<h2 align="center">CHAPTER III</h2>
<p align="center">AMERICAN COURTS AS LEGISLATIVE CHAMBERS</p>
<br/>
<p>In one point of view many of the greatest of the Federalists were idealists.
They seem sincerely to have believed that they could, by some form of written
words, constrain a people to be honest against their will, and almost as soon as
the new government went into operation they tested these beliefs by experiment,
with very indifferent success. I take it that jurists like Jay and Marshall held
it to be axiomatic that rules of conduct should be laid down by them which would
be applicable to rich and poor, great and small, alike, and that courts could
maintain such rules against all pressure. Possibly such principles may be
enforced against individuals, but they cannot be enforced against communities,
and it was here that the Federalist philosophy collapsed, as Hamilton, at least
partly, foresaw that it must.</p>
<p>Sovereigns have always enjoyed immunity from suit by private persons, unless
they have been pleased to assent thereto, not because it is less wrongful for a
sovereign than for an individual to cheat, but because the sovereign cannot be
arrested and the individual can. With the Declaration of Independence the
thirteen colonies became sovereigns. Petty sovereigns it is true, and singly
contemptible in physical force as against most foreign nations, but none the
less tenacious of the attributes of sovereignty, and especially of the attribute
which enabled them to repudiate their debts. Jay, Marshall, and their like,
thought that they could impose the same moral standard upon the states as upon
private persons; they were unable to do so, but in making the attempt they
involved the American judicial system in a maze of difficulties whose gravity, I
fear, can hardly be exaggerated. Before entering upon this history, however, I
must say a word touching the nature of our law.</p>
<p>Municipal law, to be satisfactory, should be a body of abstract principles
capable of being applied impartially to all relevant facts, just as Marshall and
Jay held it to be. Where exceptions begin, equality before the law ends, as I
have tried to show by the story of King David and Uriah, and therefore the great
effort of civilization has been to remove judges from the possibility of being
subjected to a temptation, or to a pressure, which may deflect them from
impartiality as between suitors. In modern civilization, especially, nothing is
so fatal to the principle of order as inequality in the dispensation of justice,
and it would have been reasonable to suppose that Americans, beyond all others,
would have been alive to this teaching of experience, and have studiously
withdrawn their bench from politics. In fact they have ignored it, and instead
they have set their judiciary at the focus of conflicting forces. The result has
been the more unfortunate as the English system of jurisprudence is ill
calculated to bear the strain, it being inflexible. In theory the English law
moves logically from precedent to precedent, the judge originating nothing, only
elaborating ideas which he has received from a predecessor, and which are
binding on him. If the line of precedents leads to wrongful conclusions, the
legislature must intervene with a statute rectifying the wrong. The Romans, who
were gifted with a higher legal genius than we, managed better. The praetor, by
his edict, suppressed inconvenient precedents, and hence the Romans maintained
flexibility in their municipal law without falling into confusion. We have
nothing to correspond to the praetor.</p>
<p>Thus the English system of binding precedents is troublesome enough in a
civilization in chronic and violent flux like modern civilization, even when
applied to ordinary municipal law which may be changed at will by legislation,
but it brings society almost to a stand when applied to the most vital functions
of government, with no means at hand to obtain a corrective. For the court of
last resort having once declared the meaning of a clause of the Constitution,
that meaning remains fixed forever, unless the court either reverses itself,
which is a disaster, or the Constitution can be amended by the states, which is
not only difficult, but which, even if it be possible, entails years of delay.</p>
<p>Yet pressing emergencies arise, emergencies in which a settlement of some
kind must almost necessarily be reached somewhat rapidly to avert very serious
disorders, and it has been under this tension, as I understand American
constitutional development, that our courts have resorted to legislation. Nor is
it fair for us to measure the sagacity of our great jurists by the standard of
modern experience. They lived before the acceleration of movement by electricity
and steam. They could not foresee the rapidity and the profundity of the changes
which were imminent. Hence it was that, in the spirit of great lawyers, who were
also possibly men tinged with a certain enthusiasm for the ideal, they began
their work by ruling on the powers and limitations of sovereignty, as if they
were ruling on the necessity of honest intent in dealings with one's neighbor.</p>
<p>In 1789 General Washington is said to have offered John Jay his choice of
offices under the new government, and Jay chose the chief justiceship, because
there he thought he could make his influence felt most widely. If so he had his
wish, and very shortly met with disappointment. In the August Term of 1792, one
Chisholm, a citizen of South Carolina, sued the State of Georgia for a debt.
Georgia declined to appear, and in February, 1793, Jay, in an elaborate opinion,
gave judgment for Chisholm. Jay was followed by his associates with the
exception of Iredell, J., of North Carolina. Forthwith a ferment began, and in
the very next session of Congress an amendment to the Constitution was proposed
to make such suits impossible. In January, 1798, five years after the case was
argued, this amendment was declared to be adopted, but meanwhile Jay had
resigned to become governor of New York. In December, 1800, he was again offered
the chief justiceship by John Adams, on the resignation of Oliver Ellsworth, but
Jay resolutely declined. I have often wondered whether Jay's mortification at
having his only important constitutional decision summarily condemned by the
people may not have given him a distaste for judicial life.</p>
<p>The Federalist attempt to enforce on the states a positive rule of economic
morality, therefore, collapsed at once, but it still remained possible to
approach the same problem from its negative side, through the clause of the
Constitution which forbade any state to impair the validity of contracts, and
Marshall took up this aspect of the task where Jay left it. In Marshall's mind
his work was simple. He had only to determine the nature of a contract, and the
rest followed automatically. All contracts were to be held sacred. Their greater
or less importance was immaterial.</p>
<p>In 1810 Marshall expounded this general principle in Fletcher <i>v</i>. Peck.<SPAN name="FNanchor18"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_18"><sup>[18]</sup></SPAN>
"When ... a law is in its nature a contract ... a repeal of the law cannot
devest" rights which have vested under it. A couple of years later he
applied his principle to the extreme case of an unlimited remission of taxation.<SPAN name="FNanchor19"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_19"><sup>[19]</sup></SPAN>
The State of New Jersey had granted an exemption from taxation to lands ceded to
certain Indians. Marshall held that this contract ran with the land, and inured
to the benefit of grantees from the Indians. If the state cared to resume its
power of taxation, it must buy the grant back, and the citizens of New Jersey
must pay for their improvidence.</p>
<p>Seven years later, in 1810, Marshall may, perhaps, be said to have reached
the culmination of his career, for then he carried his moral standard to a
breaking strain. But, though his theory broke down, perhaps the most striking
evidence of his wonderful intellectual superiority is that he convinced the
Democrat, Joseph Story,--a man who had been nominated by Madison to oppose him,
and of undoubted strength of character,--of the soundness of his thesis. In
1769 King George III incorporated certain Trustees of Dartmouth College. The
charter was accepted and both real and personal property were thereupon conveyed
to this corporate body, in trust for educational purposes. In 1816 the
legislature of New Hampshire reorganized the board of trustees against their
will. If the incorporation amounted to a contract, the Court was clear that this
statute impaired it; therefore the only really debatable issue was whether the
grant of a charter by the king amounted to a contract by him, with his subjects
to whom he granted it. After prolonged consideration Marshall concluded that it
did, and I conceive that, in the eye of history, he was right. Throughout the
Middle Ages corporate privileges of all kinds, but especially municipal
corporate privileges, had been subjects of purchase and sale, and indeed the
mediaeval social system rested on such contracts. So much was this the case that
the right to return members of Parliament from incorporated boroughs was, as
Lord Eldon pointed out in the debates on the Reform Bill, as much private
property "as any of your lordships'" titles and peerages.</p>
<p>It was here that Marshall faltered. He felt that the public would not support
him if he held that states could not alter town and county charters, so he
arbitrarily split corporations in halves, protecting only those which handled
exclusively private funds, and abandoning "instruments of government,"
as he called them, to the mercy of legislative assemblies.</p>
<p>Toward 1832 it became convenient for middle class Englishmen to confiscate
most of the property which the aristocracy had invested in parliamentary
boroughs, and this social revolution was effected without straining the judicial
system, because of the supremacy of Parliament. In America, at about the same
time, it became, in like manner, convenient to confiscate numerous equally
well-vested rights, because, to have compensated the owners would have entailed
a considerable sacrifice which neither the public nor the promoters of new
enterprises were willing to make. The same end was reached in America as in
England, in spite of Chief Justice Marshall and the Dartmouth College Case, only
in America it was attained by a legal somerset which has disordered the course
of justice ever since.</p>
<p>In 1697 King William III incorporated Trinity Church in the City of New York,
confirming to the society the possession of a parcel of land, adjoining the
church, to be used as a churchyard for the burial of the dead. In 1823 the
government of New York prohibited interments within the city limits, thus
closing the churchyard for the purposes for which it had been granted. As
compensation was refused, it appeared to be a clear case of confiscation, and
Trinity resisted. In the teeth of recent precedents the Supreme Court of New
York decided that, under the <i>Police Power</i>, the legislature of New York
might authorize this sort of appropriation of private property for sanitary
purposes, without paying the owners for any loss they might thereby sustain.<SPAN name="FNanchor20"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_20"><sup>[20]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>The court thus simply dispensed the legislature from obedience to the law,
saying in effect, "although the Constitution forbids impairing contracts,
and although this is a contract which you have impaired, yet, in our discretion,
we suspend the operation of the Constitution, in this instance, by calling your
act an exercise of a power unknown to the framers of the Constitution." I
cannot doubt that Marshall would have flouted this theory had he lived to pass
upon it, but Marshall died in 1835, and the Charles River Bridge Case, in which
this question was first presented to the Supreme Court of the United States, did
not come up until 1837. Then Joseph Story, who remained as the representative of
Marshall's philosophy upon the bench, vehemently protested against the
latitudinarianism of Chief Justice Taney and his associates, but without
producing the slightest effect.</p>
<p>In 1785 the Massachusetts legislature chartered the Charles River Bridge
Company to build a bridge between Boston and Charlestown, authorizing it, by way
of consideration, to collect tolls for forty years. In 1792 the franchise was
extended to seventy years, when the bridge was to revert to the Commonwealth. In
1828 the legislature chartered the Warren Bridge Company, expressly to build a
bridge parallel to and practically adjoining the Charles River Bridge, the
Warren Bridge to become a free bridge after six years. The purpose, of course,
was to accelerate movement by ruining the Charles River Bridge Company. The
Charles River Bridge Company sought to restrain the building of the Warren
Bridge as a breach of contract by the State, but failed to obtain relief in the
state courts, and before the cause could be argued at Washington the Warren
Bridge had become free and had destroyed the value of the Charles River Bridge,
though its franchise had still twenty years to run. As Story pointed out, no one
denied that the charter of the Charles River Bridge Company was a contract, and,
as he insisted, it is only common sense as well as common justice and elementary
law, that contracts of this character should be reasonably interpreted so far as
quiet enjoyment of the consideration granted is concerned; but all this availed
nothing. The gist of the opposing argument is contained in a single sentence in
the opinion of the Chief Justice who spoke for the majority of the court:
"The millions of property which have been invested in railroads and canals,
upon lines of travel which had been before occupied by turnpike corporations,
will be put in jeopardy" if this doctrine is to prevail.<SPAN name="FNanchor21"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_21"><sup>[21]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>The effect of the adoption by the Supreme Court of the United States of the
New York theory of the Police Power was to vest in the judiciary, by the use of
this catch-word, an almost unparalleled prerogative. They assumed a supreme
function which can only be compared to the Dispensing Power claimed by the
Stuarts, or to the authority which, according to the Council of Constance,
inheres in the Church, to "grant indulgences for reasonable causes." I
suppose nothing in modern judicial history has ever resembled this assumption;
and yet, when we examine it, we find it to be not only the logical, but the
inevitable, effect of those mechanical causes which constrain mankind to move
along the lines of least resistance.</p>
<p>Marshall, in a series of decisions, laid down a general principle which had
been proved to be sound when applied by ordinary courts, dealing with ordinary
social forces, and operating under the corrective power of either a legislature
or a praetor, but which had a different aspect under the American constitutional
system. He held that the fundamental law, embodied in the Constitution,
commanded that all contracts should be sacred. Therefore he, as a judge, had but
two questions to resolve: First, whether, in the case before him, a contract had
been proved to exist. Second, admitting that a contract had been proved, whether
it had also been shown to have been impaired.</p>
<p>Within ten years after these decisions it had been found in practice that
public opinion would not sustain so rigid an administration of the law. No
legislature could intervene, and a pressure was brought to bear which the judges
could not withstand; therefore, the Court yielded, declaring that if impairing a
contract were, on the whole, for the public welfare, the Constitution, as
Marshall interpreted it, should be suspended in favor of the legislation which
impaired it. They called this suspension the operation of the "Police
Power." It followed, as the "Police Power" could only come into
operation at the discretion of the Court, that, therefore, within the limits of
judicial discretion, confiscation, however arbitrary and to whatever extent,
might go on. In the energetic language of the Supreme Court of Maine: "This
duty and consequent power override all statute or contract exemptions. The state
cannot free any person or corporation from subjection to this power. All
personal, as well as property rights must be held subject to the Police Power of
the state."<SPAN name="FNanchor22"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_22"><sup>[22]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>Once the theory of the Police Power was established it became desirable to
define the limits of judicial discretion, but that proved to be impossible. It
could not be determined in advance by abstract reasoning. Hence, as each
litigation arose, the judges could follow no rule but the rule of common sense,
and the Police Power, translated into plain English, presently came to signify
whatever, at the moment, the judges happened to think reasonable. Consequently,
they began guessing at the drift of public opinion, as it percolated to them
through the medium of their education and prejudices. Sometimes they guessed
right and sometimes wrong, and when they guessed wrong they were cast aside, as
appeared dramatically enough in the temperance agitation.</p>
<p>Up to about the middle of the last century the lawfulness of the liquor
business had been unquestioned in the United States, and money had been invested
as freely in it as in any other legitimate enterprise; but, as the temperance
agitation swept over the country, in obedience to the impulsion given by science
to the study of hygiene, dealing in liquor came to be condemned as a crime.
Presently legislatures began to pass statutes to confiscate, more or less
completely, this kind of property, and sufferers brought their cases before the
courts to have the constitutionality of the acts tested, under the provisions
which existed in all state constitutions, forbidding the taking, by the public,
of private property without compensation, or without due process of law. Such a
provision existed hi the constitution of the State of New York, adopted in 1846,
and it was to invoke the protection of this clause that one Wynehamer, who had
been indicted in 1855, carried his case to the Court of Appeals in the year
1856. In that cause Mr. Justice Comstock, who was one of the ablest jurists New
York ever produced, gave an opinion which is a model of judicial' reasoning. He
showed conclusively the absurdity of constitutional restrictions, if due process
of law may be held to mean the enactment of the very statute drawn to work
confiscation.<SPAN name="FNanchor23"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_23"><sup>[23]</sup></SPAN>
This decision, which represented the profoundest convictions of men of the
calibre of Comstock and Denio, deserves to rank with Marshall's effort in the
Dartmouth College Case. In both instances the tribunal exerted itself to carry
out Hamilton's principle of judicial duty by exercising its <i>judgment</i> and
not its <i>will</i>. In other words, the judges propounded a general rule and
then simply determined whether the set of facts presented to them fell within
that rule. They resolutely declined to legislate by entering upon a
consideration of the soundness or reasonableness of the policy which underlay
the action of the legislature. In the one case as in the other the effort was
unavailing, as Jefferson prophesied that it would be. I have told of Marshall's
overthrow in the Charles River Bridge Case, and in 1887, after controversies of
this category had begun to come before the Supreme Court of the United States
under the Fourteenth Amendment, Mr. Justice Harlan swept Mr. Justice Comstock
aside by quietly ignoring an argument which was unanswerable.<SPAN name="FNanchor24"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_24"><sup>[24]</sup></SPAN>
The same series of phenomena have appeared in regard to laws confiscating
property invested in lotteries, when opinion turned against lotteries, or in
occupations supposed to be unsanitary, as in the celebrated case of the taxing
out of existence of the rendering establishment which had been erected as a
public benefit to relieve the City of Chicago of its offal.<SPAN name="FNanchor25"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_25"><sup>[25]</sup></SPAN>
In fine, whenever pressure has reached a given intensity, on one pretext or
another, courts have enforced or dispensed with constitutional limitations with
quite as much facility as have legislatures, and for the same reasons. The only
difference has been that the pressure which has operated most directly upon
courts has not always been the pressure which has swayed legislatures, though
sometimes both influences have combined. For example, during the Civil War, the
courts sanctioned everything the popular majority demanded under the pretext of
the War Power, as in peace they have sanctioned confiscations for certain
popular purposes, under the name of the Police Power. But then, courts have
always been sensitive to financial influences, and if they have been flexible in
permitting popular confiscation when the path of least resistance has lain that
way, they have gone quite as far in the reverse direction when the amount of
capital threatened has been large enough to be with them a countervailing force.</p>
<p>As the federal Constitution originally contained no restriction upon the
states touching the confiscation of the property of their own citizens, provided
contracts were not impaired, it was only in 1868, by the passage of the
Fourteenth Amendment, that the Supreme Court of the United States acquired the
possibility of becoming the censor of state legislation in such matters. Nor did
the Supreme Court accept this burden very willingly or in haste. For a number of
years it labored to confine its function to defining the limits of the Police
Power, guarding itself from the responsibility of passing upon the
"reasonableness" with which that power was used. It was only by
somewhat slow degrees, as the value of the threatened property grew to be vast,
that the Court was deflected from this conservative course into effective
legislation. The first prayers for relief came from the Southern states, who
were still groaning under reconstruction governments; but as the Southern whites
were then rather poor, their complaints were neglected. The first very famous
cause of this category is known as the Slaughter House Cases. In 1869 the Carpet
Bag government of Louisiana conceived the plan of confiscating most of the
property of the butchers who slaughtered for New Orleans, within a district
about as large as the State of Rhode Island. The Fourteenth Amendment forbade
states to deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process
of law, and the butchers of New Orleans prayed for protection, alleging that the
manner in which their property had been taken was utterly lawless. But the
Supreme Court declined to interfere, explaining that the Fourteenth Amendment
had been contrived to protect the emancipated slaves, and not to make the
federal judiciary "a perpetual censor upon all legislation of the states,
on the civil rights of their own citizens, with authority to nullify such as it
did not approve."<SPAN name="FNanchor26"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_26"><sup>[26]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>Although, even at that relatively early day, this conservatism met with
strong opposition within the Court itself, the pressure of vested wealth did not
gather enough momentum to overcome the inertia of the bench for nearly another
generation. It was the concentration of capital in monopoly, and the consequent
effort by the public to regulate monopoly prices, which created the stress which
changed the legal equilibrium. The modern American monopoly seems first to have
generated that amount of friction, which habitually finds vent in a great
litigation, about the year 1870; but only some years later did the states enter
upon a determined policy of regulating monopoly prices by law, with the
establishment by the Illinois legislature of a tariff for the Chicago elevators.
The elevator companies resisted, on the ground that regulation of prices in
private business was equivalent to confiscation, and so in 1876 the Supreme
Court was dragged into this fiercest of controversies, thereby becoming subject
to a stress to which no judiciary can safely be exposed. Obviously two questions
were presented for adjudication: The first, which by courtesy might be termed
legal, was whether the fixing of prices by statute was a prerogative which a
state legislature might constitutionally exercise at all; the second, which was
purely political, was whether, admitting that, in the abstract, such a power
could be exercised by the state, Illinois had, in this particular case, behaved <i>reasonably</i>.
The Supreme Court made a conscientious effort to adhere to the theory of
Hamilton, that it should, in emergencies like this, use its <i>judgment</i>
only, and not its <i>will</i>; that it should lay down a rule, not vote on the
wisdom of a policy. So the judges decided that, from time immemorial, the fixing
of prices in certain trades and occupations had been a legislative function,
which they supposed might be classified as a branch of the Police Power, but
they declared that with this expression of opinion their jurisdiction ended.
When it came to asking them to criticise the propriety of legislation, it was,
in substance, proposing that they should substitute their <i>will</i> for the <i>will</i>
of the representatives of the people, which was impossible. I well remember the
stir made by the case of Munn <i>v</i>. Illinois.<SPAN name="FNanchor27"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_27"><sup>[27]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>Both in and out of the legal profession, those in harmony with the great
vested interests complained that the Court had shirked its duty. But these
complaints soon ceased, for a movement was in progress which swept, for the
moment, all before it. The great aggregations of capital, which had been
accumulating ever since the Charles River Bridge Case, not long after Munn <i>v.</i>
Illinois attained to a point at which they began to grasp many important
prerogatives of sovereignty, and to impose, what was tantamount to, arbitrary
taxation upon a large scale. The crucial trial of strength came on the contest
for control of the railways, and in that contest concentrated capital prevailed.
The Supreme Court reversed its attitude, and undertook to do that which it had
solemnly protested it could not do. It began to censor legislation in the
interest of the strongest force for the time being, that force being actually
financial. By the year 1800 the railway interest had expanded prodigiously.
Between 1876 and 1890 the investment in railways had far more than doubled, and,
during the last five years of this period, the increment had been at an average
of about $450,000,000 annually. At this point the majority of the court yielded,
as ordinary political chambers always must yield, to extraordinary pressure. Mr.
Justice Bradley, however, was not an ordinary man. He was, on the contrary, one
of the ablest and strongest lawyers who sat on the federal bench during the last
half of the nineteenth century; and Bradley, like Story before him, remonstrated
against turning the bench of magistrates, to which he belonged, from a tribunal
which should propound general rules applicable to all material facts, into a
jury to find verdicts on the reasonableness of the votes of representative
assemblies. The legislature of Minnesota, in 1887, passed a statute to regulate
railway rates, and provided that the findings of the commission which it erected
to fix those rates should be final. The Chicago, Milwaukee & St. Paul
Railway contended that this statute was unconstitutional, because it was
unreasonable, and the majority of the Court sustained their contention.<SPAN name="FNanchor28"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_28"><sup>[28]</sup></SPAN>
Justices Bradley, Gray, and Lamar dissented, and Bradley on this occasion
delivered an opinion, from which I shall quote a paragraph or two, since the
argument appears to me conclusive, not only from the point of view of law, but
of political expediency and of common sense:--</p>
<p>"I cannot agree to the decision of the court in this case. It
practically overrules Munn <i>v.</i> Illinois.... The governing principle of
those cases was that the regulation and settlement of the fares of railroads and
other public accommodations is a legislative prerogative, and not a judicial
one. This is a principle which I regard as of great importance....</p>
<p>"But it is said that all charges should be reasonable, and that none but
reasonable charges can be exacted; and it is urged that what is a reasonable
charge is a judicial question. On the contrary, it is pre�minently a
legislative one, involving considerations of policy as well as of
remuneration.... By the decision now made we declare, in effect, that the
judiciary, and not the legislature, is the final arbiter in the regulation of
fares and freights of railroads.... It is an assumption of authority on the part
of the judiciary which, ... it has no right to make. The assertion of
jurisdiction by this court makes it the duty of every court of general
jurisdiction, state or federal, to entertain complaints [of this nature], for
all courts are bound by the Constitution of the United States, the same as we
are."</p>
<p>There is little to add to these words. When the Supreme Court thus undertook
to determine the reasonableness of legislation it assumed, under a somewhat thin
disguise, the position of an upper chamber, which, though it could not
originate, could absolutely veto most statutes touching the use or protection of
property, for the administration of modern American society now hinges on this
doctrine of judicial dispensation under the Police Power. Whether it be a
regulation of rates and prices, of hours of labor, of height of buildings, of
municipal distribution of charity, of flooding a cranberry bog, or of
prescribing to sleeping-car porters duties regarding the lowering of upper
berths,--in questions great and small, the courts vote upon the reasonableness
of the use of the Police Power, like any old-fashioned town meeting. There is no
rule of law involved. There is only opinion or prejudice, or pecuniary interest.
The judges admit frankly that this is so. They avow that they try to weigh
public opinion, as well as they can, and then vote. In 1911 Mr. Justice Holmes
first explained that the Police Power extended to all great public needs, and
then went on to observe that this Police Power, or extraordinary prerogative,
might be put forth by legislatures "in aid of what is sanctioned by usage,
or held by ... preponderant opinion to be ... necessary to the public
welfare."<SPAN name="FNanchor29"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_29"><sup>[29]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>A representative chamber reaches its conclusions touching "preponderant
opinion" by a simple process, but the influences which sway courts are
obscurer,--often, probably, beyond the sphere of the consciousness of the
judges themselves. Nor is this the worst; for, as I have already explained, the
very constitution of a court, if it be a court calculated to do its legitimate
work upon a lofty level, precludes it from keeping pace with the movement in
science and the arts. Necessarily it lags some years behind. And this tendency,
which is a benefit in the dispensation of justice as between private litigants,
becomes a menace when courts are involved in politics. A long line of sinister
precedents crowd unbidden upon the mind. The Court of King's Bench, when it held
Hampden to be liable for the Ship Money, draped the scaffold for Charles I. The
Parliament of Paris, when it denounced Turgot's edict touching the corv�e,
threw wide the gate by which the aristocracy of France passed to the guillotine.
The ruling of the Superior Court of the Province of Massachusetts Bay, in the
case of the Writs of Assistance, presaged the American Revolution; and the Dred
Scott decision was the prelude to the Civil War.</p>
<p>The capital essential of justice is that, under like conditions, all should
fare alike. The magistrate should be no respecter of persons. The vice of our
system of judicial dispensation is that it discriminates among suitors in
proportion to their power of resistance. This is so because, under adequate
pressure, our courts yield along the path of least resistance. I should not
suppose that any man could calmly turn over the pages of the recent volumes of
the reports of the Supreme Court of the United States and not rise from the
perusal convinced that the rich and the poor, the strong and the weak, do not
receive a common measure of justice before that judgment seat. Disregarding the
discrimination which is always apparent against those who are unpopular, or who
suffer under special opprobrium, as do liquor dealers, owners of lotteries, and
the like,<SPAN name="FNanchor30"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_30"><sup>[30]</sup></SPAN> I
will take, nearly at random, a couple of examples of rate regulation, where
tenderness has been shown property in something approaching to a mathematical
ratio to the amount involved.</p>
<p>In April, 1894, a record was produced before the Supreme Court which showed
that the State of North Dakota had in 1891 established rates for elevating and
storing grain, which rates the defendant, named Brass, who owned a small
elevator, alleged to be, to him in particular, <i>utterly</i> ruinous, and to be
in general unreasonable. He averred that he used his elevator for the storage of
his own grain, that it cost about $3000, that he had no monopoly, as there were
many hundred such elevators in the state, and, as land fit for the purpose of
building elevators was plenty and cheap, that any man could build an elevator in
the town in which he lived, as well as he; that the rates he charged were
reasonable, and that, were he compelled to receive grain generally at the rates
fixed by the statute, he could not store his own grain. All these facts were
admitted by demurrer, and Brass contended that if any man's property were ever
to be held to be appropriated by the public without compensation, and under no
form of law at all save a predatory statute, it should be his; but the Supreme
Court voted the Dakota statute to be a reasonable exercise of the Police Power,<SPAN name="FNanchor31"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_31"><sup>[31]</sup></SPAN>
and dismissed Brass to his fate.</p>
<p>The converse case is a very famous one known as Smyth <i>v.</i> Ames,<SPAN name="FNanchor32"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_32"><sup>[32]</sup></SPAN>
decided four years later, in 1898. In that case it appeared that the State of
Nebraska had, in 1893, reduced freight rates within the state about twenty-nine
per cent, in order to bring them into some sort of relation to the rates charged
in the adjoining State of Iowa, which were calculated to be forty per cent lower
than the Nebraska rates. Several of the most opulent and powerful corporations
of the Union were affected by this law, among others the exceedingly prosperous
and influential Chicago, Burlington & Quincy Railway. No one pretended that,
were the law to be enforced, the total revenues of the Burlington would be
seriously impaired, nor was it even clear that, were the estimate of reduction,
revenue, and cost confined altogether to the commerce carried on within the
limits of the State of Nebraska, leaving interstate commerce out of
consideration, a loss would be suffered during the following year. Trade might
increase with cheaper rates, or economies might be made by the company, or both
causes and many others of increased earnings might combine. Corporation counsel,
however, argued that, were the principle of the statute admitted, and should all
the states through which the line passed do the like, ultimately a point might
be reached at which the railway would be unable to maintain, even approximately,
its dividend of eight per cent, and that the creation of such a possibility was
conceding the power of confiscation, and, therefore, an unreasonable exercise of
the Police Power, by the State of Nebraska. With this argument the Supreme Court
concurred. They held the Nebraska statute to be unreasonable. Very possibly it
may have been unsound legislation, yet it is noteworthy that within three years
after this decision Mr. Hill bought the Chicago, Burlington & Quincy, at the
rate of $200 for every share of stock of the par value of $100, thus fixing
forever, on the community tributary to the road, the burden of paying a revenue
on just double the value of all the stock which it had been found necessary to
issue to build the highway. Even at this price Mr. Hill is supposed to have made
a brilliant bargain.</p>
<p>This brings me to the heart of my theorem. Ever since Hamilton's time, it has
been assumed as axiomatic, by conservative Americans, that courts whose function
is to expound a written constitution can and do act as a "barrier to the
encroachments and oppressions of the representative body."<SPAN name="FNanchor33"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_33"><sup>[33]</sup></SPAN>
I apprehend that courts can perform no such office and that in assuming
attributes beyond the limitations of their being they, as history has abundantly
proved, not only fail in their object, but shake the foundations of authority,
and immolate themselves. Hitherto I have confined myself to adducing historical
evidence to prove that American courts have, as a whole, been gifted with so
little political sagacity that their interference with legislation, on behalf of
particular suitors, has, in the end, been a danger rather than a protection to
those suitors, because of the animosity which it has engendered. I shall now go
further. For the sake of argument I am willing to admit that the courts, in the
exercise of the dispensing prerogative, called the Police Power, have always
acted wisely, so much so that every such decree which they have issued may be
triumphantly defended upon economic, moral, or social grounds. Yet, assuming
this to be true, though I think I have shown it to be untrue, the assumption
only strengthens my contention, that our courts have ceased to be true courts,
and are converted into legislative chambers, thereby promising shortly to
become, if they are not already, a menace to order. I take it to be clear that
the function of a legislature is to embody the will of the dominant social
force, for the time being, in a political policy explained by statutes, and when
that policy has reached a certain stage of development, to cause it to be
digested, together with the judicial decisions relevant to it, in a code. This
process of correlation is the highest triumph of the jurist, and it was by their
easy supremacy in this field of thought, that Roman lawyers chiefly showed their
preeminence as compared with modern lawyers. Still, while admitting this
superiority, it is probably true that the Romans owed much of their success in
codification to the greater permanence of the Roman legislative tenure of
office, and, therefore, stability of policy,--phenomena which were both
probably effects of a slower social movement among the ancients. The Romans,
therefore, had less need than we of a permanent judiciary to counteract the
disintegrating tendency of redundant legislation; <i>a fortiori</i>, of course,
they had still less to isolate the judiciary from political onslaughts which
might cause justice to become a series of exceptions to general principles,
rather than a code of unvarying rules.</p>
<p>It is precisely because they are, and are intended to be, arenas of political
combat, that legislatures cannot be trustworthy courts, and it was because this
fact was notorious that the founders of this government tried to separate the
legislative from the judicial function, and to make this separation the
foundation of the new republic. They failed, as I conceive, not because they
made their legislatures courts, but because, under the system they devised,
their courts have become legislatures. A disease, perhaps, the more insidious of
the two. Insidious because it undermines, order, while legislative murder and
confiscation induce reaction.</p>
<p>If a legislative chamber would act as a court, the first necessity is to
eliminate its legislative character. For example, the House of Lords in England
has long discharged the duties of a tribunal of last resort for the empire, and
with general approbation, but only because, when sitting as a court, the law
lords sit alone. Politicians and political influences are excluded. Where
political influences enter disaster follows. Hence the infamous renown of
political decisions in legal controversies, such as bills of attainder and <i>ex
post facto</i> laws, or special legislation to satisfy claims which could not be
defended before legitimate courts, or the scandals always attending the trial of
election petitions. The object of true courts is to shield the public from these
and kindred abuses.</p>
<p>In primitive communities courts are erected to defend the weak against the
strong, by correlating local customs in such wise that some general principle
can be deduced which shall protect the civil rights of those who cannot protect
themselves, against the arbitrary exactions of powerful neighbors. In no
community can every person have equal civil rights. That is impossible. Civil
rights must vary according to status. But such rights as any person may have,
those the courts are bound to guard indifferently. If the courts do not perform
this, their first and most sacred duty, I apprehend that order cannot be
permanently maintained, for this is equality before the law; and equality before
the law is the cornerstone of order in every modern state.</p>
<p>I conceive that the lawyers of the age of Washington were the ablest that
America has ever produced. No men ever understood the principle of equality
before the law more thoroughly than they, and after the establishment of this
government a long series of great and upright magistrates strove, as I have
shown, to carry this principle into effect. Jay and Marshall, Story and Bradley,
and many, many more, struggled, protested, and failed. Failed, as I believe,
through no fault of their own, but because fortune had placed them in a position
untenable for the judge. When plunged in the vortex of politics, courts must
waver as do legislatures, and nothing is to me more painful than to watch the
process of deterioration by which our judges lose the instinct which should warn
them to shun legislation as a breach of trust, and to cleave to those general
principles which permit of no exceptions. To illustrate my meaning I shall refer
to but one litigation, but that one is so extraordinary that I must deal with it
in detail.</p>
<p>In 1890 the dread of the enhancement of prices by monopoly, as the Supreme
Court itself has explained, caused Congress to pass the famous Sherman Act,
which prohibited indiscriminately all monopolies or restraints of trade.
Presently the government brought a bill to dissolve an obnoxious railway pool,
called the Trans-Missouri Freight Association, and in 1896 the case came up for
adjudication. I have nothing to say touching the policy involved. I am only
concerned with a series of phenomena, developed through several years, as
effects of pressure acting upon a judiciary, exposed as the judiciary, under our
system, is exposed.</p>
<p>The Trans-Missouri Case was argued on December 8, 1896, very elaborately and
by the most eminent counsel. After long consideration, and profound reflection,
Mr. Justice Peckham, speaking for the majority of the tribunal, laid down a
general principle in conformity to the legislative will, precisely as Marshall
had laid down a general principle in the Dartmouth College Case, or Story in the
Charles River Bridge Case, or Waite in Munn <i>v</i>. Illinois, or Bradley in
the Minnesota Rate Case. Then the process of agitation immediately began. In the
words of Mr. Justice Harlan, fifteen years later: "But those who were in
combinations that were illegal did not despair. They at once set up the baseless
claim that the decision of 1896 disturbed the 'business interests of the
country,' and let it be known that they would never be content until the rule
was established that would permit interstate commerce to be subjected to <i>reasonable</i>
restraints."<SPAN name="FNanchor34"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_34"><sup>[34]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>Other great causes, involving the same issue, were tried, the question was
repeatedly reargued, but the Supreme Court tenaciously adhered to its general
principle, that, under the Sherman Act, <i>all</i> restraints of trade, or
monopolies, were unlawful, and, therefore, the Court had but two matters before
it, first to define a restraint of trade or a monopoly, second to determine
whether the particular combination complained of fell within that definition. No
discretion was permitted. Judicial duty ended there.</p>
<p>The Court being found to be inflexible, recourse was had to Congress, and a
bill in the form of an amendment to the Sherman Act was brought into the Senate
authorizing, in substance, those who felt unsafe under the law, to apply to
certain government officials, to be permitted to produce evidence of the
reasonable methods they employed, and, if the evidence were satisfactory, to
receive, what was tantamount to, an indulgence. The subject thus reopened, the
Senate Committee on the Judiciary went into the whole question of monopoly anew,
and in 1909 Senator Nelson presented an exhaustive report against the proposed
relaxation. Thereupon the Senate indefinitely postponed further consideration of
the amendment. The chief reasons given by Senator Nelson were summed up in a
single sentence: "The defence of reasonable restraint would be made in
every case and there would be as many different rules of reasonableness as
cases, courts, and juries.... To amend the anti-trust act, as suggested by this
bill, would be to entirely emasculate it, and for all practical purposes render
it nugatory as a remedial statute.... The act as it exists is clear,
comprehensive, certain and highly remedial. It practically covers the field of
federal jurisdiction, and is in every respect a model law. To destroy or
undermine it at the present juncture, ... would be a calamity.</p>
<p>"In view of the foregoing, your committee recommend the indefinite
postponement of the bill."<SPAN name="FNanchor35"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_35"><sup>[35]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>And so the Senate did indefinitely postpone the bill.</p>
<p>Matters stood thus when the government brought process to dissolve the
Standard Oil Company, as an unlawful combination. The cause was decided on May
15, 1911, the Chief Justice speaking for the majority of the bench, in one of
the most suggestive opinions which I have ever read. To me this opinion, like
Taney's opinion in the Charles River Bridge Case, indicates that the tension had
reached the breaking point, the court yielding in all directions at once, while
the dominant preoccupation of the presiding judge seemed to be to plant his
tribunal in such a position that it could so yield, without stultifying itself
hopelessly before the legal profession and the public. In striving to reach this
position, however, I apprehend that the Chief Justice, unreservedly, crossed the
chasm on whose brink American jurists had been shuddering for ninety years. The
task the Chief Justice assumed was difficult almost beyond precedent. He
proposed to surrender to the vested interests the principle of <i>reasonableness</i>
which they demanded, and which the tribunal he represented, together with
Congress, had refused to surrender for fifteen years. To pacify the public,
which would certainly resent this surrender, he was prepared to punish two hated
corporations, while he strove to preserve, so far as he could, the respect of
the legal profession and of the public, for the court over which he presided, by
maintaining a semblance of consistency.</p>
<p>To accomplish these contradictory results, the Chief Justice began, rather
after the manner of Marshall in Marbury <i>v</i>. Madison, by an extra-judicial
disquisition. The object of this disquisition was to justify his admission of
the evidence of reasonableness as a defence, although it was not needful to
decide that such evidence must be admitted in order to dispose of that
particular cause. For the Chief Justice very readily agreed that the Standard
Oil Company was, in fact, an unreasonable restraint of trade, and must be
dissolved, no matter whether it were allowed to prove its reasonable methods or
not. Accordingly, he might have contented himself with stating that, admitting
for the sake of argument but without approving, all the defendant advanced, he
should sustain the government; but to have so disposed of the case would not
have suited his purpose. What the Chief Justice had it at heart to do was to
surrender a fundamental principle, and yet to appear to make no surrender at
all. Hence, he prepared his preliminary and extra-judicial essay on the human
reason, of whose precise meaning, I must admit, I still, after many perusals,
have grave doubts. I sometimes suspect that the Chief Justice did not wish to be
too explicit. So far as I comprehend the Chief Justice, his chain of reasoning
amounted to something like this: It was true, he observed, that for fifteen
years the Supreme Court had rejected the evidence of reasonableness which he
admitted, and had insisted upon a general principle which he might be supposed
to renounce, but this apparent discrepancy involved no contradiction. It was
only a progression in thought. For, he continued, the judges who, on various
previous occasions, sustained that general principle, must have reached their
conclusions by the light of reason; to-day we reach a contrary conclusion, but
we also do so by the light of reason; therefore, as all these decisions are
guided by the light of reason they fundamentally coincide, however much
superficially they may seem to differ.<SPAN name="FNanchor36"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_36"><sup>[36]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>I have never supposed that this argument carried complete conviction either
to the legal profession, to the public, or to Congress. Certainly, it did not
convince Mr. Justice Harlan, who failed to fathom it, and bluntly expressed his
astonishment in a dissenting opinion in another cause from which I regret to say
I can only quote a couple of paragraphs, although the whole deserves attentive
perusal:--</p>
<p>"If I do not misapprehend the opinion just delivered, the Court insists
that what was said in the opinion in the Standard Oil Case, was in accordance
with our previous decisions in the Trans-Missouri and Joint Traffic Cases, ...
if we resort to <i>reason</i>. This statement surprises me quite as much as
would a statement that black was white or white was black."</p>
<p>"But now the Court, in accordance with what it denominates the 'rule of
reason,' in effect inserts in the act the word 'undue,' which means the same as
'unreasonable,' and thereby makes Congress say what it did not say.... And what,
since the passage of the act, it has explicitly refused to say.... In short, the
Court now, by judicial legislation, in effect, amends an Act of Congress
relating to a subject over which that department of the Government has exclusive
cognizance."<SPAN name="FNanchor37"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_37"><sup>[37]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>The phenomenon which amazed Mr. Justice Harlan is, I conceive, perfectly
comprehensible, if we reflect a little on the conflict of forces involved, and
on the path of least resistance open to an American judge seeking to find for
this conflict, a resultant. The regulation or the domination of monopoly was an
issue going to the foundation of society, and popular and financial energy had
come into violent impact in regard to the control of prices. Popular energy
found vent through Congress, while the financiers, as financiers always have and
always will, took shelter behind the courts. Congress, in 1890, passed a statute
to constrain monopolies, against which financiers protested as being a species
of confiscation, and which the Chief Justice himself thought harsh. To this
statute the Supreme Court gave a harsh construction, as the Chief Justice had
more than once pointed out, when he was still an associate upon the bench. From
a series of these decisions an appeal had been made to Congress, and the Senate,
in the report from which I have quoted, had sustained the construction given to
the statute by the majority of his brethren with whom the Chief Justice
differed. Since the last of these decisions, however, the complexion of the
bench had been considerably changed by new appointments, much as it had been
after Hepburn <i>v</i>. Griswold, and an opportunity seemed to be presented to
conciliate every one.</p>
<p>In any other country than the United States, a chief justice so situated
would doubtless have affirmed the old precedents, permitting himself, at most,
to point out the mischief which, he thought, they worked. Not so a lawyer
nurtured under the American constitutional system, which breeds in the judge the
conviction that he is superior to the legislator. His instinct, under adequate
pressure, is always to overrule anything repugnant to him that a legitimate
legislative assembly may have done. In this instance, had the case been one of
first impression, nothing would have been easier than to have nullified the
Sherman Act as an unreasonable exercise of the Police Power, as judges had been
nullifying statutes of which they disapproved for a couple of generations
previously; but the case was not one of first impression. On the contrary, the
constitutionality of the Sherman Act had been so often upheld by the judiciary
that the Chief Justice himself admitted that so long as Congress allowed him to
use his reason, these "contentions [were] plainly foreclosed."
Therefore, for him the path of least resistance was to use his <i>reason</i>,
and, as a magistrate, to amend a statute which Congress ought to have amended,
but had <i>unreasonably</i> omitted to amend. Such was the final and logical
result of the blending of judicial and legislative functions in a court, as they
are blended under the American constitutional system. Nor is it unworthy of
remark, that the Chief Justice, in abstaining from questioning the
constitutionality of the act, expressly intimated that he did so because, by the
use of his reason, he could make that reasonable and constitutional which
otherwise might be unreasonable and unconstitutional. The defendants pressed the
argument that destroying the freedom of contract, as the Sherman Law destroyed
it, was to infringe upon the "constitutional guaranty of due process of
law." To this the Chief Justice rejoined: "But the ultimate foundation
of all these arguments is the assumption that reason may not be resorted to in
interpreting and applying the statute.... As the premise is demonstrated to be
unsound by the construction we have given the statute," these arguments
need no further notice.<SPAN name="FNanchor38"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_38"><sup>[38]</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>Should Congress amend the Sherman Act, as it seems somewhat disposed to do,
by explicitly enacting the rule of the Trans-Missouri Case, a grave issue would
be presented. The Chief Justice might submit, and thus avert, temporarily at
least, a clash; or, he might hold such an amendment unconstitutional as denying
to the Court the right to administer the law according to due process. A trial
of strength would then be imminent.</p>
<p>Nearly a century ago, Jefferson wrote to Spencer Roane, "The
Constitution, on this hypothesis, is a mere thing of wax in the hands of the
judiciary, which they may twist and shape into any form they please."<SPAN name="FNanchor39"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_39"><sup>[39]</sup></SPAN>
And however much we may recoil from admitting Jefferson's conclusion to be true,
it none the less remains the fact that it has proved itself to be true, and that
the people have recognized it to be true, and have taken measures to protect
themselves by bringing the judiciary under the same degree of control which they
enforce on other legislators. The progression has been steady and uniform, each
advance toward an assumption of the legislative function by the judiciary having
been counterbalanced by a corresponding extension of authority over the courts
by the people. First came the protest against Marbury and Madison in the
impeachment of Chase, because, as Giles explained, if judges were to annul laws,
the dominant party must have on the bench judges they could trust. Next the
Supreme Court of New York imagined the theory of the Police Power, which was
adopted by the Supreme Court of the United States in 1837. But it stood to
reason that if judges were to suspend constitutional limitations according to
their notions of reasonableness, the people must have the means of securing
judges whose views touching reasonableness coincided with their own. And behold,
within ten years, by the constitution of 1846, New York adopted an elective
judiciary.</p>
<p>Then followed the Dred Scott Case, the Civil War, and the attack on
legislative authority in Hepburn <i>v</i>. Griswold. Straightway the Court
received an admonition which it remembered for a generation. Somewhat forgetful
of this, on May 15, 1911, Chief Justice White gave his opinion in the Standard
Oil Case, which followed hard upon a number of state decisions intended to
override legislation upon several burning social issues. Forthwith, in 1912, the
proposition to submit all decisions involving a question of constitutional law
to a popular vote became an issue in a presidential election. Only one step
farther could be taken, and that we see being taken all about us. Experience has
shown, in New York and elsewhere, that an election, even for a somewhat short
term, does not bring the judge so immediately under popular control that
decisions objectionable to the majority may not be made. Hence the recall. The
degradation of the judicial function can, in theory at least, go no farther.
Thus the state courts may be said already to be prostrate, or likely shortly to
become prostrate. The United States courts alone remain, and, should there be a
struggle between them and Congress, the result can hardly be doubted. An event
has recently occurred abroad which we may do well to ponder.</p>
<p>Among European nations England has long represented intelligent conservatism,
and at the heart of her conservatism lay the House of Lords. Through many
centuries; and under many vicissitudes this ancient chamber had performed
functions of the highest moment, until of late it had come to occupy a position
not dissimilar to that which the Supreme Court of the United States yet holds.
On one side it was the highest legal tribunal of the Empire, on the other it was
a non-representative assembly, seldom indeed originating important legislation,
but enjoying an absolute veto on legislation sent it from the Commons. One day
in a moment of heated controversy the Lords vetoed a bill on which the Commons
had determined. A dissolution followed and the House of Lords, as a political
power, faded into a shadow; yet, notwithstanding this, its preeminence as a
court has remained intact. Were a similar clash to occur in America no such
result could be anticipated. Supposing a President, supported by a congressional
majority, were to formulate some policy no more subversive than that which has
been formulated by the present British Cabinet, and this policy were to be
resisted, as it surely would be, by potent financial interests, the conflicting
forces would converge upon the Supreme Court. The courts are always believed to
tend toward conservatism, therefore they are generally supported by the
conservative interest, both here and elsewhere. In this case a dilemma would be
presented. Either the judges would seek to give expression to
"preponderant" popular opinion, or they would legislate. In the one
event they would be worthless as a restraining influence. In the other, I
apprehend, a blow would fall similar to the blow which fell upon the House of
Lords, only it would cut deeper. Shearing the House of Lords of political power
did not dislocate the administration of English justice, because the law lords
are exclusively judges. They never legislate. Therefore no one denounced them.
Not even the wildest radical demanded that their tenure should be made elective,
much less that they should be subjected to the recall. With us an entirely
different problem would be presented for solution. A tribunal, nominally
judicial, would throw itself across the path of the national movement. It would
undertake to correct a disturbance of the social equilibrium. But what a
shifting of the social equilibrium means, and what follows upon tampering with
it, is a subject which demands a chapter by itself.<br/></p>
<hr style="width: 65%;">
<br/>
<br/>
<SPAN name="CHAPTER_IV"></SPAN>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />