<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0011" id="link2H_4_0011"></SPAN></p>
<h2> 9 </h2>
<p>From what we have said it will be seen that the poet's function is to
describe, not the thing that has happened, but a kind of thing that might
happen, i.e. what is possible as being probable or necessary. The
distinction between historian and poet is not in the one writing prose and
the other verse—you might put the work of Herodotus into verse, and
it would still be a species of history; it consists really in this, that
the one describes the thing that has been, and the other a kind of thing
that might be. Hence poetry is something more philosophic and of graver
import than history, since its statements are of the nature rather of
universals, whereas those of history are singulars. By a universal
statement I mean one as to what such or such a kind of man will probably
or necessarily say or do—which is the aim of poetry, though it
affixes proper names to the characters; by a singular statement, one as to
what, say, Alcibiades did or had done to him. In Comedy this has become
clear by this time; it is only when their plot is already made up of
probable incidents that they give it a basis of proper names, choosing for
the purpose any names that may occur to them, instead of writing like the
old iambic poets about particular persons. In Tragedy, however, they still
adhere to the historic names; and for this reason: what convinces is the
possible; now whereas we are not yet sure as to the possibility of that
which has not happened, that which has happened is manifestly possible,
else it would not have come to pass. Nevertheless even in Tragedy there
are some plays with but one or two known names in them, the rest being
inventions; and there are some without a single known name, e.g. Agathon's
Anthens, in which both incidents and names are of the poet's invention;
and it is no less delightful on that account. So that one must not aim at
a rigid adherence to the traditional stories on which tragedies are based.
It would be absurd, in fact, to do so, as even the known stories are only
known to a few, though they are a delight none the less to all.</p>
<p>It is evident from the above that, the poet must be more the poet of his
stories or Plots than of his verses, inasmuch as he is a poet by virtue of
the imitative element in his work, and it is actions that he imitates. And
if he should come to take a subject from actual history, he is none the
less a poet for that; since some historic occurrences may very well be in
the probable and possible order of things; and it is in that aspect of
them that he is their poet.</p>
<p>Of simple Plots and actions the episodic are the worst. I call a Plot
episodic when there is neither probability nor necessity in the sequence
of episodes. Actions of this sort bad poets construct through their own
fault, and good ones on account of the players. His work being for public
performance, a good poet often stretches out a Plot beyond its
capabilities, and is thus obliged to twist the sequence of incident.</p>
<p>Tragedy, however, is an imitation not only of a complete action, but also
of incidents arousing pity and fear. Such incidents have the very greatest
effect on the mind when they occur unexpectedly and at the same time in
consequence of one another; there is more of the marvellous in them then
than if they happened of themselves or by mere chance. Even matters of
chance seem most marvellous if there is an appearance of design as it were
in them; as for instance the statue of Mitys at Argos killed the author of
Mitys' death by falling down on him when a looker-on at a public
spectacle; for incidents like that we think to be not without a meaning. A
Plot, therefore, of this sort is necessarily finer than others.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0012" id="link2H_4_0012"></SPAN></p>
<h2> 10 </h2>
<p>Plots are either simple or complex, since the actions they represent are
naturally of this twofold description. The action, proceeding in the way
defined, as one continuous whole, I call simple, when the change in the
hero's fortunes takes place without Peripety or Discovery; and complex,
when it involves one or the other, or both. These should each of them
arise out of the structure of the Plot itself, so as to be the
consequence, necessary or probable, of the antecedents. There is a great
difference between a thing happening <i>propter hoc</i> and <i>post hoc</i>.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0013" id="link2H_4_0013"></SPAN></p>
<h2> 11 </h2>
<p>A Peripety is the change from one state of things within the play to its
opposite of the kind described, and that too in the way we are saying, in
the probable or necessary sequence of events; as it is for instance in <i>Oedipus</i>:
here the opposite state of things is produced by the Messenger, who,
coming to gladden Oedipus and to remove his fears as to his mother,
reveals the secret of his birth. And in <i>Lynceus</i>: just as he is
being led off for execution, with Danaus at his side to put him to death,
the incidents preceding this bring it about that he is saved and Danaus
put to death. A Discovery is, as the very word implies, a change from
ignorance to knowledge, and thus to either love or hate, in the personages
marked for good or evil fortune. The finest form of Discovery is one
attended by Peripeties, like that which goes with the Discovery in <i>Oedipus</i>.
There are no doubt other forms of it; what we have said may happen in a
way in reference to inanimate things, even things of a very casual kind;
and it is also possible to discover whether some one has done or not done
something. But the form most directly connected with the Plot and the
action of the piece is the first-mentioned. This, with a Peripety, will
arouse either pity or fear—actions of that nature being what Tragedy
is assumed to represent; and it will also serve to bring about the happy
or unhappy ending. The Discovery, then, being of persons, it may be that
of one party only to the other, the latter being already known; or both
the parties may have to discover themselves. Iphigenia, for instance, was
discovered to Orestes by sending the letter; and another Discovery was
required to reveal him to Iphigenia.</p>
<p>Two parts of the Plot, then, Peripety and Discovery, are on matters of
this sort. A third part is Suffering; which we may define as an action of
a destructive or painful nature, such as murders on the stage, tortures,
woundings, and the like. The other two have been already explained.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0014" id="link2H_4_0014"></SPAN></p>
<h2> 12 </h2>
<p>The parts of Tragedy to be treated as formative elements in the whole were
mentioned in a previous Chapter. From the point of view, however, of its
quantity, i.e. the separate sections into which it is divided, a tragedy
has the following parts: Prologue, Episode, Exode, and a choral portion,
distinguished into Parode and Stasimon; these two are common to all
tragedies, whereas songs from the stage and Commoe are only found in some.
The Prologue is all that precedes the Parode of the chorus; an Episode all
that comes in between two whole choral songs; the Exode all that follows
after the last choral song. In the choral portion the Parode is the whole
first statement of the chorus; a Stasimon, a song of the chorus without
anapaests or trochees; a Commas, a lamentation sung by chorus and actor in
concert. The parts of Tragedy to be used as formative elements in the
whole we have already mentioned; the above are its parts from the point of
view of its quantity, or the separate sections into which it is divided.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0015" id="link2H_4_0015"></SPAN></p>
<h2> 13 </h2>
<p>The next points after what we have said above will be these: (1) What is
the poet to aim at, and what is he to avoid, in constructing his Plots?
and (2) What are the conditions on which the tragic effect depends?</p>
<p>We assume that, for the finest form of Tragedy, the Plot must be not
simple but complex; and further, that it must imitate actions arousing
pity and fear, since that is the distinctive function of this kind of
imitation. It follows, therefore, that there are three forms of Plot to be
avoided. (1) A good man must not be seen passing from happiness to misery,
or (2) a bad man from misery to happiness.</p>
<p>The first situation is not fear-inspiring or piteous, but simply odious to
us. The second is the most untragic that can be; it has no one of the
requisites of Tragedy; it does not appeal either to the human feeling in
us, or to our pity, or to our fears. Nor, on the other hand, should (3) an
extremely bad man be seen falling from happiness into misery. Such a story
may arouse the human feeling in us, but it will not move us to either pity
or fear; pity is occasioned by undeserved misfortune, and fear by that of
one like ourselves; so that there will be nothing either piteous or
fear-inspiring in the situation. There remains, then, the intermediate
kind of personage, a man not pre-eminently virtuous and just, whose
misfortune, however, is brought upon him not by vice and depravity but by
some error of judgement, of the number of those in the enjoyment of great
reputation and prosperity; e.g. Oedipus, Thyestes, and the men of note of
similar families. The perfect Plot, accordingly, must have a single, and
not (as some tell us) a double issue; the change in the hero's fortunes
must be not from misery to happiness, but on the contrary from happiness
to misery; and the cause of it must lie not in any depravity, but in some
great error on his part; the man himself being either such as we have
described, or better, not worse, than that. Fact also confirms our theory.
Though the poets began by accepting any tragic story that came to hand, in
these days the finest tragedies are always on the story of some few
houses, on that of Alemeon, Oedipus, Orestes, Meleager, Thyestes,
Telephus, or any others that may have been involved, as either agents or
sufferers, in some deed of horror. The theoretically best tragedy, then,
has a Plot of this description. The critics, therefore, are wrong who
blame Euripides for taking this line in his tragedies, and giving many of
them an unhappy ending. It is, as we have said, the right line to take.
The best proof is this: on the stage, and in the public performances, such
plays, properly worked out, are seen to be the most truly tragic; and
Euripides, even if his elecution be faulty in every other point, is seen
to be nevertheless the most tragic certainly of the dramatists. After this
comes the construction of Plot which some rank first, one with a double
story (like the <i>Odyssey</i>) and an opposite issue for the good and the
bad personages. It is ranked as first only through the weakness of the
audiences; the poets merely follow their public, writing as its wishes
dictate. But the pleasure here is not that of Tragedy. It belongs rather
to Comedy, where the bitterest enemies in the piece (e.g. Orestes and
Aegisthus) walk off good friends at the end, with no slaying of any one by
any one.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />