of who were not either fascinating
women or obeying them. But indeed the female ideal of dignity, like the
female ideal of thrift, lies deeper and may easily be misunderstood. It
rests ultimately on a strong idea of spiritual isolation; the same that
makes women religious. They do not like being melted down; they dislike
and avoid the mob. That anonymous quality we have remarked in the club
conversation would be common impertinence in a case of ladies. I remember
an artistic and eager lady asking me in her grand green drawing-room
whether I believed in comradeship between the sexes, and why not. I was
driven back on offering the obvious and sincere answer “Because if I were
to treat you for two minutes like a comrade you would turn me out of the
house.” The only certain rule on this subject is always to deal with woman
and never with women. “Women” is a profligate word; I have used it
repeatedly in this chapter; but it always has a blackguard sound. It
smells of oriental cynicism and hedonism. Every woman is a captive queen.
But every crowd of women is only a harem broken loose.</p>
<p>I am not expressing my own views here, but those of nearly all the women I
have known. It is quite unfair to say that a woman hates other women
individually; but I think it would be quite true to say that she detests
them in a confused heap. And this is not because she despises her own sex,
but because she respects it; and respects especially that sanctity and
separation of each item which is represented in manners by the idea of
dignity and in morals by the idea of chastity.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0023" id="link2H_4_0023"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> V. THE COLDNESS OF CHLOE </h2>
<p>We hear much of the human error which accepts what is sham and what is
real. But it is worth while to remember that with unfamiliar things we
often mistake what is real for what is sham. It is true that a very young
man may think the wig of an actress is her hair. But it is equally true
that a child yet younger may call the hair of a negro his wig. Just
because the woolly savage is remote and barbaric he seems to be
unnaturally neat and tidy. Everyone must have noticed the same thing in
the fixed and almost offensive color of all unfamiliar things, tropic
birds and tropic blossoms. Tropic birds look like staring toys out of a
toy-shop. Tropic flowers simply look like artificial flowers, like things
cut out of wax. This is a deep matter, and, I think, not unconnected with
divinity; but anyhow it is the truth that when we see things for the first
time we feel instantly that they are fictive creations; we feel the finger
of God. It is only when we are thoroughly used to them and our five wits
are wearied, that we see them as wild and objectless; like the shapeless
tree-tops or the shifting cloud. It is the design in Nature that strikes
us first; the sense of the crosses and confusions in that design only
comes afterwards through experience and an almost eerie monotony. If a man
saw the stars abruptly by accident he would think them as festive and as
artificial as a firework. We talk of the folly of painting the lily; but
if we saw the lily without warning we should think that it was painted. We
talk of the devil not being so black as he is painted; but that very
phrase is a testimony to the kinship between what is called vivid and what
is called artificial. If the modern sage had only one glimpse of grass and
sky, he would say that grass was not as green as it was painted; that sky
was not as blue as it was painted. If one could see the whole universe
suddenly, it would look like a bright-colored toy, just as the South
American hornbill looks like a bright-colored toy. And so they are—both
of them, I mean.</p>
<p>But it was not with this aspect of the startling air of artifice about all
strange objects that I meant to deal. I mean merely, as a guide to
history, that we should not be surprised if things wrought in fashions
remote from ours seem artificial; we should convince ourselves that nine
times out of ten these things are nakedly and almost indecently honest.
You will hear men talk of the frosted classicism of Corneille or of the
powdered pomposities of the eighteenth century, but all these phrases are
very superficial. There never was an artificial epoch. There never was an
age of reason. Men were always men and women women: and their two generous
appetites always were the expression of passion and the telling of truth.
We can see something stiff and quaint in their mode of expression, just as
our descendants will see something stiff and quaint in our coarsest slum
sketch or our most naked pathological play. But men have never talked
about anything but important things; and the next force in femininity
which we have to consider can be considered best perhaps in some dusty old
volume of verses by a person of quality.</p>
<p>The eighteenth century is spoken of as the period of artificiality, in
externals at least; but, indeed, there may be two words about that. In
modern speech one uses artificiality as meaning indefinitely a sort of
deceit; and the eighteenth century was far too artificial to deceive. It
cultivated that completest art that does not conceal the art. Its fashions
and costumes positively revealed nature by allowing artifice; as in that
obvious instance of a barbering that frosted every head with the same
silver. It would be fantastic to call this a quaint humility that
concealed youth; but, at least, it was not one with the evil pride that
conceals old age. Under the eighteenth century fashion people did not so
much all pretend to be young, as all agree to be old. The same applies to
the most odd and unnatural of their fashions; they were freakish, but they
were not false. A lady may or may not be as red as she is painted, but
plainly she was not so black as she was patched.</p>
<p>But I only introduce the reader into this atmosphere of the older and
franker fictions that he may be induced to have patience for a moment with
a certain element which is very common in the decoration and literature of
that age and of the two centuries preceding it. It is necessary to mention
it in such a connection because it is exactly one of those things that
look as superficial as powder, and are really as rooted as hair.</p>
<p>In all the old flowery and pastoral love-songs, those of the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries especially, you will find a perpetual reproach
against woman in the matter of her coldness; ceaseless and stale similes
that compare her eyes to northern stars, her heart to ice, or her bosom to
snow. Now most of us have always supposed these old and iterant phrases to
be a mere pattern of dead words, a thing like a cold wall-paper. Yet I
think those old cavalier poets who wrote about the coldness of Chloe had
hold of a psychological truth missed in nearly all the realistic novels of
today. Our psychological romancers perpetually represent wives as striking
terror into their husbands by rolling on the floor, gnashing their teeth,
throwing about the furniture or poisoning the coffee; all this upon some
strange fixed theory that women are what they call emotional. But in truth
the old and frigid form is much nearer to the vital fact. Most men if they
spoke with any sincerity would agree that the most terrible quality in
women, whether in friendship, courtship or marriage, was not so much being
emotional as being unemotional.</p>
<p>There is an awful armor of ice which may be the legitimate protection of a
more delicate organism; but whatever be the psychological explanation
there can surely be no question of the fact. The instinctive cry of the
female in anger is noli me tangere. I take this as the most obvious and at
the same time the least hackneyed instance of a fundamental quality in the
female tradition, which has tended in our time to be almost immeasurably
misunderstood, both by the cant of moralists and the cant of immoralists.
The proper name for the thing is modesty; but as we live in an age of
prejudice and must not call things by their right names, we will yield to
a more modern nomenclature and call it dignity. Whatever else it is, it is
the thing which a thousand poets and a million lovers have called the
coldness of Chloe. It is akin to the classical, and is at least the
opposite of the grotesque. And since we are talking here chiefly in types
and symbols, perhaps as good an embodiment as any of the idea may be found
in the mere fact of a woman wearing a skirt. It is highly typical of the
rabid plagiarism which now passes everywhere for emancipation, that a
little while ago it was common for an “advanced” woman to claim the right
to wear trousers; a right about as grotesque as the right to wear a false
nose. Whether female liberty is much advanced by the act of wearing a
skirt on each leg I do not know; perhaps Turkish women might offer some
information on the point. But if the western woman walks about (as it
were) trailing the curtains of the harem with her, it is quite certain
that the woven mansion is meant for a perambulating palace, not for a
perambulating prison. It is quite certain that the skirt means female
dignity, not female submission; it can be proved by the simplest of all
tests. No ruler would deliberately dress up in the recognized fetters of a
slave; no judge would appear covered with broad arrows. But when men wish
to be safely impressive, as judges, priests or kings, they do wear skirts,
the long, trailing robes of female dignity The whole world is under
petticoat government; for even men wear petticoats when they wish to
govern.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0024" id="link2H_4_0024"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> VI. THE PEDANT AND THE SAVAGE </h2>
<p>We say then that the female holds up with two strong arms these two
pillars of civilization; we say also that she could do neither, but for
her position; her curious position of private omnipotence, universality on
a small scale. The first element is thrift; not the destructive thrift of
the miser, but the creative thrift of the peasant; the second element is
dignity, which is but the expression of sacred personality and privacy.
Now I know the question that will be abruptly and automatically asked by
all that know the dull tricks and turns of the modern sexual quarrel. The
advanced person will at once begin to argue about whether these instincts
are inherent and inevitable in woman or whether they are merely prejudices
produced by her history and education. Now I do not propose to discuss
whether woman could now be educated out of her habits touching thrift and
dignity; and that for two excellent reasons. First it is a question which
cannot conceivably ever find any answer: that is why modern people are so
fond of it. From the nature of the case it is obviously impossible to
decide whether any of the peculiarities of civilized man have been
strictly necessary to his civilization. It is not self-evident (for
instance), that even the habit of standing upright was the only path of
human progress. There might have been a quadrupedal civilization, in which
a city gentleman put on four boots to go to the city every morning. Or
there might have been a reptilian civilization, in which he rolled up to
the office on his stomach; it is impossible to say that intelligence might
not have developed in such creatures. All we can say is that man as he is
walks upright; and that woman is something almost more upright than
uprightness.</p>
<p>And the second point is this: that upon the whole we rather prefer women
(nay, even men) to walk upright; so we do not waste much of our noble
lives in inventing any other way for them to walk. In short, my second
reason for not speculating upon whether woman might get rid of these
peculiarities, is that I do not want her to get rid of them; nor does she.
I will not exhaust my intelligence by inventing ways in which mankind
might unlearn the violin or forget how to ride horses; and the art of
domesticity seems to me as special and as valuable as all the ancient arts
of our race. Nor do I propose to enter at all into those formless and
floundering speculations about how woman was or is regarded in the
primitive times that we cannot remember, or in the savage countries which
we cannot understand. Even if these people segregated their women for low
or barbaric reasons it would not make our reasons barbaric; and I am
haunted with a tenacious suspicion that these people’s feelings were
really, under other forms, very much the same as ours. Some impatient
trader, some superficial missionary, walks across an island and sees the
squaw digging in the fields while the man is playing a flute; and
immediately says that the man is a mere lord of creation and the woman a
mere serf. He does not remember that he might see the same thing in half
the back gardens in Brixton, merely because women are at once more
conscientious and more impatient, while men are at once more quiescent and
more greedy for pleasure. It may often be in Hawaii simply as it is in
Hoxton. That is, the woman does not work because the man tells her to work
and she obeys. On the contrary, the woman works because she has told the
man to work and he hasn’t obeyed. I do not affirm that this is the whole
truth, but I do affirm that we have too little comprehension of the souls
of savages to know how far it is untrue. It is the same with the relations
of our hasty and surface science, with the problem of sexual dignity and
modesty. Professors find all over the world fragmentary ceremonies in
which the bride affects some sort of reluctance, hides from her husband,
or runs away from him. The professor then pompously proclaims that this is
a survival of Marriage by Capture. I wonder he never says that the veil
thrown over the bride is really a net. I gravely doubt whether women ever
were married by capture I think they pretended to be; as they do still.</p>
<p>It is equally obvious that these two necessary sanctities of thrift and
dignity are bound to come into collision with the wordiness, the
wastefulness, and the perpetual pleasure-seeking of masculine
companionship. Wise women allow for the thing; foolish women try to crush
it; but all women try to counteract it, and they do well. In many a home
all round us at this moment, we know that the nursery rhyme is reversed.
The queen is in the counting-house, counting out the money. The king is in
the parlor, eating bread and honey. But it must be strictly understood
that the king has captured the honey in some heroic wars. The quarrel can
be found in moldering Gothic carvings and in crabbed Greek manuscripts. In
every age, in every land, in every tribe and village, has been waged the
great sexual war between the Private House and the Public House. I have
seen a collection of mediaeval English poems, divided into sections such
as “Religious Carols,” “Drinking Songs,” and so on; and the section
headed, “Poems of Domestic Life” consisted entirely (literally, entirely)
of the complaints of husbands who were bullied by their wives. Though the
English was archaic, the words were in many cases precisely the same as
those which I have heard in the streets and public houses of Battersea,
protests on behalf of an extension of time and talk, protests against the
nervous impatience and the devouring utilitarianism of the female. Such, I
say, is the quarrel; it can never be anything but a quarrel; but the aim
of all morals and all society is to keep it a lovers’ quarrel.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0025" id="link2H_4_0025"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> VII. THE MODERN SURRENDER OF WOMAN </h2>
<p>But in this corner called England, at this end of the century, there has
happened a strange and startling thing. Openly and to all appearance, this
ancestral conflict has silently and abruptly ended; one of the two sexes
has suddenly surrendered to the other. By the beginning of the twentieth
century, within the last few years, the woman has in public surrendered to
the man. She has seriously and officially owned that the man has been
right all along; that the public house (or Parliament) is really more
important than the private house; that politics are not (as woman had
always maintained) an excuse for pots of beer, but are a sacred solemnity
to which new female worshipers may kneel; that the talkative patriots in
the tavern are not only admirable but enviable; that talk is not a waste
of time, and therefore (as a consequence, surely) that taverns are not a
waste of money. All we men had grown used to our wives and mothers, and
grandmothers, and great aunts all pouring a chorus of contempt upon our
hobbies of sport, drink and party politics. And now comes Miss Pankhurst
with tears in her eyes, owning that all the women were wrong and all the
men were right; humbly imploring to be admitted into so much as an outer
court, from which she may catch a glimpse of those masculine merits which
her erring sisters had so thoughtlessly scorned.</p>
<p>Now this development naturally perturbs and even paralyzes us. Males, like
females, in the course of that old fight between the public and private
house, had indulged in overstatement and extravagance, feeling that they
must keep up their end of the see-saw. We told our wives that Parliament
had sat late on most essential business; but it never crossed our minds
that our wives would believe it. We said that everyone must have a vote in
the country; similarly our wives said that no one must have a pipe in the
drawing room. In both cases the idea was the same. “It does not matter
much, but if you let those things slide there is chaos.” We said that Lord
Huggins or Mr. Buggins was absolutely necessary to the country. We knew
quite well that nothing is necessary to the country except that the men
should be men and the women women. We knew this; we thought the women knew
it even more clearly; and we thought the women would say it. Suddenly,
without warning, the women have begun to say all the nonsense that we
ourselves hardly believed when we said it. The solemnity of politics; the
necessity of votes; the necessity of Huggins; the necessity of Buggins;
all these flow in a pellucid stream from the lips of all the suffragette
speakers. I suppose in every fight, however old, one has a vague
aspiration to conquer; but we never wanted to conquer women so completely
as this. We only expected that they might leave us a little more margin
for our nonsense; we never expected that they would accept it seriously as
sense. Therefore I am all at sea about the existing situation; I scarcely
know whether to be relieved or enraged by this substitution of the feeble
platform lecture for the forcible curtain-lecture. I am lost without the
trenchant and candid Mrs. Caudle. I really do not know what to do with the
prostrate and penitent Miss Pankhurst. This surrender of the modern woman
has taken us all so much by surprise that it is desirable to pause a
moment, and collect our wits about what she is really saying.</p>
<p>As I have already remarked, there is one very simple answer to all this;
these are not the modern women, but about one in two thousand of the
modern women. This fact is important to a democrat; but it is of very
little importance to the typically modern mind. Both the characteristic
modern parties believed in a government by the few; the only difference is
whether it is the Conservative few or Progressive few. It might be put,
somewhat coarsely perhaps, by saying that one believes in any minority
that is rich and the other in any minority that is mad. But in this state
of things the democratic argument obviously falls out for the moment; and
we are bound to take the prominent minority, merely because it is
prominent. Let us eliminate altogether from our minds the thousands of
women who detest this cause, and the millions of women who have hardly
heard of it. Let us concede that the English people itself is not and will
not be for a very long time within the sphere of practical politics. Let
us confine ourselves to saying that these particular women want a vote and
to asking themselves what a vote is. If we ask these ladies ourselves what
a vote is, we shall get a very vague reply. It is the only question, as a
rule, for which they are not prepared. For the truth is that they go
mainly by precedent; by the mere fact that men have votes already. So far
from being a mutinous movement, it is really a very Conservative one; it
is in the narrowest rut of the British Constitution. Let us take a little
wider and freer sweep of thought and ask ourselves what is the ultimate
point and meaning of this odd business called voting.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0026" id="link2H_4_0026"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> VIII. THE BRAND OF THE FLEUR-DE-LIS </h2>
<p>Seemingly from the dawn of man all nations have had governments; and all
nations have been ashamed of them. Nothing is more openly fallacious than
to fancy that in ruder or simpler ages ruling, judging and punishing
appeared perfectly innocent and dignified. These things were always
regarded as the penalties of the Fall; as part of the humiliation of
mankind, as bad in themselves. That the king can do no wrong was never
anything but a legal fiction; and it is a legal fiction still. The
doctrine of Divine Right was not a piece of idealism, but rather a piece
of realism, a practical way of ruling amid the ruin of humanity; a very
pragmatist piece of faith. The religious basis of government was not so
much that people put their trust in princes, as that they did not put
their trust in any child of man. It was so with all the ugly institutions
which disfigure human history. Torture and slavery were never talked of as
good things; they were always talked of as necessary evils. A pagan spoke
of one man owning ten slaves just as a modern business man speaks of one
merchant sacking ten clerks: “It’s very horrible; but how else can society
be conducted?” A mediaeval scholastic regarded the possibility of a man
being burned to death just as a modern business man regards the
possibility of a man being starved to death: “It is a shocking torture;
but can you organize a painless world?” It is possible that a future
society may find a way of doing without the question by hunger as we have
done without the question by fire. It is equally possible, for the matter
of that, that a future society may reestablish legal torture with the
whole apparatus of rack and fagot. The most modern of countries, America,
has introduced with a vague savor of science, a method which it calls “the
third degree.” This is simply the extortion of secrets by nervous fatigue;
which is surely uncommonly close to their extortion by bodily pain. And
this is legal and scientific in America. Amateur ordinary America, of
course, simply burns people alive in broad daylight, as they did in the
Reformation Wars. But though some punishments are more inhuman than others
there is no such thing as humane punishment. As long as nineteen men claim
the right in any sense or shape to take hold of the twentieth man and make
him even mildly uncomfortable, so long the whole proceeding must be a
humiliating one for all concerned. And the proof of how poignantly men
have always felt this lies in the fact that the headsman and the hangman,
the jailors and the torturers, were always regarded not merely with fear
but with contempt; while all kinds of careless smiters, bankrupt knights
and swashbucklers and outlaws, were regarded with indulgence or even
admiration. To kill a man lawlessly was pardoned. To kill a man lawfully
was unpardonable. The most bare-faced duelist might almost brandish his
weapon. But the executioner was always masked.</p>
<p>This is the first essential element in government, coercion; a necessary
but not a noble element. I may remark in passing that when people say that
government rests on force they give an admirable instance of the foggy and
muddled cynicism of modernity. Government does not rest on force.
Government is force; it rests on consent or a conception of justice. A
king or a community holding a certain thing to be abnormal, evil, uses the
general strength to crush it out; the strength is his tool, but the belief
is his only sanction. You might as well say that glass is the real reason
for telescopes. But arising from whatever reason the act of government is
coercive and is burdened with all the coarse and painful qualities of
coercion. And if anyone asks what is the use of insisting on the ugliness
of this task of state violence since all mankind is condemned to employ
it, I have a simple answer to that. It would be useless to insist on it if
all humanity were condemned to it. But it is not irrelevant to insist on
its ugliness so long as half of humanity is kept out of it.</p>
<p>All government then is coercive; we happen to have created a government
which is not only coercive; but collective. There are only two kinds of
government, as I have already said, the despotic and the democratic.
Aristocracy is not a government, it is a riot; that most effective kind of
riot, a riot of the rich. The most intelligent apologists of aristocracy,
sophists like Burke and Nietzsche, have never claimed for aristocracy any
virtues but the virtues of a riot, the accidental virtues, courage,
variety and adventure. There is no case anywhere of aristocracy having
established a universal and applicable order, as despots and democracies
have often done; as the last Caesars created the Roman law, as the last
Jacobins created the Code Napoleon. With the first of these elementary
forms of government, that of the king or chieftain, we are not in this
matter of the sexes immediately concerned. We shall return to it later
when we remark how differently mankind has dealt with female claims in the
despotic as against the democratic field. But for the moment the essential
point is that in self-governing countries this coercion of criminals is a
collective coercion. The abnormal person is theoretically thumped by a
million fists and kicked by a million feet. If a man is flogged we all
flogged him; if a man is hanged, we all hanged him. That is the only
possible meaning of democracy, which can give any meaning to the first two
syllables and also to the last two. In this sense each citizen has the
high responsibility of a rioter. Every statute is a declaration of war, to
be backed by arms. Every tribunal is a revolutionary tribunal. In a
republic all punishment is as sacred and solemn as lynching.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0027" id="link2H_4_0027"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> IX. SINCERITY AND THE GALLOWS </h2>
<p>When, therefore, it is said that the tradition against Female Suffrage
keeps women out of activity, social influence and citizenship, let us a
little more soberly and strictly ask ourselves what it actually does keep
her out of. It does definitely keep her out of the collective act of
coercion; the act of punishment by a mob. The human tradition does say
that, if twenty men hang a man from a tree or lamp-post, they shall be
twenty men and not women. Now I do not think any reasonable Suffragist
will deny that exclusion from this function, to say the least of it, might
be maintained to be a protection as well as a veto. No candid person will
wholly dismiss the proposition that the idea of having a Lord Chancellor
but not a Lady Chancellor may at least be connected with the idea of
having a headsman but not a headswoman, a hangman but not a hangwoman. Nor
will it be adequate to answer (as is so often answered to this contention)
that in modern civilization women would not really be required to capture,
to sentence, or to slay; that all this is done indirectly, that
specialists kill our criminals as they kill our cattle. To urge this is
not to urge the reality of the vote, but to urge its unreality. Democracy
was meant to be a more direct way of ruling, not a more indirect way; and
if we do not feel that we are all jailers, so much the worse for us, and
for the prisoners. If it is really an unwomanly thing to lock up a robber
or a tyrant, it ought to be no softening of the situation that the woman
does not feel as if she were doing the thing that she certainly is doing.
It is bad enough that men can only associate on paper who could once
associate in the street; it is bad enough that men have made a vote very
much of a fiction. It is much worse that a great class should claim the
vote be cause it is a fiction, who would be sickened by it if it were a
fact. If votes for women do not mean mobs for women they do not mean what
they were meant to mean. A woman can make a cross on a paper as well as a
man; a child could do it as well as a woman; and a chimpanzee after a few
lessons could do it as well as a child. But nobody ought to regard it
merely as making a cross on paper; everyone ought to regard it as what it
ultimately is, branding the fleur-de-lis, marking the broad arrow, signing
the death warrant. Both men and women ought to face more fully the things
they do or cause to be done; face them or leave off doing them.</p>
<p>On that disastrous day when public executions were abolished, private
executions were renewed and ratified, perhaps forever. Things grossly
unsuited to the moral sentiment of a society cannot be safely done in
broad daylight; but I see no reason why we should not still be roasting
heretics alive, in a private room. It is very likely (to speak in the
manner foolishly called Irish) that if there were public executions there
would be no executions. The old open-air punishments, the pillory and the
gibbet, at least fixed responsibility upon the law; and in actual practice
they gave the mob an opportunity of throwing roses as well as rotten eggs;
of crying “Hosannah” as well as “Crucify.” But I do not like the public
executioner being turned into the private executioner. I think it is a
crooked oriental, sinister sort of business, and smells of the harem and
the divan rather than of the forum and the market place. In modern times
the official has lost all the social honor and dignity of the common
hangman. He is only the bearer of the bowstring.</p>
<p>Here, however, I suggest a plea for a brutal publicity only in order to
emphasize the fact that it is this brutal publicity and nothing else from
which women have been excluded. I also say it to emphasize the fact that
the mere modern veiling of the brutality does not make the situation
different, unless we openly say that we are giving the suffrage, not only
because it is power but because it is not, or in other words, that women
are not so much to vote as to play voting. No suffragist, I suppose, will
take up that position; and a few suffragists will wholly deny that this
human necessity of pains and penalties is an ugly, humiliating business,
and that good motives as well as bad may have helped to keep women out of
it. More than once I have remarked in these pages that female limitations
may be the limits of a temple as well as of a prison, the disabilities of
a priest and not of a pariah. I noted it, I think, in the case of the
pontifical feminine dress. In the same way it is not evidently irrational,
if men decided that a woman, like a priest, must not be a shedder of
blood.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0028" id="link2H_4_0028"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> X. THE HIGHER ANARCHY </h2>
<p>But there is a further fact; forgotten also because we moderns forget that
there is a female point of view. The woman’s wisdom stands partly, not
only for a wholesome hesitation about punishment, but even for a wholesome
hesitation about absolute rules. There was something feminine and
perversely true in that phrase of Wilde’s, that people should not be
treated as the rule, but all of them as exceptions. Made by a man the
remark was a little effeminate; for Wilde did lack the masculine power of
dogma and of democratic cooperation. But if a woman had said it it would
have been simply true; a woman does treat each person as a peculiar
person. In other words, she stands for Anarchy; a very ancient and
arguable philosophy; not anarchy in the sense of having no customs in
one’s life (which is inconceivable), but anarchy in the sense of having no
rules for one’s mind. To her, almost certainly, are due all those working
traditions that cannot be found in books, especially those of education;
it was she who first gave a child a stuffed stocking for being good or
stood him in the corner for being naughty. This unclassified knowledge is
sometimes called rule of thumb and sometimes motherwit. The last phrase
suggests the whole truth, for none ever called it fatherwit.</p>
<p>Now anarchy is only tact when it works badly. Tact is only anarchy when it
works well. And we ought to realize that in one half of the world—the
private house—it does work well. We modern men are perpetually
forgetting that the case for clear rules and crude penalties is not
self-evident, that there is a great deal to be said for the benevolent
lawlessness of the autocrat, especially on a small scale; in short, that
government is only one side of life. The other half is called Society, in
which women are admittedly dominant. And they have always been ready to
maintain that their kingdom is better governed than ours, because (in the
logical and legal sense) it is not governed at all. “Whenever you have a
real difficulty,” they say, “when a boy is bumptious or an aunt is stingy,
when a silly girl will marry somebody, or a wicked man won’t marry
somebody, all your lumbering Roman Law and British Constitution come to a
standstill. A snub from a duchess or a slanging from a fish-wife are much
more likely to put things straight.” So, at least, rang the ancient female
challenge down the ages until the recent female capitulation. So streamed
the red standard of the higher anarchy until Miss Pankhurst hoisted the
white flag.</p>
<p>It must be remembered that the modern world has done deep treason to the
eternal intellect by believing in the swing of the pendulum. A man must be
dead before he swings. It has substituted an idea of fatalistic
alternation for the mediaeval freedom of the soul seeking truth. All
modern thinkers are reactionaries; for their thought is always a reaction
from what went before. When you meet a modern man he is always coming from
a place, not going to it. Thus, mankind has in nearly all places and
periods seen that there is a soul and a body as plainly as that there is a
sun and moon. But because a narrow Protestant sect called Materialists
declared for a short time that there was no soul, another narrow
Protestant sect called Christian Science is now maintaining that there is
no body. Now just in the same way the unreasonable neglect of government
by the Manchester School has produced, not a reasonable regard for
government, but an unreasonable neglect of everything else. So that to
hear people talk to-day one would fancy that every important human
function must be organized and avenged by law; that all education must be
state education, and all employment state employment; that everybody and
everything must be brought to the foot of the august and prehistoric
gibbet. But a somewhat more liberal and sympathetic examination of mankind
will convince us that the cross is even older than the gibbet, that
voluntary suffering was before and independent of compulsory; and in short
that in most important matters a man has always been free to ruin himself
if he chose. The huge fundamental function upon which all anthropology
turns, that of sex and childbirth, has never been inside the political
state, but always outside of it. The state concerned itself with the
trivial question of killing people, but wisely left alone the whole
business of getting them born. A Eugenist might indeed plausibly say that
the government is an absent-minded and inconsistent person who occupies
himself with providing for the old age of people who have never been
infants. I will not deal here in any detail with the fact that some
Eugenists have in our time made the maniacal answer that the police ought
to control marriage and birth as they control labor and death. Except for
this inhuman handful (with whom I regret to say I shall have to deal with
later) all the Eugenists I know divide themselves into two sections:
ingenious people who once meant this, and rather bewildered people who
swear they never meant it—nor anything else. But if it be conceded
(by a breezier estimate of men) that they do mostly desire marriage to
remain free from government, it does not follow that they desire it to
remain free from everything. If man does not control the marriage market
by law, is it controlled at all? Surely the answer is broadly that man
does not control the marriage market by law, but the woman does control it
by sympathy and prejudice. There was until lately a law forbidding a man
to marry his deceased wife’s sister; yet the thing happened constantly.
There was no law forbidding a man to marry his deceased wife’s
scullery-maid; yet it did not happen nearly so often. It did not happen
because the marriage market is managed in the spirit and by the authority
of women; and women are generally conservative where classes are
concerned. It is the same with that system of exclusiveness by which
ladies have so often contrived (as by a process of elimination) to prevent
marriages that they did not want and even sometimes procure those they
did. There is no need of the broad arrow and the fleur-de lis, the
turnkey’s chains or the hangman’s halter. You need not strangle a man if
you can silence him. The branded shoulder is less effective and final than
the cold shoulder; and you need not trouble to lock a man in when you can
lock him out.</p>
<p>The same, of course, is true of the colossal architecture which we call
infant education: an architecture reared wholly by women. Nothing can ever
overcome that one enormous sex superiority, that even the male child is
born closer to his mother than to his father. No one, staring at that
frightful female privilege, can quite believe in the equality of the
sexes. Here and there we read of a girl brought up like a tom-boy; but
every boy is brought up like a tame girl. The flesh and spirit of
femininity surround him from the first like the four walls of a house; and
even the vaguest or most brutal man has been womanized by being born. Man
that is born of a woman has short days and full of misery; but nobody can
picture the obscenity and bestial tragedy that would belong to such a
monster as man that was born of a man.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0029" id="link2H_4_0029"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> XI. THE QUEEN AND THE SUFFRAGETTES </h2>
<p>But, indeed, with this educational matter I must of necessity embroil
myself later. The fourth section of discussion is supposed to be about the
child, but I think it will be mostly about the mother. In this place I
have systematically insisted on the large part of life that is governed,
not by man with his vote, but by woman with her voice, or more often, with
her horrible silence. Only one thing remains to be added. In a sprawling
and explanatory style has been traced out the idea that government is
ultimately coercion, that coercion must mean cold definitions as well as
cruel consequences, and that therefore there is something to be said for
the old human habit of keeping one-half of humanity out of so harsh and
dirty a business. But the case is stronger still.</p>
<p>Voting is not only coercion, but collective coercion. I think Queen
Victoria would have been yet more popular and satisfying if she had never
signed a death warrant. I think Queen Elizabeth would have stood out as
more solid and splendid in history if she had not earned (among those who
happen to know her history) the nickname of Bloody Bess. I think, in
short, that the great historic woman is more herself when she is
persuasive rather than coercive. But I feel all mankind behind me when I
say that if a woman has this power it should be despotic power—not
democratic power. There is a much stronger historic argument for giving
Miss Pankhurst a throne than for giving her a vote. She might have a
crown, or at least a coronet, like so many of her supporters; for these
old powers are purely personal and therefore female. Miss Pankhurst as a
despot might be as virtuous as Queen Victoria, and she certainly would
find it difficult to be as wicked as Queen Bess, but the point is that,
good or bad, she would be irresponsible—she would not be governed by
a rule and by a ruler. There are only two ways of governing: by a rule and
by a ruler. And it is seriously true to say of a woman, in education and
domesticity, that the freedom of the autocrat appears to be necessary to
her. She is never responsible until she is irresponsible. In case this
sounds like an idle contradiction, I confidently appeal to the cold facts
of history. Almost every despotic or oligarchic state has admitted women
to its privileges. Scarcely one democratic state has ever admitted them to
its rights The reason is very simple: that something female is endangered
much more by the violence of the crowd. In short, one Pankhurst is an
exception, but a thousand Pankhursts are a nightmare, a Bacchic orgie, a
Witches Sabbath. For in all legends men have thought of women as sublime
separately but horrible in a herd.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0030" id="link2H_4_0030"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> XII. THE MODERN SLAVE </h2>
<p>Now I have only taken the test case of Female Suffrage because it is
topical and concrete; it is not of great moment for me as a political
proposal. I can quite imagine anyone substantially agreeing with my view
of woman as universalist and autocrat in a limited area; and still
thinking that she would be none the worse for a ballot paper. The real
question is whether this old ideal of woman as the great amateur is
admitted or not. There are many modern things which threaten it much more
than suffragism; notably the increase of self-supporting women, even in
the most severe or the most squalid employments. If there be something
against nature in the idea of a horde of wild women governing, there is
something truly intolerable in the idea of a herd of tame women being
governed. And there are elements in human psychology that make this
situation particularly poignant or ignominous. The ugly exactitudes of
business, the bells and clocks the fixed hours and rigid departments, were
all meant for the male: who, as a rule, can only do one thing and can only
with the greatest difficulty be induced to do that. If clerks do not try
to shirk their work, our whole great commercial system breaks down. It is
breaking down, under the inroad of women who are adopting the
unprecedented and impossible course of taking the system seriously and
doing it well. Their very efficiency is the definition of their slavery.
It is generally a very bad sign when one is trusted very much by one’s
employers. And if the evasive clerks have a look of being blackguards, the
earnest ladies are often something very like blacklegs. But the more
immediate point is that the modern working woman bears a double burden,
for she endures both the grinding officialism of the new office and the
distracting scrupulosity of the old home. Few men understand what
conscientiousness is. They understand duty, which generally means one
duty; but conscientiousness is the duty of the universalist. It is limited
by no work days or holidays; it is a lawless, limitless, devouring
decorum. If women are to be subjected to the dull rule of commerce, we
must find some way of emancipating them from the wild rule of conscience.
But I rather fancy you will find it easier to leave the conscience and
knock off the commerce. As it is, the modern clerk or secretary exhausts
herself to put one thing straight in the ledger and then goes home to put
everything straight in the house.</p>
<p>This condition (described by some as emancipated) is at least the reverse
of my ideal. I would give woman, not more rights, but more privileges.
Instead of sending her to seek such freedom as notoriously prevails in
banks and factories, I would design specially a house in which she can be
free. And with that we come to the last point of all; the point at which
we can perceive the needs of women, like the rights of men, stopped and
falsified by something which it is the object of this book to expose.</p>
<p>The Feminist (which means, I think, one who dislikes the chief feminine
characteristics) has heard my loose monologue, bursting all the time with
one pent-up protest. At this point he will break out and say, “But what
are we to do? There is modern commerce and its clerks; there is the modern
family with its unmarried daughters; specialism is expected everywhere;
female thrift and conscientiousness are demanded and supplied. What does
it matter whether we should in the abstract prefer the old human and
housekeeping woman; we might prefer the Garden of Eden. But since women
have trades they ought to have trades unions. Since women work in
factories, they ought to vote on factory-acts. If they are unmarried they
must be commercial; if they are commercial they must be political. We must
have new rules for a new world—even if it be not a better one.” I
said to a Feminist once: “The question is not whether women are good
enough for votes: it is whether votes are good enough for women.” He only
answered: “Ah, you go and say that to the women chain-makers on Cradley
Heath.”</p>
<p>Now this is the attitude which I attack. It is the huge heresy of
Precedent. It is the view that because we have got into a mess we must
grow messier to suit it; that because we have taken a wrong turn some time
ago we must go forward and not backwards; that because we have lost our
way we must lose our map also; and because we have missed our ideal, we
must forget it. “There are numbers of excellent people who do not think
votes unfeminine; and there may be enthusiasts for our beautiful modern
industry who do not think factories unfeminine.” But if these things are
unfeminine it is no answer to say that they fit into each other. I am not
satisfied with the statement that my daughter must have unwomanly powers
because she has unwomanly wrongs. Industrial soot and political printer’s
ink are two blacks which do not make a white. Most of the Feminists would
probably agree with me that womanhood is under shameful tyranny in the
shops and mills. But I want to destroy the tyranny. They want to destroy
womanhood. That is the only difference.</p>
<p>Whether we can recover the clear vision of woman as a tower with many
windows, the fixed eternal feminine from which her sons, the specialists,
go forth; whether we can preserve the tradition of a central thing which
is even more human than democracy and even more practical than politics;
whether, in word, it is possible to re-establish the family, freed from
the filthy cynicism and cruelty of the commercial epoch, I shall discuss
in the last section of this book. But meanwhile do not talk to me about
the poor chain-makers on Cradley Heath. I know all about them and what
they are doing. They are engaged in a very wide-spread and flourishing
industry of the present age. They are making chains.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_PART4" id="link2H_PART4"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> PART FOUR. EDUCATION: OR THE MISTAKE ABOUT THE CHILD </h2>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0032" id="link2H_4_0032"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> I. THE CALVINISM OF TO-DAY </h2>
<p>When I wrote a little volume on my friend Mr. Bernard Shaw, it is needless
to say that he reviewed it. I naturally felt tempted to answer and to
criticise the book from the same disinterested and impartial standpoint
from which Mr. Shaw had criticised the subject of it. I was not withheld
by any feeling that the joke was getting a little obvious; for an obvious
joke is only a successful joke; it is only the unsuccessful clowns who
comfort themselves with being subtle. The real reason why I did not answer
Mr. Shaw’s amusing attack was this: that one simple phrase in it
surrendered to me all that I have ever wanted, or could want from him to
all eternity. I told Mr. Shaw (in substance) that he was a charming and
clever fellow, but a common Calvinist. He admitted that this was true, and
there (so far as I am concerned) is an end of the matter. He said that, of
course, Calvin was quite right in holding that “if once a man is born it
is too late to damn or save him.” That is the fundamental and subterranean
secret; that is the last lie in hell.</p>
<p>The difference between Puritanism and Catholicism is not about whether
some priestly word or gesture is significant and sacred. It is about
whether any word or gesture is significant and sacred. To the Catholic
every other daily act is dramatic dedication to the service of good or of
evil. To the Calvinist no act can have that sort of solemnity, because the
person doing it has been dedicated from eternity, and is merely filling up
his time until the crack of doom. The difference is something subtler than
plum-puddings or private theatricals; the difference is that to a
Christian of my kind this short earthly life is intensely thrilling and
precious; to a Calvinist like Mr. Shaw it is confessedly automatic and
uninteresting. To me these threescore years and ten are the battle. To the
Fabian Calvinist (by his own confession) they are only a long procession
of the victors in laurels and the vanquished in chains. To me earthly life
is the drama; to him it is the epilogue. Shavians think about the embryo;
Spiritualists about the ghost; Christians about the man. It is as well to
have these things clear.</p>
<p>Now all our sociology and eugenics and the rest of it are not so much
materialist as confusedly Calvinist, they are chiefly occupied in
educating the child before he exists. The whole movement is full of a
singular depression about what one can do with the populace, combined with
a strange disembodied gayety about what may be done with posterity. These
essential Calvinists have, indeed, abolished some of the more liberal and
universal parts of Calvinism, such as the belief in an intellectual design
or an everlasting happiness. But though Mr. Shaw and his friends admit it
is a superstition that a man is judged after death, they stick to their
central doctrine, that he is judged before he is born.</p>
<p>In consequence of this atmosphere of Calvinism in the cultured world of
to-day, it is apparently necessary to begin all arguments on education
with some mention of obstetrics and the unknown world of the prenatal. All
I shall have to say, however, on heredity will be very brief, because I
shall confine myself to what is known about it, and that is very nearly
nothing. It is by no means self-evident, but it is a current modern dogma,
that nothing actually enters the body at birth except a life derived and
compounded from the parents. There is at least quite as much to be said
for the Christian theory that an element comes from God, or the Buddhist
theory that such an element comes from previous existences. But this is
not a religious work, and I must submit to those very narrow intellectual
limits which the absence of theology always imposes. Leaving the soul on
one side, let us suppose for the sake of argument that the human character
in the first case comes wholly from parents; and then let us curtly state
our knowledge rather than our ignorance.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0033" id="link2H_4_0033"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> II. THE TRIBAL TERROR </h2>
<p>Popular science, like that of Mr. Blatchford, is in this matter as mild as
old wives’ tales. Mr. Blatchford, with colossal simplicity, explained to
millions of clerks and workingmen that the mother is like a bottle of blue
beads and the father is like a bottle of yellow beads; and so the child is
like a bottle of mixed blue beads and yellow. He might just as well have
said that if the father has two legs and the mother has two legs, the
child will have four legs. Obviously it is not a question of simple
addition or simple division of a number of hard detached “qualities,” like
beads. It is an organic crisis and transformation of the most mysterious
sort; so that even if the result is unavoidable, it will still be
unexpected. It is not like blue beads mixed with yellow beads; it is like
blue mixed with yellow; the result of which is green, a totally novel and
unique experience, a new emotion. A man might live in a complete cosmos of
blue and yellow, like the “Edinburgh Review”; a man might never have seen
anything but a golden cornfield and a sapphire sky; and still he might
never have had so wild a fancy as green. If you paid a sovereign for a
bluebell; if you spilled the mustard on the blue-books; if you married a
canary to a blue baboon; there is nothing in any of these wild weddings
that contains even a hint of green. Green is not a mental combination,
like addition; it is a physical result like birth. So, apart from the fact
that nobody ever really understands parents or children either, yet even
if we could understand the parents, we could not make any conjecture about
the children. Each time the force works in a different way; each time the
constituent colors combine into a different spectacle. A girl may actually
inherit her ugliness from her mother’s good looks. A boy may actually get
his weakness from his father’s strength. Even if we admit it is really a
fate, for us it must remain a fairy tale. Considered in regard to its
causes, the Calvinists and materialists may be right or wrong; we leave
them their dreary debate. But considered in regard to its results there is
no doubt about it. The thing is always a new color; a strange star. Every
birth is as lonely as a miracle. Every child is as uninvited as a
monstrosity.</p>
<p>On all such subjects there is no science, but only a sort of ardent
ignorance; and nobody has ever been able to offer any theories of moral
heredity which justified themselves in the only scientific sense; that is
that one could calculate on them beforehand. There are six cases, say, of
a grandson having the same twitch of mouth or vice of character as his
grandfather; or perhaps there are sixteen cases, or perhaps sixty. But
there are not two cases, there is not one case, there are no cases at all,
of anybody betting half a crown that the grandfather will have a grandson
with the twitch or the vice. In short, we deal with heredity as we deal
with omens, affinities and the fulfillment of dreams. The things do
happen, and when they happen we record them; but not even a lunatic ever
reckons on them. Indeed, heredity, like dreams and omens, is a barbaric
notion; that is, not necessarily an untrue, but a dim, groping and
unsystematized notion. A civilized man feels himself a little more free
from his family. Before Christianity these tales of tribal doom occupied
the savage north; and since the Reformation and the revolt against
Christianity (which is the religion of a civilized freedom) savagery is
slowly creeping back in the form of realistic novels and problem plays.
The curse of Rougon-Macquart is as heathen and superstitious as the curse
of Ravenswood; only not so well written. But in this twilight barbaric
sense the feeling of a racial fate is not irrational, and may be allowed
like a hundred other half emotions that make life whole. The only
essential of tragedy is that one should take it lightly. But even when the
barbarian deluge rose to its highest in the madder novels of Zola (such as
that called “The Human Beast”, a gross libel on beasts as well as
humanity), even then the application of the hereditary idea to practice is
avowedly timid and fumbling. The students of heredity are savages in this
vital sense; that they stare back at marvels, but they dare not stare
forward to schemes. In practice no one is mad enough to legislate or
educate upon dogmas of physical inheritance; and even the language of the
thing is rarely used except for special modern purposes, such as the
endowment of research or the oppression of the poor.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0034" id="link2H_4_0034"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> III. THE TRICKS OF ENVIRONMENT </h2>
<p>After all the modern clatter of Calvinism, therefore, it is only with the
born child that anybody dares to deal; and the question is not eugenics
but education. Or again, to adopt that rather tiresome terminology of
popular science, it is not a question of heredity but of environment. I
will not needlessly complicate this question by urging at length that
environment also is open to some of the objections and hesitations which
paralyze the employment of heredity. I will merely suggest in passing that
even about the effect of environment modern people talk much too
cheerfully and cheaply. The idea that surroundings will mold a man is
always mixed up with the totally different idea that they will mold him in
one particular way. To take the broadest case, landscape no doubt affects
the soul; but how it affects it is quite another matter. To be born among
pine-trees might mean loving pine-trees. It might mean loathing
pine-trees. It might quite seriously mean never having seen a pine-tree.
Or it might mean any mixture of these or any degree of any of them. So
that the scientific method here lacks a little in precision. I am not
speaking without the book; on the contrary, I am speaking with the blue
book, with the guide-book and the atlas. It may be that the Highlanders
are poetical because they inhabit mountains; but are the Swiss prosaic
because they inhabit mountains? It may be the Swiss have fought for
freedom because they had hills; did the Dutch fight for freedom because
they hadn’t? Personally I should think it quite likely. Environment might
work negatively as well as positively. The Swiss may be sensible, not in
spite of their wild skyline, but be cause of their wild skyline. The
Flemings may be fantastic artists, not in spite of their dull skyline, but
because of it.</p>
<p>I only pause on this parenthesis to show that, even in matters admittedly
within its range, popular science goes a great deal too fast, and drops
enormous links of logic. Nevertheless, it remains the working reality that
what we have to deal with in the case of children is, for all practical
purposes, environment; or, to use the older word, education. When all such
deductions are made, education is at least a form of will-worship; not of
cowardly fact-worship; it deals with a department that we can control; it
does not merely darken us with the barbarian pessimism of Zola and the
heredity-hunt. We shall certainly make fools of ourselves; that is what is
meant by philosophy. But we shall not merely make beasts of ourselves;
which is the nearest popular definition for merely following the laws of
Nature and cowering under the vengeance of the flesh. Education contains
much moonshine; but not of the sort that makes mere mooncalves and idiots
the slaves of a silver magnet, the one eye of the world. In this decent
arena there are fads, but not frenzies. Doubtless we shall often find a
mare’s nest; but it will not always be the nightmare’s.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0035" id="link2H_4_0035"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> IV. THE TRUTH ABOUT EDUCATION </h2>
<p>When a man is asked to write down what he really thinks on education, a
certain gravity grips and stiffens his soul, which might be mistaken by
the superficial for disgust. If it be really true that men sickened of
sacred words and wearied of theology, if this largely unreasoning
irritation against “dogma” did arise out of some ridiculous excess of such
things among priests in the past, then I fancy we must be laying up a fine
crop of cant for our descendants to grow tired of. Probably the word
“education” will some day seem honestly as old and objectless as the word
“justification” now seems in a Puritan folio. Gibbon thought it
frightfully funny that people should have fought about the difference
between the “Homoousion” and the “Homoiousion.” The time will come when
somebody will laugh louder to think that men thundered against Sectarian
Education and also against Secular Education; that men of prominence and
position actually denounced the schools for teaching a creed and also for
not teaching a faith. The two Greek words in Gibbon look rather alike; but
they really mean quite different things. Faith and creed do not look
alike, but they mean exactly the same thing. Creed happens to be the Latin
for faith.</p>
<p>Now having read numberless newspaper articles on education, and even
written a good many of them, and having heard deafening and indeterminate
discussion going on all around me almost ever since I was born, about
whether religion was part of education, about whether hygiene was an
essential of education, about whether militarism was inconsistent with
true education, I naturally pondered much on this recurring substantive,
and I am ashamed to say that it was comparatively late in life that I saw
the main fact about it.</p>
<p>Of course, the main fact about education is that there is no such thing.
It does not exist, as theology or soldiering exist. Theology is a word
like geology, soldiering is a word like soldering; these sciences may be
healthy or no as hobbies; but they deal with stone and kettles, with
definite things. But education is not a word like geology or kettles.
Education is a word like “transmission” or “inheritance”; it is not an
object, but a method. It must mean the conveying of certain facts, views
or qualities, to the last baby born. They might be the most trivial facts
or the most preposterous views or the most offensive qualities; but if
they are handed on from one generation to another they are education.
Education is not a thing like theology, it is not an inferior or superior
thing; it is not a thing in the same category of terms. Theology and
education are to each other like a love-letter to the General Post Office.
Mr. Fagin was quite as educational as Dr. Strong; in practice probably
more educational. It is giving something—perhaps poison. Education
is tradition, and tradition (as its name implies) can be treason.</p>
<p>This first truth is frankly banal; but it is so perpetually ignored in our
political prosing that it must be made plain. A little boy in a little
house, son of a little tradesman, is taught to eat his breakfast, to take
his medicine, to love his country, to say his prayers, and to wear his
Sunday clothes. Obviously Fagin, if he found such a boy, would teach him
to drink gin, to lie, to betray his country, to blaspheme and to wear
false whiskers. But so also Mr. Salt the vegetarian would abolish the
boy’s breakfast; Mrs. Eddy would throw away his medicine; Count Tolstoi
would rebuke him for loving his country; Mr. Blatchford would stop his
prayers, and Mr. Edward Carpenter would theoretically denounce Sunday
clothes, and perhaps all clothes. I do not defend any of these advanced
views, not even Fagin’s. But I do ask what, between the lot of them, has
become of the abstract entity called education. It is not (as commonly
supposed) that the tradesman teaches education plus Christianity; Mr.
Salt, education plus vegetarianism; Fagin, education plus crime. The truth
is, that there is nothing in common at all between these teachers, except
that they teach. In short, the only thing they share is the one thing they
profess to dislike: the general idea of authority. It is quaint that
people talk of separating dogma from education. Dogma is actually the only
thing that cannot be separated from education. It is education. A teacher
who is not dogmatic is simply a teacher who is not teaching.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0036" id="link2H_4_0036"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> V. AN EVIL CRY </h2>
<p>The fashionable fallacy is that by education we can give people something
that we have not got. To hear people talk one would think it was some sort
of magic chemistry, by which, out of a laborious hotchpotch of hygienic
meals, baths, breathing exercises, fresh air and freehand drawing, we can
produce something splendid by accident; we can create what we cannot
conceive. These pages have, of course, no other general purpose than to
point out that we cannot create anything good until we have conceived it.
It is odd that these people, who in the matter of heredity are so sullenly
attached to law, in the matter of environment seem almost to believe in
miracle. They insist that nothing but what was in the bodies of the
parents can go to make the bodies of the children. But they seem somehow
to think that things can get into the heads of the children which were not
in the heads of the parents, or, indeed, anywhere else.</p>
<p>There has arisen in this connection a foolish and wicked cry typical of
the confusion. I mean the cry, “Save the children.” It is, of course, part
of that modern morbidity that insists on treating the State (which is the
home of man) as a sort of desperate expedient in time of panic. This
terrified opportunism is also the origin of the Socialist and other
schemes. Just as they would collect and share all the food as men do in a
famine, so they would divide the children from their fathers, as men do in
a shipwreck. That a human community might conceivably not be in a
condition of famine or shipwreck never seems to cross their minds. This
cry of “Save the children” has in it the hateful implication that it is
impossible to save the fathers; in other words, that many millions of
grown-up, sane, responsible and self-supporting Europeans are to be
treated as dirt or debris and swept away out of the discussion; called
dipsomaniacs because they drink in public houses instead of private
houses; called unemployables because nobody knows how to get them work;
called dullards if they still adhere to conventions, and called loafers if
they still love liberty. Now I am concerned, first and last, to maintain
that unless you can save the fathers, you cannot save the children; that
at present we cannot save others, for we cannot save ourselves. We cannot
teach citizenship if we are not citizens; we cannot free others if we have
forgotten the appetite of freedom. Education is only truth in a state of
transmission; and how can we pass on truth if it has never come into our
hand? Thus we find that education is of all the cases the clearest for our
general purpose. It is vain to save children; for they cannot remain
children. By hypothesis we are teaching them to be men; and how can it be
so simple to teach an ideal manhood to others if it is so vain and
hopeless to find one for ourselves?</p>
<p>I know that certain crazy pedants have attempted to counter this
difficulty by maintaining that education is not instruction at all, does
not teach by authority at all. They present the process as coming, not
from the outside, from the teacher, but entirely from inside the boy.
Education, they say, is the Latin for leading out or drawing out the
dormant faculties of each person. Somewhere far down in the dim boyish
soul is a primordial yearning to learn Greek accents or to wear clean
collars; and the schoolmaster only gently and tenderly liberates this
imprisoned purpose. Sealed up in the newborn babe are the intrinsic
secrets of how to eat asparagus and what was the date of Bannockburn. The
educator only draws out the child’s own unapparent love of long division;
only leads out the child’s slightly veiled preference for milk pudding to
tarts. I am not sure that I believe in the derivation; I have heard the
disgraceful suggestion that “educator,” if applied to a Roman
schoolmaster, did not mean leading our young functions into freedom; but
only meant taking out little boys for a walk. But I am much more certain
that I do not agree with the doctrine; I think it would be about as sane
to say that the baby’s milk comes from the baby as to say that the baby’s
educational merits do. There is, indeed, in each living creature a
collection of forces and functions; but education means producing these in
particular shapes and training them to particular purposes, or it means
nothing at all. Speaking is the most practical instance of the whole
situation. You may indeed “draw out” squeals and grunts from the child by
simply poking him and pulling him about, a pleasant but cruel pastime to
which many psychologists are addicted. But you will wait and watch very
patiently indeed before you draw the English language out of him. That you
have got to put into him; and there is an end of the matter.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0037" id="link2H_4_0037"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> VI. AUTHORITY THE UNAVOIDABLE </h2>
<p>But the important point here is only that you cannot anyhow get rid of
authority in education; it is not so much (as poor Conservatives say) that
parental authority ought to be preserved, as that it cannot be destroyed.
Mr. Bernard Shaw once said that he hated the idea of forming a child’s
mind. In that case Mr. Bernard Shaw had better hang himself; for he hates
something inseparable from human life. I only mentioned educere and the
drawing out of the faculties in order to point out that even this mental
trick does not avoid the inevitable idea of parental or scholastic
authority. The educator drawing out is just as arbitrary and coercive as
the instructor pouring in; for he draws out what he chooses. He decides
what in the child shall be developed and what shall not be developed. He
does not (I suppose) draw out the neglected faculty of forgery. He does
not (so far at least) lead out, with timid steps, a shy talent for
torture. The only result of all this pompous and precise distinction
between the educator and the instructor is that the instructor pokes where
he likes and the educator pulls where he likes. Exactly the same
intellectual violence is done to the creature who is poked and pulled. Now
we must all accept the responsibility of this intellectual violence.
Education is violent; because it is creative. It is creative because it is
human. It is as reckless as playing on the fiddle; as dogmatic as drawing
a picture; as brutal as building a house. In short, it is what all human
action is; it is an interference with life and growth. After that it is a
trifling and even a jocular question whether we say of this tremendous
tormentor, the artist Man, that he puts things into us like an apothecary,
or draws things out of us, like a dentist.</p>
<p>The point is that Man does what he likes. He claims the right to take his
mother Nature under his control; he claims the right to make his child the
Superman, in his image. Once flinch from this creative authority of man,
and the whole courageous raid which we call civilization wavers and falls
to pieces. Now most modern freedom is at root fear. It is not so much that
we are too bold to endure rules; it is rather that we are too timid to
endure responsibilities. And Mr. Shaw and such people are especially
shrinking from that awful and ancestral responsibility to which our
fathers committed us when they took the wild step of becoming men. I mean
the responsibility of affirming the truth of our human tradition and
handing it on with a voice of authority, an unshaken voice. That is the
one eternal education; to be sure enough that something is true that you
dare to tell it to a child. From this high audacious duty the moderns are
fleeing on every side; and the only excuse for them is, (of course,) that
their modern philosophies are so half-baked and hypothetical that they
cannot convince themselves enough to convince even a newborn babe. This,
of course, is connected with the decay of democracy; and is somewhat of a
separate subject. Suffice it to say here that when I say that we should
instruct our children, I mean that we should do it, not that Mr. Sully or
Professor Earl Barnes should do it. The trouble in too many of our modern
schools is that the State, being controlled so specially by the few,
allows cranks and experiments to go straight to the schoolroom when they
have never passed through the Parliament, the public house, the private
house, the church, or the marketplace. Obviously, it ought to be the
oldest things that are taught to the youngest people; the assured and
experienced truths that are put first to the baby. But in a school to-day
the baby has to submit to a system that is younger than himself. The
flopping infant of four actually has more experience, and has weathered
the world longer, than the dogma to which he is made to submit. Many a
school boasts of having the last ideas in education, when it has not even
the first idea; for the first idea is that even innocence, divine as it
is, may learn something from experience. But this, as I say, is all due to
the mere fact that we are managed by a little oligarchy; my system
presupposes that men who govern themselves will govern their children.
To-day we all use Popular Education as meaning education of the people. I
wish I could use it as meaning education by the people.</p>
<p>The urgent point at present is that these expansive educators do not avoid
the violence of authority an inch more than the old school masters. Nay,
it might be maintained that they avoid it less. The old village
schoolmaster beat a boy for not learning grammar and sent him out into the
playground to play anything he liked; or at nothing, if he liked that
better. The modern scientific schoolmaster pursues him into the playground
and makes him play at cricket, because exercise is so good for the health.
The modern Dr. Busby is a doctor of medicine as well as a doctor of
divinity. He may say that the good of exercise is self-evident; but he
must say it, and say it with authority. It cannot really be self-evident
or it never could have been compulsory. But this is in modern practice a
very mild case. In modern practice the free educationists forbid far more
things than the old-fashioned educationists. A person with a taste for
paradox (if any such shameless creature could exist) might with some
plausibility maintain concerning all our expansion since the failure of
Luther’s frank paganism and its replacement by Calvin’s Puritanism, that
all this expansion has not been an expansion, but the closing in of a
prison, so that less and less beautiful and humane things have been
permitted. The Puritans destroyed images; the Rationalists forbade fairy
tales. Count Tostoi practically issued one of his papal encyclicals
against music; and I have heard of modern educationists who forbid
children to play with tin soldiers. I remember a meek little madman who
came up to me at some Socialist soiree or other, and asked me to use my
influence (have I any influence?) against adventure stories for boys. It
seems they breed an appetite for blood. But never mind that; one must keep
one’s temper in this madhouse. I need only insist here that these things,
even if a just deprivation, are a deprivation. I do not deny that the old
vetoes and punishments were often idiotic and cruel; though they are much
more so in a country like England (where in practice only a rich man
decrees the punishment and only a poor man receives it) than in countries
with a clearer popular tradition—such as Russia. In Russia flogging
is often inflicted by peasants on a peasant. In modern England flogging
can only in practice be inflicted by a gentleman on a very poor man. Thus
only a few days ago as I write a small boy (a son of the poor, of course)
was sentenced to flogging and imprisonment for five years for having
picked up a small piece of coal which the experts value at 5d. I am
entirely on the side of such liberals and humanitarians as have protested
against this almost bestial ignorance about boys. But I do think it a
little unfair that these humanitarians, who excuse boys for being robbers,
should denounce them for playing at robbers. I do think that those who
understand a guttersnipe playing with a piece of coal might, by a sudden
spurt of imagination, understand him playing with a tin soldier. To sum it
up in one sentence: I think my meek little madman might have understood
that there is many a boy who would rather be flogged, and unjustly
flogged, than have his adventure story taken away.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0038" id="link2H_4_0038"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> VII. THE HUMILITY OF MRS. GRUNDY </h2>
<p>In short, the new education is as harsh as the old, whether or no it is as
high. The freest fad, as much as the strictest formula, is stiff with
authority. It is because the humane father thinks soldiers wrong that they
are forbidden; there is no pretense, there can be no pretense, that the
boy would think so. The average boy’s impression certainly would be simply
this: “If your father is a Methodist you must not play with soldiers on
Sunday. If your father is a Socialist you must not play with them even on
week days.” All educationists are utterly dogmatic and authoritarian. You
cannot have free education; for if you left a child free you would not
educate him at all. Is there, then, no distinction or difference between
the most hide-bound conventionalists and the most brilliant and bizarre
innovators? Is there no difference between the heaviest heavy father and
the most reckless and speculative maiden aunt? Yes; there is. The
difference is that the heavy father, in his heavy way, is a democrat. He
does not urge a thing merely because to his fancy it should be done; but,
because (in his own admirable republican formula) “Everybody does it.” The
conventional authority does claim some popular mandate; the unconventional
authority does not. The Puritan who forbids soldiers on Sunday is at least
expressing Puritan opinion; not merely his own opinion. He is not a
despot; he is a democracy, a tyrannical democracy, a dingy and local
democracy perhaps; but one that could do and has done the two ultimate
virile things—fight and appeal to God. But the veto of the new
educationist is like the veto of the House of Lords; it does not pretend
to be representative. These innovators are always talking about the
blushing modesty of Mrs. Grundy. I do not know whether Mrs. Grundy is more
modest than they are; but I am sure she is more humble.</p>
<p>But there is a further complication. The more anarchic modern may again
attempt to escape the dilemma by saying that education should only be an
enlargement of the mind, an opening of all the organs of receptivity.
Light (he says) should be brought into darkness; blinded and thwarted
existences in all our ugly corners should merely be permitted to perceive
and expand; in short, enlightenment should be shed over darkest London.
Now here is just the trouble; that, in so far as this is involved, there
is no darkest London. London is not dark at all; not even at night. We
have said that if education is a solid substance, then there is none of
it. We may now say that if education is an abstract expansion there is no
lack of it. There is far too much of it. In fact, there is nothing else.</p>
<p>There are no uneducated people. Everybody in England is educated; only
most people are educated wrong. The state schools were not the first
schools, but among the last schools to be established; and London had been
educating Londoners long before the London School Board. The error is a
highly practical one. It is persistently assumed that unless a child is
civilized by the established schools, he must remain a barbarian. I wish
he did. Every child in London becomes a highly civilized person. But here
are so many different civilizations, most of them born tired. Anyone will
tell you that the trouble with the poor is not so much that the old are
still foolish, but rather that the young are already wise. Without going
to school at all, the gutter-boy would be educated. Without going to
school at all, he would be over-educated. The real object of our schools
should be not so much to suggest complexity as solely to restore
simplicity. You will hear venerable idealists declare we must make war on
the ignorance of the poor; but, indeed, we have rather to make war on
their knowledge. Real educationists have to resist a kind of roaring
cataract of culture. The truant is being taught all day. If the children
do not look at the large letters in the spelling-book, they need only walk
outside and look at the large letters on the poster. If they do not care
for the colored maps provided by the school, they can gape at the colored
maps provided by the Daily Mail. If they tire of electricity, they can
take to electric trams. If they are unmoved by music, they can take to
drink. If they will not work so as to get a prize from their school, they
may work to get a prize from Prizy Bits. If they cannot learn enough about
law and citizenship to please the teacher, they learn enough about them to
avoid the policeman. If they will not learn history forwards from the
right end in the history books, they will learn it backwards from the
wrong end in the party newspapers. And this is the tragedy of the whole
affair: that the London poor, a particularly quick-witted and civilized
class, learn everything tail foremost, learn even what is right in the way
of what is wrong. They do not see the first principles of law in a law
book; they only see its last results in the police news. They do not see
the truths of politics in a general survey. They only see the lies of
politics, at a General Election.</p>
<p>But whatever be the pathos of the London poor, it has nothing to do with
being uneducated. So far from being without guidance, they are guided
constantly, earnestly, excitedly; only guided wrong. The poor are not at
all neglected, they are merely oppressed; nay, rather they are persecuted.
There are no people in London who are not appealed to by the rich; the
appeals of the rich shriek from every hoarding and shout from every
hustings. For it should always be remembered that the queer, abrupt
ugliness of our streets and costumes are not the creation of democracy,
but of aristocracy. The House of Lords objected to the Embankment being
disfigured by trams. But most of the rich men who disfigure the
street-walls with their wares are actually in the House of Lords. The
peers make the country seats beautiful by making the town streets hideous.
This, however, is parenthetical. The point is, that the poor in London are
not left alone, but rather deafened and bewildered with raucous and
despotic advice. They are not like sheep without a shepherd. They are more
like one sheep whom twenty-seven shepherds are shouting at. All the
newspapers, all the new advertisements, all the new medicines and new
theologies, all the glare and blare of the gas and brass of modern times—it
is against these that the national school must bear up if it can. I will
not question that our elementary education is better than barbaric
ignorance. But there is no barbaric ignorance. I do not doubt that our
schools would be good for uninstructed boys. But there are no uninstructed
boys. A modern London school ought not merely to be clearer, kindlier,
more clever and more rapid than ignorance and darkness. It must also be
clearer than a picture postcard, cleverer than a Limerick competition,
quicker than the tram, and kindlier than the tavern. The school, in fact,
has the responsibility of universal rivalry. We need not deny that
everywhere there is a light that must conquer darkness. But here we demand
a light that can conquer light.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0039" id="link2H_4_0039"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> VIII. THE BROKEN RAINBOW </h2>
<p>I will take one case that will serve both as symbol and example: the case
of color. We hear the realists (those sentimental fellows) talking about
the gray streets and the gray lives of the poor. But whatever the poor
streets are they are not gray; but motley, striped, spotted, piebald and
patched like a quilt. Hoxton is not aesthetic enough to be monochrome; and
there is nothing of the Celtic twilight about it. As a matter of fact, a
London gutter-boy walks unscathed among furnaces of color. Watch him walk
along a line of hoardings, and you will see him now against glowing green,
like a traveler in a tropic forest; now black like a bird against the
burning blue of the Midi; now passant across a field gules, like the
golden leopards of England. He ought to understand the irrational rapture
of that cry of Mr. Stephen Phillips about “that bluer blue, that greener
green.” There is no blue much bluer than Reckitt’s Blue and no blacking
blacker than Day and Martin’s; no more emphatic yellow than that of
Colman’s Mustard. If, despite this chaos of color, like a shattered
rainbow, the spirit of the small boy is not exactly intoxicated with art
and culture, the cause certainly does not lie in universal grayness or the
mere starving of his senses. It lies in the fact that the colors are
presented in the wrong connection, on the wrong scale, and, above all,
from the wrong motive. It is not colors he lacks, but a philosophy of
colors. In short, there is nothing wrong with Reckitt’s Blue except that
it is not Reckitt’s. Blue does not belong to Reckitt, but to the sky;
black does not belong to Day and Martin, but to the abyss. Even the finest
posters are only very little things on a very large scale. There is
something specially irritant in this way about the iteration of
advertisements of mustard: a condiment, a small luxury; a thing in its
nature not to be taken in quantity. There is a special irony in these
starving streets to see such a great deal of mustard to such very little
meat. Yellow is a bright pigment; mustard is a pungent pleasure. But to
look at these seas of yellow is to be like a man who should swallow
gallons of mustard. He would either die, or lose the taste of mustard
altogether.</p>
<p>Now suppose we compare these gigantic trivialities on the hoardings with
those tiny and tremendous pictures in which the mediaevals recorded their
dreams; little pictures where the blue sky is hardly longer than a single
sapphire, and the fires of judgment only a pigmy patch of gold. The
difference here is not merely that poster art is in its nature more hasty
than illumination art; it is not even merely that the ancient artist was
serving the Lord while the modern artist is serving the lords. It is that
the old artist contrived to convey an impression that colors really were
significant and precious things, like jewels and talismanic stones. The
color was often arbitrary; but it was always authoritative. If a bird was
blue, if a tree was golden, if a fish was silver, if a cloud was scarlet,
the artist managed to convey that these colors were important and almost
painfully intense; all the red red-hot and all the gold tried in the fire.
Now that is the spirit touching color which the schools must recover and
protect if they are really to give the children any imaginative appetite
or pleasure in the thing. It is not so much an indulgence in color; it is
rather, if anything, a sort of fiery thrift. It fenced in a green field in
heraldry as straitly as a green field in peasant proprietorship. It would
not fling away gold leaf any more than gold coin; it would not heedlessly
pour out purple or crimson, any more than it would spill good wine or shed
blameless blood. That is the hard task before educationists in this
special matter; they have to teach people to relish colors like liquors.
They have the heavy business of turning drunkards into wine tasters. If
even the twentieth century succeeds in doing these things, it will almost
catch up with the twelfth.</p>
<p>The principle covers, however, the whole of modern life. Morris and the
merely aesthetic mediaevalists always indicated that a crowd in the time
of Chaucer would have been brightly clad and glittering, compared with a
crowd in the time of Queen Victoria. I am not so sure that the real
distinction is here. There would be brown frocks of friars in the first
scene as well as brown bowlers of clerks in the second. There would be
purple plumes of factory girls in the second scene as well as purple
lenten vestments in the first. There would be white waistcoats against
white ermine; gold watch chains against gold lions. The real difference is
this: that the brown earth-color of the monk’s coat was instinctively
chosen to express labor and humility, whereas the brown color of the
clerk’s hat was not chosen to express anything. The monk did mean to say
that he robed himself in dust. I am sure the clerk does not mean to say
that he crowns himself with clay. He is not putting dust on his head, as
the only diadem of man. Purple, at once rich and somber, does suggest a
triumph temporarily eclipsed by a tragedy. But the factory girl does not
intend her hat to express a triumph temporarily eclipsed by a tragedy; far
from it. White ermine was meant to express moral purity; white waistcoats
were not. Gold lions do suggest a flaming magnanimity; gold watch chains
do not. The point is not that we have lost the material hues, but that we
have lost the trick of turning them to the best advantage. We are not like
children who have lost their paint box and are left alone with a gray
lead-pencil. We are like children who have mixed all the colors in the
paint-box together and lost the paper of instructions. Even then (I do not
deny) one has some fun.</p>
<p>Now this abundance of colors and loss of a color scheme is a pretty
perfect parable of all that is wrong with our modern ideals and especially
with our modern education. It is the same with ethical education, economic
education, every sort of education. The growing London child will find no
lack of highly controversial teachers who will teach him that geography
means painting the map red; that economics means taxing the foreigner,
that patriotism means the peculiarly un-English habit of flying a flag on
Empire Day. In mentioning these examples specially I do not mean to imply
that there are no similar crudities and popular fallacies upon the other
political side. I mention them because they constitute a very special and
arresting feature of the situation. I mean this, that there were always
Radical revolutionists; but now there are Tory revolutionists also. The
modern Conservative no longer conserves. He is avowedly an innovator. Thus
all the current defenses of the House of Lords which describe it as a
bulwark against the mob, are intellectually done for; the bottom has
fallen out of them; because on five or six of the most turbulent topics of
the day, the House of Lords is a mob itself; and exceedingly likely to
behave like one.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0040" id="link2H_4_0040"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> IX. THE NEED FOR NARROWNESS </h2>
<p>Through all this chaos, then we come back once more to our main
conclusion. The true task of culture to-day is not a task of expansion,
but very decidedly of selection—and rejection. The educationist must
find a creed and teach it. Even if it be not a theological creed, it must
still be as fastidious and as firm as theology. In short, it must be
orthodox. The teacher may think it antiquated to have to decide precisely
between the faith of Calvin and of Laud, the faith of Aquinas and of
Swedenborg; but he still has to choose between the faith of Kipling and of
Shaw, between the world of Blatchford and of General Booth. Call it, if
you will, a narrow question whether your child shall be brought up by the
vicar or the minister or the popish priest. You have still to face that
larger, more liberal, more highly civilized question, of whether he shall
be brought up by Harmsworth or by Pearson, by Mr. Eustace Miles with his
Simple Life or Mr. Peter Keary with his Strenuous Life; whether he shall
most eagerly read Miss Annie S. Swan or Mr. Bart Kennedy; in short,
whether he shall end up in the mere violence of the S. D. F., or in the
mere vulgarity of the Primrose League. They say that nowadays the creeds
are crumbling; I doubt it, but at least the sects are increasing; and
education must now be sectarian education, merely for practical purposes.
Out of all this throng of theories it must somehow select a theory; out of
all these thundering voices it must manage to hear a voice; out of all
this awful and aching battle of blinding lights, without one shadow to
give shape to them, it must manage somehow to trace and to track a star.</p>
<p>I have spoken so far of popular education, which began too vague and vast
and which therefore has accomplished little. But as it happens there is in
England something to compare it with. There is an institution, or class of
institutions, which began with the same popular object, which has since
followed a much narrower object, but which had the great advantage that it
did follow some object, unlike our modern elementary schools.</p>
<p>In all these problems I should urge the solution which is positive, or, as
silly people say, “optimistic.” I should set my face, that is, against
most of the solutions that are solely negative and abolitionist. Most
educators of the poor seem to think that they have to teach the poor man
not to drink. I should be quite content if they teach him to drink; for it
is mere ignorance about how to drink and when to drink that is accountable
for most of his tragedies. I do not propose (like some of my revolutionary
friends) that we should abolish the public schools. I propose the much
more lurid and desperate experiment that we should make them public. I do
not wish to make Parliament stop working, but rather to make it work; not
to shut up churches, but rather to open them; not to put out the lamp of
learning or destroy the hedge of property, but only to make some rude
effort to make universities fairly universal and property decently proper.</p>
<p>In many cases, let it be remembered, such action is not merely going back
to the old ideal, but is even going back to the old reality. It would be a
great step forward for the gin shop to go back to the inn. It is
incontrovertibly true that to mediaevalize the public schools would be to
democratize the public schools. Parliament did once really mean (as its
name seems to imply) a place where people were allowed to talk. It is only
lately that the general increase of efficiency, that is, of the Speaker,
has made it mostly a place where people are prevented from talking. The
poor do not go to the modern church, but they went to the ancient church
all right; and if the common man in the past had a grave respect for
property, it may conceivably have been because he sometimes had some of
his own. I therefore can claim that I have no vulgar itch of innovation in
anything I say about any of these institutions. Certainly I have none in
that particular one which I am now obliged to pick out of the list; a type
of institution to which I have genuine and personal reasons for being
friendly and grateful: I mean the great Tudor foundations, the public
schools of England. They have been praised for a great many things,
mostly, I am sorry to say, praised by themselves and their children. And
yet for some reason no one has ever praised them the one really convincing
reason.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0041" id="link2H_4_0041"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> X. THE CASE FOR THE PUBLIC SCHOOLS </h2>
<p>The word success can of course be used in two senses. It may be used with
reference to a thing serving its immediate and peculiar purpose, as of a
wheel going around; or it can be used with reference to a thing adding to
the general welfare, as of a wheel being a useful discovery. It is one
thing to say that Smith’s flying machine is a failure, and quite another
to say that Smith has failed to make a flying machine. Now this is very
broadly the difference between the old English public schools and the new
democratic schools. Perhaps the old public schools are (as I personally
think they are) ultimately weakening the country rather than strengthening
it, and are therefore, in that ultimate sense, inefficient. But there is
such a thing as being efficiently inefficient. You can make your flying
ship so that it flies, even if you also make it so that it kills you. Now
the public school system may not work satisfactorily, but it works; the
public schools may not achieve what we want, but they achieve what they
want. The popular elementary schools do not in that sense achieve anything
at all. It is very difficult to point to any guttersnipe in the street and
say that he embodies the ideal for which popular education has been
working, in the sense that the fresh-faced, foolish boy in “Etons” does
embody the ideal for which the headmasters of Harrow and Winchester have
been working. The aristocratic educationists have the positive purpose of
turning out gentlemen, and they do turn out gentlemen, even when they
expel them. The popular educationists would say that they had the far
nobler idea of turning out citizens. I concede that it is a much nobler
idea, but where are the citizens? I know that the boy in “Etons” is stiff
with a rather silly and sentimental stoicism, called being a man of the
world. I do not fancy that the errand-boy is rigid with that republican
stoicism that is called being a citizen. The schoolboy will really say
with fresh and innocent hauteur, “I am an English gentleman.” I cannot so
easily picture the errand-boy drawing up his head to the stars and
answering, “Romanus civis sum.” Let it be granted that our elementary
teachers are teaching the very broadest code of morals, while our great
headmasters are teaching only the narrowest code of manners. Let it be
granted that both these things are being taught. But only one of them is
being learned.</p>
<p>It is always said that great reformers or masters of events can manage to
bring about some specific and practical reforms, but that they never
fulfill their visions or satisfy their souls. I believe there is a real
sense in which this apparent platitude is quite untrue. By a strange
inversion the political idealist often does not get what he asks for, but
does get what he wants. The silent pressure of his ideal lasts much longer
and reshapes the world much more than the actualities by which he
attempted to suggest it. What perishes is the letter, which he thought so
practical. What endures is the spirit, which he felt to be unattainable
and even unutterable. It is exactly his schemes that are not fulfilled; it
is exactly his vision that is fulfilled. Thus the ten or twelve paper
constitutions of the French Revolution, which seemed so business-like to
the framers of them, seem to us to have flown away on the wind as the
wildest fancies. What has not flown away, what is a fixed fact in Europe,
is the ideal and vision. The Republic, the idea of a land full of mere
citizens all with some minimum of manners and minimum of wealth, the
vision of the eighteenth century, the reality of the twentieth. So I think
it will generally be with the creator of social things, desirable or
undesirable. All his schemes will fail, all his tools break in his hands.
His compromises will collapse, his concessions will be useless. He must
brace himself to bear his fate; he shall have nothing but his heart’s
desire.</p>
<p>Now if one may compare very small things with very great, one may say that
the English aristocratic schools can claim something of the same sort of
success and solid splendor as the French democratic politics. At least
they can claim the same sort of superiority over the distracted and
fumbling attempts of modern England to establish democratic education.
Such success as has attended the public schoolboy throughout the Empire, a
success exaggerated indeed by himself, but still positive and a fact of a
certain indisputable shape and size, has been due to the central and
supreme circumstance that the managers of our public schools did know what
sort of boy they liked. They wanted something and they got something;
instead of going to work in the broad-minded manner and wanting everything
and getting nothing.</p>
<p>The only thing in question is the quality of the thing they got. There is
something highly maddening in the circumstance that when modern people
attack an institution that really does demand reform, they always attack
it for the wrong reasons. Thus many opponents of our public schools,
imagining themselves to be very democratic, have exhausted themselves in
an unmeaning attack upon the study of Greek. I can understand how Greek
may be regarded as useless, especially by those thirsting to throw
themselves into the cut throat commerce which is the negation of
citizenship; but I do not understand how it can be considered
undemocratic. I quite understand why Mr. Carnegie has a hatred of Greek.
It is obscurely founded on the firm and sound impression that in any
self-governing Greek city he would have been killed. But I cannot
comprehend why any chance democrat, say Mr. Quelch, or Mr. Will Crooks, I
or Mr. John M. Robertson, should be opposed to people learning the Greek
alphabet, which was the alphabet of liberty. Why should Radicals dislike
Greek? In that language is written all the earliest and, Heaven knows, the
most heroic history of the Radical party. Why should Greek disgust a
democrat, when the very word democrat is Greek?</p>
<p>A similar mistake, though a less serious one, is merely attacking the
athletics of public schools as something promoting animalism and
brutality. Now brutality, in the only immoral sense, is not a vice of the
English public schools. There is much moral bullying, owing to the general
lack of moral courage in the public-school atmosphere. These schools do,
upon the whole, encourage physical courage; but they do not merely
discourage moral courage, they forbid it. The ultimate result of the thing
is seen in the egregious English officer who cannot even endure to wear a
bright uniform except when it is blurred and hidden in the smoke of
battle. This, like all the affectations of our present plutocracy, is an
entirely modern thing. It was unknown to the old aristocrats. The Black
Prince would certainly have asked that any knight who had the courage to
lift his crest among his enemies, should also have the courage to lift it
among his friends. As regards moral courage, then it is not so much that
the public schools support it feebly, as that they suppress it firmly. But
physical courage they do, on the whole, support; and physical courage is a
magnificent fundamental. The one great, wise Englishman of the eighteenth
century said truly that if a man lost that virtue he could never be sure
of keeping any other. Now it is one of the mean and morbid modern lies
that physical courage is connected with cruelty. The Tolstoian and
Kiplingite are nowhere more at one than in maintaining this. They have, I
believe, some small sectarian quarrel with each other, the one saying that
courage must be abandoned because it is connected with cruelty, and the
other maintaining that cruelty is charming because it is a part of
courage. But it is all, thank God, a lie. An energy and boldness of body
may make a man stupid or reckless or dull or drunk or hungry, but it does
not make him spiteful. And we may admit heartily (without joining in that
perpetual praise which public-school men are always pouring upon
themselves) that this does operate to the removal of mere evil cruelty in
the public schools. English public school life is extremely like English
public life, for which it is the preparatory school. It is like it
specially in this, that things are either very open, common and
conventional, or else are very secret indeed. Now there is cruelty in
public schools, just as there is kleptomania and secret drinking and vices
without a name. But these things do not flourish in the full daylight and
common consciousness of the school, and no more does cruelty. A tiny trio
of sullen-looking boys gather in corners and seem to have some ugly
business always; it may be indecent literature, it may be the beginning of
drink, it may occasionally be cruelty to little boys. But on this stage
the bully is not a braggart. The proverb says that bullies are always
cowardly, but these bullies are more than cowardly; they are shy.</p>
<p>As a third instance of the wrong form of revolt against the public
schools, I may mention the habit of using the word aristocracy with a
double implication. To put the plain truth as briefly as possible, if
aristocracy means rule by a rich ring, England has aristocracy and the
English public schools support it. If it means rule by ancient families or
flawless blood, England has not got aristocracy, and the public schools
systematically destroy it. In these circles real aristocracy, like real
democracy, has become bad form. A modern fashionable host dare not praise
his ancestry; it would so often be an insult to half the other oligarchs
at table, who have no ancestry. We have said he has not the moral courage
to wear his uniform; still less has he the moral courage to wear his
coat-of-arms. The whole thing now is only a vague hotch-potch of nice and
nasty gentlemen. The nice gentleman never refers to anyone else’s father,
the nasty gentleman never refers to his own. That is the only difference,
the rest is the public-school manner. But Eton and Harrow have to be
aristocratic because they consist so largely of parvenues. The public
school is not a sort of refuge for aristocrats, like an asylum, a place
where they go in and never come out. It is a factory for aristocrats; they
come out without ever having perceptibly gone in. The poor little private
schools, in their old-world, sentimental, feudal style, used to stick up a
notice, “For the Sons of Gentlemen only.” If the public schools stuck up a
notice it ought to be inscribed, “For the Fathers of Gentlemen only.” In
two generations they can do the trick.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0042" id="link2H_4_0042"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> XI. THE SCHOOL FOR HYPOCRITES </h2>
<p>These are the false accusations; the accusation of classicism, the
accusation of cruelty, and the accusation of an exclusiveness based on
perfection of pedigree. English public-school boys are not pedants, they
are not torturers; and they are not, in the vast majority of cases, people
fiercely proud of their ancestry, or even people with any ancestry to be
proud of. They are taught to be courteous, to be good tempered, to be
brave in a bodily sense, to be clean in a bodily sense; they are generally
kind to animals, generally civil to servants, and to anyone in any sense
their equal, the jolliest companions on earth. Is there then anything
wrong in the public-school ideal? I think we all feel there is something
very wrong in it, but a blinding network of newspaper phraseology obscures
and entangles us; so that it is hard to trace to its beginning, beyond all
words and phrases, the faults in this great English achievement.</p>
<p>Surely, when all is said, the ultimate objection to the English public
school is its utterly blatant and indecent disregard of the duty of
telling the truth. I know there does still linger among maiden ladies in
remote country houses a notion that English schoolboys are taught to tell
the truth, but it cannot be maintained seriously for a moment. Very
occasionally, very vaguely, English schoolboys are told not to tell lies,
which is a totally different thing. I may silently support all the obscene
fictions and forgeries in the universe, without once telling a lie. I may
wear another man’s coat, steal another man’s wit, apostatize to another
man’s creed, or poison another man’s coffee, all without ever telling a
lie. But no English school-boy is ever taught to tell the truth, for the
very simple reason that he is never taught to desire the truth. From the
very first he is taught to be totally careless about whether a fact is a
fact; he is taught to care only whether the fact can be used on his “side”
when he is engaged in “playing the game.” He takes sides in his Union
debating society to settle whether Charles I ought to have been killed,
with the same solemn and pompous frivolity with which he takes sides in
the cricket field to decide whether Rugby or Westminster shall win. He is
never allowed to admit the abstract notion of the truth, that the match is
a matter of what may happen, but that Charles I is a matter of what did
happen—or did not. He is Liberal or Tory at the general election
exactly as he is Oxford or Cambridge at the boat race. He knows that sport
deals with the unknown; he has not even a notion that politics should deal
with the known. If anyone really doubts this self-evident proposition,
that the public schools definitely discourage the love of truth, there is
one fact which I should think would settle him. England is the country of
the Party System, and it has always been chiefly run by public-school men.
Is there anyone out of Hanwell who will maintain that the Party System,
whatever its conveniences or inconveniences, could have been created by
people particularly fond of truth?</p>
<p>The very English happiness on this point is itself a hypocrisy. When a man
really tells the truth, the first truth he tells is that he himself is a
liar. David said in his haste, that is, in his honesty, that all men are
liars. It was afterwards, in some leisurely official explanation, that he
said the Kings of Israel at least told the truth. When Lord Curzon was
Viceroy he delivered a moral lecture to the Indians on their reputed
indifference to veracity, to actuality and intellectual honor. A great
many people indignantly discussed whether orientals deserved to receive
this rebuke; whether Indians were indeed in a position to receive such
severe admonition. No one seemed to ask, as I should venture to ask,
whether Lord Curzon was in a position to give it. He is an ordinary party
politician; a party politician means a politician who might have belonged
to either party. Being such a person, he must again and again, at every
twist and turn of party strategy, either have deceived others or grossly
deceived himself. I do not know the East; nor do I like what I know. I am
quite ready to believe that when Lord Curzon went out he found a very
false atmosphere. I only say it must have been something startlingly and
chokingly false if it was falser than that English atmosphere from which
he came. The English Parliament actually cares for everything except
veracity. The public-school man is kind, courageous, polite, clean,
companionable; but, in the most awful sense of the words, the truth is not
in him.</p>
<p>This weakness of untruthfulness in the English public schools, in the
English political system, and to some extent in the English character, is
a weakness which necessarily produces a curious crop of superstitions, of
lying legends, of evident delusions clung to through low spiritual
self-indulgence. There are so many of these public-school superstitions
that I have here only space for one of them, which may be called the
superstition of soap. It appears to have been shared by the ablutionary
Pharisees, who resembled the English public-school aristocrats in so many
respects: in their care about club rules and traditions, in their
offensive optimism at the expense of other people, and above all in their
unimaginative plodding patriotism in the worst interests of their country.
Now the old human common sense about washing is that it is a great
pleasure. Water (applied externally) is a splendid thing, like wine.
Sybarites bathe in wine, and Nonconformists drink water; but we are not
concerned with these frantic exceptions. Washing being a pleasure, it
stands to reason that rich people can afford it more than poor people, and
as long as this was recognized all was well; and it was very right that
rich people should offer baths to poor people, as they might offer any
other agreeable thing—a drink or a donkey ride. But one dreadful
day, somewhere about the middle of the nineteenth century, somebody
discovered (somebody pretty well off) the two great modern truths, that
washing is a virtue in the rich and therefore a duty in the poor. For a
duty is a virtue that one can’t do. And a virtue is generally a duty that
one can do quite easily; like the bodily cleanliness of the upper classes.
But in the public-school tradition of public life, soap has become
creditable simply because it is pleasant. Baths are represented as a part
of the decay of the Roman Empire; but the same baths are represented as
part of the energy and rejuvenation of the British Empire. There are
distinguished public school men, bishops, dons, headmasters, and high
politicians, who, in the course of the eulogies which from time to time
they pass upon themselves, have actually identified physical cleanliness
with moral purity. They say (if I remember rightly) that a public-school
man is clean inside and out. As if everyone did not know that while saints
can afford to be dirty, seducers have to be clean. As if everyone did not
know that the harlot must be clean, because it is her business to
captivate, while the good wife may be dirty, because it is her business to
clean. As if we did not all know that whenever God’s thunder cracks above
us, it is very likely indeed to find the simplest man in a muck cart and
the most complex blackguard in a bath.</p>
<p>There are other instances, of course, of this oily trick of turning the
pleasures of a gentleman into the virtues of an Anglo-Saxon. Sport, like
soap, is an admirable thing, but, like soap, it is an agreeable thing. And
it does not sum up all mortal merits to be a sportsman playing the game in
a world where it is so often necessary to be a workman doing the work. By
all means let a gentleman congratulate himself that he has not lost his
natural love of pleasure, as against the blase, and unchildlike. But when
one has the childlike joy it is best to have also the childlike
unconsciousness; and I do not think we should have special affection for
the little boy who ever lastingly explained that it was his duty to play
Hide and Seek and one of his family virtues to be prominent in Puss in the
Corner.</p>
<p>Another such irritating hypocrisy is the oligarchic attitude towards
mendicity as against organized charity. Here again, as in the case of
cleanliness and of athletics, the attitude would be perfectly human and
intelligible if it were not maintained as a merit. Just as the obvious
thing about soap is that it is a convenience, so the obvious thing about
beggars is that they are an inconvenience. The rich would deserve very
little blame if they simply said that they never dealt directly with
beggars, because in modern urban civilization it is impossible to deal
directly with beggars; or if not impossible, at least very difficult. But
these people do not refuse money to beggars on the ground that such
charity is difficult. They refuse it on the grossly hypocritical ground
that such charity is easy. They say, with the most grotesque gravity,
“Anyone can put his hand in his pocket and give a poor man a penny; but
we, philanthropists, go home and brood and travail over the poor man’s
troubles until we have discovered exactly what jail, reformatory,
workhouse, or lunatic asylum it will really be best for him to go to.”
This is all sheer lying. They do not brood about the man when they get
home, and if they did it would not alter the original fact that their
motive for discouraging beggars is the perfectly rational one that beggars
are a bother. A man may easily be forgiven for not doing this or that
incidental act of charity, especially when the question is as genuinely
difficult as is the case of mendicity. But there is something quite
pestilently Pecksniffian about shrinking from a hard task on the plea that
it is not hard enough. If any man will really try talking to the ten
beggars who come to his door he will soon find out whether it is really so
much easier than the labor of writing a check for a hospital.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0043" id="link2H_4_0043"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> XII. THE STALENESS OF THE NEW SCHOOLS </h2>
<p>For this deep and disabling reason therefore, its cynical and abandoned
indifference to the truth, the English public school does not provide us
with the ideal that we require. We can only ask its modern critics to
remember that right or wrong the thing can be done; the factory is
working, the wheels are going around, the gentlemen are being produced,
with their soap, cricket and organized charity all complete. And in this,
as we have said before, the public school really has an advantage over all
the other educational schemes of our time. You can pick out a
public-school man in any of the many companies into which they stray, from
a Chinese opium den to a German Jewish dinner-party. But I doubt if you
could tell which little match girl had been brought up by undenominational
religion and which by secular education. The great English aristocracy
which has ruled us since the Reformation is really, in this sense, a model
to the moderns. It did have an ideal, and therefore it has produced a
reality.</p>
<p>We may repeat here that these pages propose mainly to show one thing: that
progress ought to be based on principle, while our modern progress is
mostly based on precedent. We go, not by what may be affirmed in theory,
but by what has been already admitted in practice. That is why the
Jacobites are the last Tories in history with whom a high-spirited person
can have much sympathy. They wanted a specific thing; they were ready to
go forward for it, and so they were also ready to go back for it. But
modern Tories have only the dullness of defending situations that they had
not the excitement of creating. Revolutionists make a reform,
Conservatives only conserve the reform. They never reform the reform,
which is often very much wanted. Just as the rivalry of armaments is only
a sort of sulky plagiarism, so the rivalry of parties is only a sort of
sulky inheritance. Men have votes, so women must soon have votes; poor
children are taught by force, so they must soon be fed by force; the
police shut public houses by twelve o’clock, so soon they must shut them
by eleven o’clock; children stop at school till they are fourteen, so soon
they will stop till they are forty. No gleam of reason, no momentary
return to first principles, no abstract asking of any obvious question,
can interrupt this mad and monotonous gallop of mere progress by
precedent. It is a good way to prevent real revolution. By this logic of
events, the Radical gets as much into a rut as the Conservative. We meet
one hoary old lunatic who says his grandfather told him to stand by one
stile. We meet another hoary old lunatic who says his grandfather told him
only to walk along one lane.</p>
<p>I say we may repeat here this primary part of the argument, because we
have just now come to the place where it is most startlingly and strongly
shown. The final proof that our elementary schools have no definite ideal
of their own is the fact that they so openly imitate the ideals of the
public schools. In the elementary schools we have all the ethical
prejudices and exaggerations of Eton and Harrow carefully copied for
people to whom they do not even roughly apply. We have the same wildly
disproportionate doctrine of the effect of physical cleanliness on moral
character. Educators and educational politicians declare, amid warm
cheers, that cleanliness is far more important than all the squabbles
about moral and religious training. It would really seem that so long as a
little boy washes his hands it does not matter whether he is washing off
his mother’s jam or his brother’s gore. We have the same grossly insincere
pretense that sport always encourages a sense of honor, when we know that
it often ruins it. Above all, we have the same great upperclass assumption
that things are done best by large institutions handling large sums of
money and ordering everybody about; and that trivial and impulsive charity
is in some way contemptible. As Mr. Blatchford says, “The world does not
want piety, but soap—and Socialism.” Piety is one of the popular
virtues, whereas soap and Socialism are two hobbies of the upper middle
class.</p>
<p>These “healthy" ideals, as they are called, which our politicians and
schoolmasters have borrowed from the aristocratic schools and applied to
the democratic, are by no means particularly appropriate to an
impoverished democracy. A vague admiration for organized government and a
vague distrust of individual aid cannot be made to fit in at all into the
lives of people among whom kindness means lending a saucepan and honor
means keeping out of the workhouse. It resolves itself either into
discouraging that system of prompt and patchwork generosity which is a
daily glory of the poor, or else into hazy advice to people who have no
money not to give it recklessly away. Nor is the exaggerated glory of
athletics, defensible enough in dealing with the rich who, if they did not
romp and race, would eat and drink unwholesomely, by any means so much to
the point when applied to people, most of whom will take a great deal of
exercise anyhow, with spade or hammer, pickax or saw. And for the third
case, of washing, it is obvious that the same sort of rhetoric about
corporeal daintiness which is proper to an ornamental class cannot, merely
as it stands, be applicable to a dustman. A gentleman is expected to be
substantially spotless all the time. But it is no more discreditable for a
scavenger to be dirty than for a deep-sea diver to be wet. A sweep is no
more disgraced when he is covered with soot than Michael Angelo when he is
covered with clay, or Bayard when he is covered with blood. Nor have these
extenders of the public-school tradition done or suggested anything by way
of a substitute for the present snobbish system which makes cleanliness
almost impossible to the poor; I mean the general ritual of linen and the
wearing of the cast-off clothes of the rich. One man moves into another
man’s clothes as he moves into another man’s house. No wonder that our
educationists are not horrified at a man picking up the aristocrat’s
second-hand trousers, when they themselves have only taken up the
aristocrat’s second-hand ideas.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0044" id="link2H_4_0044"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> XIII. THE OUTLAWED PARENT </h2>
<p>There is one thing at least of which there is never so much as a whisper
inside the popular schools; and that is the opinion of the people. The
only persons who seem to have nothing to do with the education of the
children are the parents. Yet the English poor have very definite
traditions in many ways. They are hidden under embarrassment and irony;
and those psychologists who have disentangled them talk of them as very
strange, barbaric and secretive things. But, as a matter of fact, the
traditions of the poor are mostly simply the traditions of humanity, a
thing which many of us have not seen for some time. For instance,
workingmen have a tradition that if one is talking about a vile thing it
is better to talk of it in coarse language; one is the less likely to be
seduced into excusing it. But mankind had this tradition also, until the
Puritans and their children, the Ibsenites, started the opposite idea,
that it does not matter what you say so long as you say it with long words
and a long face. Or again, the educated classes have tabooed most jesting
about personal appearance; but in doing this they taboo not only the humor
of the slums, but more than half the healthy literature of the world; they
put polite nose-bags on the noses of Punch and Bardolph, Stiggins and
Cyrano de Bergerac. Again, the educated classes have adopted a hideous and
heathen custom of considering death as too dreadful to talk about, and
letting it remain a secret for each person, like some private
malformation. The poor, on the contrary, make a great gossip and display
about bereavement; and they are right. They have hold of a truth of
psychology which is at the back of all the funeral customs of the children
of men. The way to lessen sorrow is to make a lot of it. The way to endure
a painful crisis is to insist very much that it is a crisis; to permit
people who must feel sad at least to feel important. In this the poor are
simply the priests of the universal civilization; and in their stuffy
feasts and solemn chattering there is the smell of the baked meats of
Hamlet and the dust and echo of the funeral games of Patroclus.</p>
<p>The things philanthropists barely excuse (or do not excuse) in the life of
the laboring classes are simply the things we have to excuse in all the
greatest monuments of man. It may be that the laborer is as gross as
Shakespeare or as garrulous as Homer; that if he is religious he talks
nearly as much about hell as Dante; that if he is worldly he talks nearly
as much about drink as Dickens. Nor is the poor man without historic
support if he thinks less of that ceremonial washing which Christ
dismissed, and rather more of that ceremonial drinking which Christ
specially sanctified. The only difference between the poor man of to-day
and the saints and heroes of history is that which in all classes
separates the common man who can feel things from the great man who can
express them. What he feels is merely the heritage of man. Now nobody
expects of course that the cabmen and coal-heavers can be complete
instructors of their children any more than the squires and colonels and
tea merchants are complete instructors of their children. There must be an
educational specialist in loco parentis. But the master at Harrow is in
loco parentis; the master in Hoxton is rather contra parentem. The vague
politics of the squire, the vaguer virtues of the colonel, the soul and
spiritual yearnings of a tea merchant, are, in veritable practice,
conveyed to the children of these people at the English public schools.
But I wish here to ask a very plain and emphatic question. Can anyone
alive even pretend to point out any way in which these special virtues and
traditions of the poor are reproduced in the education of the poor? I do
not wish the coster’s irony to appeal as coarsely in the school as it does
in the tap room; but does it appear at all? Is the child taught to
sympathize at all with his father’s admirable cheerfulness and slang? I do
not expect the pathetic, eager pietas of the mother, with her funeral
clothes and funeral baked meats, to be exactly imitated in the educational
system; but has it any influence at all on the educational system? Does
any elementary schoolmaster accord it even an instant’s consideration or
respect? I do not expect the schoolmaster to hate hospitals and C.O.S.
centers so much as the schoolboy’s father; but does he hate them at all?
Does he sympathize in the least with the poor man’s point of honor against
official institutions? Is it not quite certain that the ordinary
elementary schoolmaster will think it not merely natural but simply
conscientious to eradicate all these rugged legends of a laborious people,
and on principle to preach soap and Socialism against beer and liberty? In
the lower classes the school master does not work for the parent, but
against the parent. Modern education means handing down the customs of the
minority, and rooting out the customs of the majority. Instead of their
Christlike charity, their Shakespearean laughter and their high Homeric
reverence for the dead, the poor have imposed on them mere pedantic copies
of the prejudices of the remote rich. They must think a bathroom a
necessity because to the lucky it is a luxury; they must swing Swedish
clubs because their masters are afraid of English cudgels; and they must
get over their prejudice against being fed by the parish, because
aristocrats feel no shame about being fed by the nation.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0045" id="link2H_4_0045"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> XIV. FOLLY AND FEMALE EDUCATION </h2>
<p>It is the same in the case of girls. I am often solemnly asked what I
think of the new ideas about female education. But there are no new ideas
about female education. There is not, there never has been, even the
vestige of a new idea. All the educational reformers did was to ask what
was being done to boys and then go and do it to girls; just as they asked
what was being taught to young squires and then taught it to young chimney
sweeps. What they call new ideas are very old ideas in the wrong place.
Boys play football, why shouldn’t girls play football; boys have school
colors, why shouldn’t girls have school-colors; boys go in hundreds to
day-schools, why shouldn’t girls go in hundreds to day-schools; boys go to
Oxford, why shouldn’t girls go to Oxford—in short, boys grow
mustaches, why shouldn’t girls grow mustaches—that is about their
notion of a new idea. There is no brain-work in the thing at all; no root
query of what sex is, of whether it alters this or that, and why, anymore
than there is any imaginative grip of the humor and heart of the populace
in the popular education. There is nothing but plodding, elaborate,
elephantine imitation. And just as in the case of elementary teaching, the
cases are of a cold and reckless inappropriateness. Even a savage could
see that bodily things, at least, which are good for a man are very likely
to be bad for a woman. Yet there is no boy’s game, however brutal, which
these mild lunatics have not promoted among girls. To take a stronger
case, they give girls very heavy home-work; never reflecting that all
girls have home-work already in their homes. It is all a part of the same
silly subjugation; there must be a hard stick-up collar round the neck of
a woman, because it is already a nuisance round the neck of a man. Though
a Saxon serf, if he wore that collar of cardboard, would ask for his
collar of brass.</p>
<p>It will then be answered, not without a sneer, “And what would you prefer?
Would you go back to the elegant early Victorian female, with ringlets and
smelling-bottle, doing a little in water colors, dabbling a little in
Italian, playing a little on the harp, writing in vulgar albums and
painting on senseless screens? Do you prefer that?” To which I answer,
“Emphatically, yes.” I solidly prefer it to the new female education, for
this reason, that I can see in it an intellectual design, while there is
none in the other. I am by no means sure that even in point of practical
fact that elegant female would not have been more than a match for most of
the inelegant females. I fancy Jane Austen was stronger, sharper and
shrewder than Charlotte Bronte; I am quite certain she was stronger,
sharper and shrewder than George Eliot. She could do one thing neither of
them could do: she could coolly and sensibly describe a man. I am not sure
that the old great lady who could only smatter Italian was not more
vigorous than the new great lady who can only stammer American; nor am I
certain that the bygone duchesses who were scarcely successful when they
painted Melrose Abbey, were so much more weak-minded than the modern
duchesses who paint only their own faces, and are bad at that. But that is
not the point. What was the theory, what was the idea, in their old, weak
water-colors and their shaky Italian? The idea was the same which in a
ruder rank expressed itself in home-made wines and hereditary recipes; and
which still, in a thousand unexpected ways, can be found clinging to the
women of the poor. It was the idea I urged in the second part of this
book: that the world must keep one great amateur, lest we all become
artists and perish. Somebody must renounce all specialist conquests, that
she may conquer all the conquerors. That she may be a queen of life, she
must not be a private soldier in it. I do not think the elegant female
with her bad Italian was a perfect product, any more than I think the slum
woman talking gin and funerals is a perfect product; alas! there are few
perfect products. But they come from a comprehensible idea; and the new
woman comes from nothing and nowhere. It is right to have an ideal, it is
right to have the right ideal, and these two have the right ideal. The
slum mother with her funerals is the degenerate daughter of Antigone, the
obstinate priestess of the household gods. The lady talking bad Italian
was the decayed tenth cousin of Portia, the great and golden Italian lady,
the Renascence amateur of life, who could be a barrister because she could
be anything. Sunken and neglected in the sea of modern monotony and
imitation, the types hold tightly to their original truths. Antigone,
ugly, dirty and often drunken, will still bury her father. The elegant
female, vapid and fading away to nothing, still feels faintly the
fundamental difference between herself and her husband: that he must be
Something in the City, that she may be everything in the country.</p>
<p>There was a time when you and I and all of us were all very close to God;
so that even now the color of a pebble (or a paint), the smell of a flower
(or a firework), comes to our hearts with a kind of authority and
certainty; as if they were fragments of a muddled message, or features of
a forgotten face. To pour that fiery simplicity upon the whole of life is
the only real aim of education; and closest to the child comes the woman—she
understands. To say what she understands is beyond me; save only this,
that it is not a solemnity. Rather it is a towering levity, an uproarious
amateurishness of the universe, such as we felt when we were little, and
would as soon sing as garden, as soon paint as run. To smatter the tongues
of men and angels, to dabble in the dreadful sciences, to juggle with
pillars and pyramids and toss up the planets like balls, this is that
inner audacity and indifference which the human soul, like a conjurer
catching oranges, must keep up forever. This is that insanely frivolous
thing we call sanity. And the elegant female, drooping her ringlets over
her water-colors, knew it and acted on it. She was juggling with frantic
and flaming suns. She was maintaining the bold equilibrium of
inferiorities which is the most mysterious of superiorities and perhaps
the most unattainable. She was maintaining the prime truth of woman, the
universal mother: that if a thing is worth doing, it is worth doing badly.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_PART5" id="link2H_PART5"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> PART FIVE. THE HOME OF MAN </h2>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0047" id="link2H_4_0047"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> I. THE EMPIRE OF THE INSECT </h2>
<p>A cultivated Conservative friend of mine once exhibited great distress
because in a gay moment I once called Edmund Burke an atheist. I need
scarcely say that the remark lacked something of biographical precision;
it was meant to. Burke was certainly not an atheist in his conscious
cosmic theory, though he had not a special and flaming faith in God, like
Robespierre. Nevertheless, the remark had reference to a truth which it is
here relevant to repeat. I mean that in the quarrel over the French
Revolution, Burke did stand for the atheistic attitude and mode of
argument, as Robespierre stood for the theistic. The Revolution appealed
to the idea of an abstract and eternal justice, beyond all local custom or
convenience. If there are commands of God, then there must be rights of
man. Here Burke made his brilliant diversion; he did not attack the
Robespierre doctrine with the old mediaeval doctrine of jus divinum
(which, like the Robespierre doctrine, was theistic), he attacked it with
the modern argument of scientific relativity; in short, the argument of
evolution. He suggested that humanity was everywhere molded by or fitted
to its environment and institutions; in fact, that each people practically
got, not only the tyrant it deserved, but the tyrant it ought to have. “I
know nothing of the rights of men,” he said, “but I know something of the
rights of Englishmen.” There you have the essential atheist. His argument
is that we have got some protection by natural accident and growth; and
why should we profess to think beyond it, for all the world as if we were
the images of God! We are born under a House of Lords, as birds under a
house of leaves; we live under a monarchy as niggers live under a tropic
sun; it is not their fault if they are slaves, and it is not ours if we
are snobs. Thus, long before Darwin struck his great blow at democracy,
the essential of the Darwinian argument had been already urged against the
French Revolution. Man, said Burke in effect, must adapt himself to
everything, like an animal; he must not try to alter everything, like an
angel. The last weak cry of the pious, pretty, half-artificial optimism
and deism of the eighteenth century came in the voice of Sterne, saying,
“God tempers the wind to the shorn lamb.” And Burke, the iron
evolutionist, essentially answered, “No; God tempers the shorn lamb to the
wind.” It is the lamb that has to adapt himself. That is, he either dies
or becomes a particular kind of lamb who likes standing in a draught.</p>
<p>The subconscious popular instinct against Darwinism was not a mere offense
at the grotesque notion of visiting one’s grandfather in a cage in the
Regent’s Park. Men go in for drink, practical jokes and many other
grotesque things; they do not much mind making beasts of themselves, and
would not much mind having beasts made of their forefathers. The real
instinct was much deeper and much more valuable. It was this: that when
once one begins to think of man as a shifting and alterable thing, it is
always easy for the strong and crafty to twist him into new shapes for all
kinds of unnatural purposes. The popular instinct sees in such
developments the possibility of backs bowed and hunch-backed for their
burden, or limbs twisted for their task. It has a very well-grounded guess
that whatever is done swiftly and systematically will mostly be done by a
successful class and almost solely in their interests. It has therefore a
vision of inhuman hybrids and half-human experiments much in the style of
Mr. Wells’s “Island of Dr. Moreau.” The rich man may come to breeding a
tribe of dwarfs to be his jockeys, and a tribe of giants to be his
hall-porters. Grooms might be born bow-legged and tailors born
cross-legged; perfumers might have long, large noses and a crouching
attitude, like hounds of scent; and professional wine-tasters might have
the horrible expression of one tasting wine stamped upon their faces as
infants. Whatever wild image one employs it cannot keep pace with the
panic of the human fancy, when once it supposes that the fixed type called
man could be changed. If some millionaire wanted arms, some porter must
grow ten arms like an octopus; if he wants legs, some messenger-boy must
go with a hundred trotting legs like a centipede. In the distorted mirror
of hypothesis, that is, of the unknown, men can dimly see such monstrous
and evil shapes; men run all to eye, or all to fingers, with nothing left
but one nostril or one ear. That is the nightmare with which the mere
notion of adaptation threatens us. That is the nightmare that is not so
very far from the reality.</p>
<p>It will be said that not the wildest evolutionist really asks that we
should become in any way unhuman or copy any other animal. Pardon me, that
is exactly what not merely the wildest evolutionists urge, but some of the
tamest evolutionists too. There has risen high in recent history an
important cultus which bids fair to be the religion of the future—which
means the religion of those few weak-minded people who live in the future.
It is typical of our time that it has to look for its god through a
microscope; and our time has marked a definite adoration of the insect.
Like most things we call new, of course, it is not at all new as an idea;
it is only new as an idolatry. Virgil takes bees seriously but I doubt if
he would have kept bees as carefully as he wrote about them. The wise king
told the sluggard to watch the ant, a charming occupation—for a
sluggard. But in our own time has appeared a very different tone, and more
than one great man, as well as numberless intelligent men, have in our
time seriously suggested that we should study the insect because we are
his inferiors. The old moralists merely took the virtues of man and
distributed them quite decoratively and arbitrarily among the animals. The
ant was an almost heraldic symbol of industry, as the lion was of courage,
or, for the matter of that, the pelican of charity. But if the mediaevals
had been convinced that a lion was not courageous, they would have dropped
the lion and kept the courage; if the pelican is not charitable, they
would say, so much the worse for the pelican. The old moralists, I say,
permitted the ant to enforce and typify man’s morality; they never allowed
the ant to upset it. They used the ant for industry as the lark for
punctuality; they looked up at the flapping birds and down at the crawling
insects for a homely lesson. But we have lived to see a sect that does not
look down at the insects, but looks up at the insects, that asks us
essentially to bow down and worship beetles, like ancient Egyptians.</p>
<p>Maurice Maeterlinck is a man of unmistakable genius, and genius always
carries a magnifying glass. In the terrible crystal of his lens we have
seen the bees not as a little yellow swarm, but rather in golden armies
and hierarchies of warriors and queens. Imagination perpetually peers and
creeps further down the avenues and vistas in the tubes of science, and
one fancies every frantic reversal of proportions; the earwig striding
across the echoing plain like an elephant, or the grasshopper coming
roaring above our roofs like a vast aeroplane, as he leaps from
Hertfordshire to Surrey. One seems to enter in a dream a temple of
enormous entomology, whose architecture is based on something wilder than
arms or backbones; in which the ribbed columns have the half-crawling look
of dim and monstrous caterpillars; or the dome is a starry spider hung
horribly in the void. There is one of the modern works of engineering that
gives one something of this nameless fear of the exaggerations of an
underworld; and that is the curious curved architecture of the under
ground railway, commonly called the Twopenny Tube. Those squat archways,
without any upright line or pillar, look as if they had been tunneled by
huge worms who have never learned to lift their heads. It is the very
underground palace of the Serpent, the spirit of changing shape and color,
that is the enemy of man.</p>
<p>But it is not merely by such strange aesthetic suggestions that writers
like Maeterlinck have influenced us in the matter; there is also an
ethical side to the business. The upshot of M. Maeterlinck’s book on bees
is an admiration, one might also say an envy, of their collective
spirituality; of the fact that they live only for something which he calls
the Soul of the Hive. And this admiration for the communal morality of
insects is expressed in many other modern writers in various quarters and
shapes; in Mr. Benjamin Kidd’s theory of living only for the evolutionary
future of our race, and in the great interest of some Socialists in ants,
which they generally prefer to bees, I suppose, because they are not so
brightly colored. Not least among the hundred evidences of this vague
insectolatry are the floods of flattery poured by modern people on that
energetic nation of the Far East of which it has been said that
“Patriotism is its only religion”; or, in other words, that it lives only
for the Soul of the Hive. When at long intervals of the centuries
Christendom grows weak, morbid or skeptical, and mysterious Asia begins to
move against us her dim populations and to pour them westward like a dark
movement of matter, in such cases it has been very common to compare the
invasion to a plague of lice or incessant armies of locusts. The Eastern
armies were indeed like insects; in their blind, busy destructiveness, in
their black nihilism of personal outlook, in their hateful indifference to
individual life and love, in their base belief in mere numbers, in their
pessimistic courage and their atheistic patriotism, the riders and raiders
of the East are indeed like all the creeping things of the earth. But
never before, I think, have Christians called a Turk a locust and meant it
as a compliment. Now for the first time we worship as well as fear; and
trace with adoration that enormous form advancing vast and vague out of
Asia, faintly discernible amid the mystic clouds of winged creatures hung
over the wasted lands, thronging the skies like thunder and discoloring
the skies like rain; Beelzebub, the Lord of Flies.</p>
<p>In resisting this horrible theory of the Soul of the Hive, we of
Christendom stand not for ourselves, but for all humanity; for the
essential and distinctive human idea that one good and happy man is an end
in himself, that a soul is worth saving. Nay, for those who like such
biological fancies it might well be said that we stand as chiefs and
champions of a whole section of nature, princes of the house whose
cognizance is the backbone, standing for the milk of the individual mother
and the courage of the wandering cub, representing the pathetic chivalry
of the dog, the humor and perversity of cats, the affection of the
tranquil horse, the loneliness of the lion. It is more to the point,
however, to urge that this mere glorification of society as it is in the
social insects is a transformation and a dissolution in one of the
outlines which have been specially the symbols of man. In the cloud and
confusion of the flies and bees is growing fainter and fainter, as is
finally disappearing, the idea of the human family. The hive has become
larger than the house, the bees are destroying their captors; what the
locust hath left, the caterpillar hath eaten; and the little house and
garden of our friend Jones is in a bad way.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0048" id="link2H_4_0048"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> II. THE FALLACY OF THE UMBRELLA STAND </h2>
<p>When Lord Morley said that the House of Lords must be either mended or
ended, he used a phrase which has caused some confusion; because it might
seem to suggest that mending and ending are somewhat similar things. I
wish specially to insist on the fact that mending and ending are opposite
things. You mend a thing because you like it; you end a thing because you
don’t. To mend is to strengthen. I, for instance, disbelieve in oligarchy;
so I would no more mend the House of Lords than I would mend a thumbscrew.
On the other hand, I do believe in the family; therefore I would mend the
family as I would mend a chair; and I will never deny for a moment that
the modern family is a chair that wants mending. But here comes in the
essential point about the mass of modern advanced sociologists. Here are
two institutions that have always been fundamental with mankind, the
family and the state. Anarchists, I believe, disbelieve in both. It is
quite unfair to say that Socialists believe in the state, but do not
believe in the family; thousands of Socialists believe more in the family
than any Tory. But it is true to say that while anarchists would end both,
Socialists are specially engaged in mending (that is, strengthening and
renewing) the state; and they are not specially engaged in strengthening
and renewing the family. They are not doing anything to define the
functions of father, mother, and child, as such; they are not tightening
the machine up again; they are not blackening in again the fading lines of
the old drawing. With the state they are doing this; they are sharpening
its machinery, they are blackening in its black dogmatic lines, they are
making mere government in every way stronger and in some ways harsher than
before. While they leave the home in ruins, they restore the hive,
especially the stings. Indeed, some schemes of labor and Poor Law reform
recently advanced by distinguished Socialists, amount to little more than
putting the largest number of people in the despotic power of Mr. Bumble.
Apparently, progress means being moved on—by the police.</p>
<p>The point it is my purpose to urge might perhaps be suggested thus: that
Socialists and most social reformers of their color are vividly conscious
of the line between the kind of things that belong to the state and the
kind of things that belong to mere chaos or uncoercible nature; they may
force children to go to school before the sun rises, but they will not try
to force the sun to rise; they will not, like Canute, banish the sea, but
only the sea-bathers. But inside the outline of the state their lines are
confused, and entities melt into each other. They have no firm instinctive
sense of one thing being in its nature private and another public, of one
thing being necessarily bond and another free. That is why piece by piece,
and quite silently, personal liberty is being stolen from Englishmen, as
personal land has been silently stolen ever since the sixteenth century.</p>
<p>I can only put it sufficiently curtly in a careless simile. A Socialist
means a man who thinks a walking-stick like an umbrella because they both
go into the umbrella-stand. Yet they are as different as a battle-ax and a
bootjack. The essential idea of an umbrella is breadth and protection. The
essential idea of a stick is slenderness and, partly, attack. The stick is
the sword, the umbrella is the shield, but it is a shield against another
and more nameless enemy—the hostile but anonymous universe. More
properly, therefore, the umbrella is the roof; it is a kind of collapsible
house. But the vital difference goes far deeper than this; it branches off
into two kingdoms of man’s mind, with a chasm between. For the point is
this: that the umbrella is a shield against an enemy so actual as to be a
mere nuisance; whereas the stick is a sword against enemies so entirely
imaginary as to be a pure pleasure. The stick is not merely a sword, but a
court sword; it is a thing of purely ceremonial swagger. One cannot
express the emotion in any way except by saying that a man feels more like
a man with a stick in his hand, just as he feels more like a man with a
sword at his side. But nobody ever had any swelling sentiments about an
umbrella; it is a convenience, like a door scraper. An umbrella is a
necessary evil. A walking-stick is a quite unnecessary good. This, I
fancy, is the real explanation of the perpetual losing of umbrellas; one
does not hear of people losing walking sticks. For a walking-stick is a
pleasure, a piece of real personal property; it is missed even when it is
not needed. When my right hand forgets its stick may it forget its
cunning. But anybody may forget an umbrella, as anybody might forget a
shed that he has stood up in out of the rain. Anybody can forget a
necessary thing.</p>
<p>If I might pursue the figure of speech, I might briefly say that the whole
Collectivist error consists in saying that because two men can share an
umbrella, therefore two men can share a walking-stick. Umbrellas might
possibly be replaced by some kind of common awnings covering certain
streets from particular showers. But there is nothing but nonsense in the
notion of swinging a communal stick; it is as if one spoke of twirling a
communal mustache. It will be said that this is a frank fantasia and that
no sociologists suggest such follies. Pardon me if they do. I will give a
precise parallel to the case of confusion of sticks and umbrellas, a
parallel from a perpetually reiterated suggestion of reform. At least
sixty Socialists out of a hundred, when they have spoken of common
laundries, will go on at once to speak of common kitchens. This is just as
mechanical and unintelligent as the fanciful case I have quoted. Sticks
and umbrellas are both stiff rods that go into holes in a stand in the
hall. Kitchens and washhouses are both large rooms full of heat and damp
and steam. But the soul and function of the two things are utterly
opposite. There is only one way of washing a shirt; that is, there is only
one right way. There is no taste and fancy in tattered shirts. Nobody
says, “Tompkins likes five holes in his shirt, but I must say, give me the
good old four holes.” Nobody says, “This washerwoman rips up the left leg
of my pyjamas; now if there is one thing I insist on it is the right leg
ripped up.” The ideal washing is simply to send a thing back washed. But
it is by no means true that the ideal cooking is simply to send a thing
back cooked. Cooking is an art; it has in it personality, and even
perversity, for the definition of an art is that which must be personal
and may be perverse. I know a man, not otherwise dainty, who cannot touch
common sausages unless they are almost burned to a coal. He wants his
sausages fried to rags, yet he does not insist on his shirts being boiled
to rags. I do not say that such points of culinary delicacy are of high
importance. I do not say that the communal ideal must give way to them.
What I say is that the communal ideal is not conscious of their existence,
and therefore goes wrong from the very start, mixing a wholly public thing
with a highly individual one. Perhaps we ought to accept communal kitchens
in the social crisis, just as we should accept communal cat’s-meat in a
siege. But the cultured Socialist, quite at his ease, by no means in a
siege, talks about communal kitchens as if they were the same kind of
thing as communal laundries. This shows at the start that he
misunderstands human nature. It is as different as three men singing the
same chorus from three men playing three tunes on the same piano.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0049" id="link2H_4_0049"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> III. THE DREADFUL DUTY OF GUDGE </h2>
<p>In the quarrel earlier alluded to between the energetic Progressive and
the obstinate Conservative (or, to talk a tenderer language, between Hudge
and Gudge), the state of cross-purposes is at the present moment acute.
The Tory says he wants to preserve family life in Cindertown; the
Socialist very reasonably points out to him that in Cindertown at present
there isn’t any family life to preserve. But Hudge, the Socialist, in his
turn, is highly vague and mysterious about whether he would preserve the
family life if there were any; or whether he will try to restore it where
it has disappeared. It is all very confusing. The Tory sometimes talks as
if he wanted to tighten the domestic bonds that do not exist; the
Socialist as if he wanted to loosen the bonds that do not bind anybody.
The question we all want to ask of both of them is the original ideal
question, “Do you want to keep the family at all?” If Hudge, the
Socialist, does want the family he must be prepared for the natural
restraints, distinctions and divisions of labor in the family. He must
brace himself up to bear the idea of the woman having a preference for the
private house and a man for the public house. He must manage to endure
somehow the idea of a woman being womanly, which does not mean soft and
yielding, but handy, thrifty, rather hard, and very humorous. He must
confront without a quiver the notion of a child who shall be childish,
that is, full of energy, but without an idea of independence;
fundamentally as eager for authority as for information and butter-scotch.
If a man, a woman and a child live together any more in free and sovereign
households, these ancient relations will recur; and Hudge must put up with
it. He can only avoid it by destroying the family, driving both sexes into
sexless hives and hordes, and bringing up all children as the children of
the state—like Oliver Twist. But if these stern words must be
addressed to Hudge, neither shall Gudge escape a somewhat severe
admonition. For the plain truth to be told pretty sharply to the Tory is
this, that if he wants the family to remain, if he wants to be strong
enough to resist the rending forces of our essentially savage commerce, he
must make some very big sacrifices and try to equalize property. The
overwhelming mass of the English people at this particular instant are
simply too poor to be domestic. They are as domestic as they can manage;
they are much more domestic than the governing class; but they cannot get
what good there was originally meant to be in this institution, simply
because they have not got enough money. The man ought to stand for a
certain magnanimity, quite lawfully expressed in throwing money away: but
if under given circumstances he can only do it by throwing the week’s food
away, then he is not magnanimous, but mean. The woman ought to stand for a
certain wisdom which is well expressed in valuing things rightly and
guarding money sensibly; but how is she to guard money if there is no
money to guard? The child ought to look on his mother as a fountain of
natural fun and poetry; but how can he unless the fountain, like other
fountains, is allowed to play? What chance have any of these ancient arts
and functions in a house so hideously topsy-turvy; a house where the woman
is out working and the man isn’t; and the child is forced by law to think
his schoolmaster’s requirements more important than his mother’s? No,
Gudge and his friends in the House of Lords and the Carlton Club must make
up their minds on this matter, and that very quickly. If they are content
to have England turned into a beehive and an ant-hill, decorated here and
there with a few faded butterflies playing at an old game called
domesticity in the intervals of the divorce court, then let them have
their empire of insects; they will find plenty of Socialists who will give
it to them. But if they want a domestic England, they must “shell out,” as
the phrase goes, to a vastly greater extent than any Radical politician
has yet dared to suggest; they must endure burdens much heavier than the
Budget and strokes much deadlier than the death duties; for the thing to
be done is nothing more nor less than the distribution of the great
fortunes and the great estates. We can now only avoid Socialism by a
change as vast as Socialism. If we are to save property, we must
distribute property, almost as sternly and sweepingly as did the French
Revolution. If we are to preserve the family we must revolutionize the
nation.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0050" id="link2H_4_0050"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> IV. A LAST INSTANCE </h2>
<p>And now, as this book is drawing to a close, I will whisper in the
reader’s ear a horrible suspicion that has sometimes haunted me: the
suspicion that Hudge and Gudge are secretly in partnership. That the
quarrel they keep up in public is very much of a put-up job, and that the
way in which they perpetually play into each other’s hands is not an
everlasting coincidence. Gudge, the plutocrat, wants an anarchic
industrialism; Hudge, the idealist, provides him with lyric praises of
anarchy. Gudge wants women-workers because they are cheaper; Hudge calls
the woman’s work “freedom to live her own life.” Gudge wants steady and
obedient workmen, Hudge preaches teetotalism—to workmen, not to
Gudge—Gudge wants a tame and timid population who will never take
arms against tyranny; Hudge proves from Tolstoi that nobody must take arms
against anything. Gudge is naturally a healthy and well-washed gentleman;
Hudge earnestly preaches the perfection of Gudge’s washing to people who
can’t practice it. Above all, Gudge rules by a coarse and cruel system of
sacking and sweating and bi-sexual toil which is totally inconsistent with
the free family and which is bound to destroy it; therefore Hudge,
stretching out his arms to the universe with a prophetic smile, tells us
that the family is something that we shall soon gloriously outgrow.</p>
<p>I do not know whether the partnership of Hudge and Gudge is conscious or
unconscious. I only know that between them they still keep the common man
homeless. I only know I still meet Jones walking the streets in the gray
twilight, looking sadly at the poles and barriers and low red goblin
lanterns which still guard the house which is none the less his because he
has never been in it.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0051" id="link2H_4_0051"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> V. CONCLUSION </h2>
<p>Here, it may be said, my book ends just where it ought to begin. I have
said that the strong centers of modern English property must swiftly or
slowly be broken up, if even the idea of property is to remain among
Englishmen. There are two ways in which it could be done, a cold
administration by quite detached officials, which is called Collectivism,
or a personal distribution, so as to produce what is called Peasant
Proprietorship. I think the latter solution the finer and more fully
human, because it makes each man as somebody blamed somebody for saying of
the Pope, a sort of small god. A man on his own turf tastes eternity or,
in other words, will give ten minutes more work than is required. But I
believe I am justified in shutting the door on this vista of argument,
instead of opening it. For this book is not designed to prove the case for
Peasant Proprietorship, but to prove the case against modern sages who
turn reform to a routine. The whole of this book has been a rambling and
elaborate urging of one purely ethical fact. And if by any chance it
should happen that there are still some who do not quite see what that
point is, I will end with one plain parable, which is none the worse for
being also a fact.</p>
<p>A little while ago certain doctors and other persons permitted by modern
law to dictate to their shabbier fellow-citizens, sent out an order that
all little girls should have their hair cut short. I mean, of course, all
little girls whose parents were poor. Many very unhealthy habits are
common among rich little girls, but it will be long before any doctors
interfere forcibly with them. Now, the case for this particular
interference was this, that the poor are pressed down from above into such
stinking and suffocating underworlds of squalor, that poor people must not
be allowed to have hair, because in their case it must mean lice in the
hair. Therefore, the doctors propose to abolish the hair. It never seems
to have occurred to them to abolish the lice. Yet it could be done. As is
common in most modern discussions the unmentionable thing is the pivot of
the whole discussion. It is obvious to any Christian man (that is, to any
man with a free soul) that any coercion applied to a cabman’s daughter
ought, if possible, to be applied to a Cabinet Minister’s daughter. I will
not ask why the doctors do not, as a matter of fact apply their rule to a
Cabinet Minister’s daughter. I will not ask, because I know. They do not
because they dare not. But what is the excuse they would urge, what is the
plausible argument they would use, for thus cutting and clipping poor
children and not rich? Their argument would be that the disease is more
likely to be in the hair of poor people than of rich. And why? Because the
poor children are forced (against all the instincts of the highly domestic
working classes) to crowd together in close rooms under a wildly
inefficient system of public instruction; and because in one out of the
forty children there may be offense. And why? Because the poor man is so
ground down by the great rents of the great ground landlords that his wife
often has to work as well as he. Therefore she has no time to look after
the children, therefore one in forty of them is dirty. Because the
workingman has these two persons on top of him, the landlord sitting
(literally) on his stomach, and the schoolmaster sitting (literally) on
his head, the workingman must allow his little girl’s hair, first to be
neglected from poverty, next to be poisoned by promiscuity, and, lastly,
to be abolished by hygiene. He, perhaps, was proud of his little girl’s
hair. But he does not count.</p>
<p>Upon this simple principle (or rather precedent) the sociological doctor
drives gayly ahead. When a crapulous tyranny crushes men down into the
dirt, so that their very hair is dirty, the scientific course is clear. It
would be long and laborious to cut off the heads of the tyrants; it is
easier to cut off the hair of the slaves. In the same way, if it should
ever happen that poor children, screaming with toothache, disturbed any
schoolmaster or artistic gentleman, it would be easy to pull out all the
teeth of the poor; if their nails were disgustingly dirty, their nails
could be plucked out; if their noses were indecently blown, their noses
could be cut off. The appearance of our humbler fellow-citizen could be
quite strikingly simplified before we had done with him. But all this is
not a bit wilder than the brute fact that a doctor can walk into the house
of a free man, whose daughter’s hair may be as clean as spring flowers,
and order him to cut it off. It never seems to strike these people that
the lesson of lice in the slums is the wrongness of slums, not the
wrongness of hair. Hair is, to say the least of it, a rooted thing. Its
enemy (like the other insects and oriental armies of whom we have spoken)
sweep upon us but seldom. In truth, it is only by eternal institutions
like hair that we can test passing institutions like empires. If a house
is so built as to knock a man’s head off when he enters it, it is built
wrong.</p>
<p>The mob can never rebel unless it is conservative, at least enough to have
conserved some reasons for rebelling. It is the most awful thought in all
our anarchy, that most of the ancient blows struck for freedom would not
be struck at all to-day, because of the obscuration of the clean, popular
customs from which they came. The insult that brought down the hammer of
Wat Tyler might now be called a medical examination. That which Virginius
loathed and avenged as foul slavery might now be praised as free love. The
cruel taunt of Foulon, “Let them eat grass,” might now be represented as
the dying cry of an idealistic vegetarian. Those great scissors of science
that would snip off the curls of the poor little school children are
ceaselessly snapping closer and closer to cut off all the corners and
fringes of the arts and honors of the poor. Soon they will be twisting
necks to suit clean collars, and hacking feet to fit new boots. It never
seems to strike them that the body is more than raiment; that the Sabbath
was made for man; that all institutions shall be judged and damned by
whether they have fitted the normal flesh and spirit. It is the test of
political sanity to keep your head. It is the test of artistic sanity to
keep your hair on.</p>
<p>Now the whole parable and purpose of these last pages, and indeed of all
these pages, is this: to assert that we must instantly begin all over
again, and begin at the other end. I begin with a little girl’s hair. That
I know is a good thing at any rate. Whatever else is evil, the pride of a
good mother in the beauty of her daughter is good. It is one of those
adamantine tendernesses which are the touchstones of every age and race.
If other things are against it, other things must go down. If landlords
and laws and sciences are against it, landlords and laws and sciences must
go down. With the red hair of one she-urchin in the gutter I will set fire
to all modern civilization. Because a girl should have long hair, she
should have clean hair; because she should have clean hair, she should not
have an unclean home: because she should not have an unclean home, she
should have a free and leisured mother; because she should have a free
mother, she should not have an usurious landlord; because there should not
be an usurious landlord, there should be a redistribution of property;
because there should be a redistribution of property, there shall be a
revolution. That little urchin with the gold-red hair, whom I have just
watched toddling past my house, she shall not be lopped and lamed and
altered; her hair shall not be cut short like a convict’s; no, all the
kingdoms of the earth shall be hacked about and mutilated to suit her. She
is the human and sacred image; all around her the social fabric shall sway
and split and fall; the pillars of society shall be shaken, and the roofs
of ages come rushing down, and not one hair of her head shall be harmed.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0052" id="link2H_4_0052"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> THREE NOTES </h2>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0053" id="link2H_4_0053"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> I. ON FEMALE SUFFRAGE </h2>
<p>Not wishing to overload this long essay with too many parentheses, apart
from its thesis of progress and precedent, I append here three notes on
points of detail that may possibly be misunderstood.</p>
<p>The first refers to the female controversy. It may seem to many that I
dismiss too curtly the contention that all women should have votes, even
if most women do not desire them. It is constantly said in this connection
that males have received the vote (the agricultural laborers for instance)
when only a minority of them were in favor of it. Mr. Galsworthy, one of
the few fine fighting intellects of our time, has talked this language in
the “Nation.” Now, broadly, I have only to answer here, as everywhere in
this book, that history is not a toboggan slide, but a road to be
reconsidered and even retraced. If we really forced General Elections upon
free laborers who definitely disliked General Elections, then it was a
thoroughly undemocratic thing to do; if we are democrats we ought to undo
it. We want the will of the people, not the votes of the people; and to
give a man a vote against his will is to make voting more valuable than
the democracy it declares.</p>
<p>But this analogy is false, for a plain and particular reason. Many
voteless women regard a vote as unwomanly. Nobody says that most voteless
men regarded a vote as unmanly. Nobody says that any voteless men regarded
it as unmanly. Not in the stillest hamlet or the most stagnant fen could
you find a yokel or a tramp who thought he lost his sexual dignity by
being part of a political mob. If he did not care about a vote it was
solely because he did not know about a vote; he did not understand the
word any better than Bimetallism. His opposition, if it existed, was
merely negative. His indifference to a vote was really indifference.</p>
<p>But the female sentiment against the franchise, whatever its size, is
positive. It is not negative; it is by no means indifferent. Such women as
are opposed to the change regard it (rightly or wrongly) as unfeminine.
That is, as insulting certain affirmative traditions to which they are
attached. You may think such a view prejudiced; but I violently deny that
any democrat has a right to override such prejudices, if they are popular
and positive. Thus he would not have a right to make millions of Moslems
vote with a cross if they had a prejudice in favor of voting with a
crescent. Unless this is admitted, democracy is a farce we need scarcely
keep up. If it is admitted, the Suffragists have not merely to awaken an
indifferent, but to convert a hostile majority.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0054" id="link2H_4_0054"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> II. ON CLEANLINESS IN EDUCATION </h2>
<p>On re-reading my protest, which I honestly think much needed, against our
heathen idolatry of mere ablution, I see that it may possibly be misread.
I hasten to say that I think washing a most important thing to be taught
both to rich and poor. I do not attack the positive but the relative
position of soap. Let it be insisted on even as much as now; but let other
things be insisted on much more. I am even ready to admit that cleanliness
is next to godliness; but the moderns will not even admit godliness to be
next to cleanliness. In their talk about Thomas Becket and such saints and
heroes they make soap more important than soul; they reject godliness
whenever it is not cleanliness. If we resent this about remote saints and
heroes, we should resent it more about the many saints and heroes of the
slums, whose unclean hands cleanse the world. Dirt is evil chiefly as
evidence of sloth; but the fact remains that the classes that wash most
are those that work least. Concerning these, the practical course is
simple; soap should be urged on them and advertised as what it is—a
luxury. With regard to the poor also the practical course is not hard to
harmonize with our thesis. If we want to give poor people soap we must set
out deliberately to give them luxuries. If we will not make them rich
enough to be clean, then emphatically we must do what we did with the
saints. We must reverence them for being dirty.</p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0055" id="link2H_4_0055"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> III. ON PEASANT PROPRIETORSHIP </h2>
<p>I have not dealt with any details touching distributed ownership, or its
possibility in England, for the reason stated in the text. This book deals
with what is wrong, wrong in our root of argument and effort. This wrong
is, I say, that we will go forward because we dare not go back. Thus the
Socialist says that property is already concentrated into Trusts and
Stores: the only hope is to concentrate it further in the State. I say the
only hope is to unconcentrate it; that is, to repent and return; the only
step forward is the step backward.</p>
<p>But in connection with this distribution I have laid myself open to
another potential mistake. In speaking of a sweeping redistribution, I
speak of decision in the aim, not necessarily of abruptness in the means.
It is not at all too late to restore an approximately rational state of
English possessions without any mere confiscation. A policy of buying out
landlordism, steadily adopted in England as it has already been adopted in
Ireland (notably in Mr. Wyndham’s wise and fruitful Act), would in a very
short time release the lower end of the see-saw and make the whole plank
swing more level. The objection to this course is not at all that it would
not do, only that it will not be done. If we leave things as they are,
there will almost certainly be a crash of confiscation. If we hesitate, we
shall soon have to hurry. But if we start doing it quickly we have still
time to do it slowly.</p>
<p>This point, however, is not essential to my book. All I have to urge
between these two boards is that I dislike the big Whiteley shop, and that
I dislike Socialism because it will (according to Socialists) be so like
that shop. It is its fulfilment, not its reversal. I do not object to
Socialism because it will revolutionize our commerce, but because it will
leave it so horribly the same.</p>
<p><br/><br/><br/><br/></p>
<SPAN name="endofbook"></SPAN>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />