<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0001" id="link2HCH0001"></SPAN></p>
<h2> Chapter One ~~ Introductory </h2>
<p>The institution of a leisure class is found in its best development at the
higher stages of the barbarian culture; as, for instance, in feudal Europe
or feudal Japan. In such communities the distinction between classes is
very rigorously observed; and the feature of most striking economic
significance in these class differences is the distinction maintained
between the employments proper to the several classes. The upper classes
are by custom exempt or excluded from industrial occupations, and are
reserved for certain employments to which a degree of honour attaches.
Chief among the honourable employments in any feudal community is warfare;
and priestly service is commonly second to warfare. If the barbarian
community is not notably warlike, the priestly office may take the
precedence, with that of the warrior second. But the rule holds with but
slight exceptions that, whether warriors or priests, the upper classes are
exempt from industrial employments, and this exemption is the economic
expression of their superior rank. Brahmin India affords a fair
illustration of the industrial exemption of both these classes. In the
communities belonging to the higher barbarian culture there is a
considerable differentiation of sub-classes within what may be
comprehensively called the leisure class; and there is a corresponding
differentiation of employments between these sub-classes. The leisure
class as a whole comprises the noble and the priestly classes, together
with much of their retinue. The occupations of the class are
correspondingly diversified; but they have the common economic
characteristic of being non-industrial. These non-industrial upper-class
occupations may be roughly comprised under government, warfare, religious
observances, and sports.</p>
<p>At an earlier, but not the earliest, stage of barbarism, the leisure class
is found in a less differentiated form. Neither the class distinctions nor
the distinctions between leisure-class occupations are so minute and
intricate. The Polynesian islanders generally show this stage of the
development in good form, with the exception that, owing to the absence of
large game, hunting does not hold the usual place of honour in their
scheme of life. The Icelandic community in the time of the Sagas also
affords a fair instance. In such a community there is a rigorous
distinction between classes and between the occupations peculiar to each
class. Manual labour, industry, whatever has to do directly with the
everyday work of getting a livelihood, is the exclusive occupation of the
inferior class. This inferior class includes slaves and other dependents,
and ordinarily also all the women. If there are several grades of
aristocracy, the women of high rank are commonly exempt from industrial
employment, or at least from the more vulgar kinds of manual labour. The
men of the upper classes are not only exempt, but by prescriptive custom
they are debarred, from all industrial occupations. The range of
employments open to them is rigidly defined. As on the higher plane
already spoken of, these employments are government, warfare, religious
observances, and sports. These four lines of activity govern the scheme of
life of the upper classes, and for the highest rank—the kings or
chieftains—these are the only kinds of activity that custom or the
common sense of the community will allow. Indeed, where the scheme is well
developed even sports are accounted doubtfully legitimate for the members
of the highest rank. To the lower grades of the leisure class certain
other employments are open, but they are employments that are subsidiary
to one or another of these typical leisure-class occupations. Such are,
for instance, the manufacture and care of arms and accoutrements and of
war canoes, the dressing and handling of horses, dogs, and hawks, the
preparation of sacred apparatus, etc. The lower classes are excluded from
these secondary honourable employments, except from such as are plainly of
an industrial character and are only remotely related to the typical
leisure-class occupations.</p>
<p>If we go a step back of this exemplary barbarian culture, into the lower
stages of barbarism, we no longer find the leisure class in fully
developed form. But this lower barbarism shows the usages, motives, and
circumstances out of which the institution of a leisure class has arisen,
and indicates the steps of its early growth. Nomadic hunting tribes in
various parts of the world illustrate these more primitive phases of the
differentiation. Any one of the North American hunting tribes may be taken
as a convenient illustration. These tribes can scarcely be said to have a
defined leisure class. There is a differentiation of function, and there
is a distinction between classes on the basis of this difference of
function, but the exemption of the superior class from work has not gone
far enough to make the designation "leisure class" altogether applicable.
The tribes belonging on this economic level have carried the economic
differentiation to the point at which a marked distinction is made between
the occupations of men and women, and this distinction is of an invidious
character. In nearly all these tribes the women are, by prescriptive
custom, held to those employments out of which the industrial occupations
proper develop at the next advance. The men are exempt from these vulgar
employments and are reserved for war, hunting, sports, and devout
observances. A very nice discrimination is ordinarily shown in this
matter.</p>
<p>This division of labour coincides with the distinction between the working
and the leisure class as it appears in the higher barbarian culture. As
the diversification and specialisation of employments proceed, the line of
demarcation so drawn comes to divide the industrial from the
non-industrial employments. The man's occupation as it stands at the
earlier barbarian stage is not the original out of which any appreciable
portion of later industry has developed. In the later development it
survives only in employments that are not classed as industrial,—war,
politics, sports, learning, and the priestly office. The only notable
exceptions are a portion of the fishery industry and certain slight
employments that are doubtfully to be classed as industry; such as the
manufacture of arms, toys, and sporting goods. Virtually the whole range
of industrial employments is an outgrowth of what is classed as woman's
work in the primitive barbarian community.</p>
<p>The work of the men in the lower barbarian culture is no less
indispensable to the life of the group than the work done by the women. It
may even be that the men's work contributes as much to the food supply and
the other necessary consumption of the group. Indeed, so obvious is this
"productive" character of the men's work that in the conventional economic
writings the hunter's work is taken as the type of primitive industry. But
such is not the barbarian's sense of the matter. In his own eyes he is not
a labourer, and he is not to be classed with the women in this respect;
nor is his effort to be classed with the women's drudgery, as labour or
industry, in such a sense as to admit of its being confounded with the
latter. There is in all barbarian communities a profound sense of the
disparity between man's and woman's work. His work may conduce to the
maintenance of the group, but it is felt that it does so through an
excellence and an efficacy of a kind that cannot without derogation be
compared with the uneventful diligence of the women.</p>
<p>At a farther step backward in the cultural scale—among savage groups—the
differentiation of employments is still less elaborate and the invidious
distinction between classes and employments is less consistent and less
rigorous. Unequivocal instances of a primitive savage culture are hard to
find. Few of these groups or communities that are classed as "savage" show
no traces of regression from a more advanced cultural stage. But there are
groups—some of them apparently not the result of retrogression—which
show the traits of primitive savagery with some fidelity. Their culture
differs from that of the barbarian communities in the absence of a leisure
class and the absence, in great measure, of the animus or spiritual
attitude on which the institution of a leisure class rests. These
communities of primitive savages in which there is no hierarchy of
economic classes make up but a small and inconspicuous fraction of the
human race. As good an instance of this phase of culture as may be had is
afforded by the tribes of the Andamans, or by the Todas of the Nilgiri
Hills. The scheme of life of these groups at the time of their earliest
contact with Europeans seems to have been nearly typical, so far as
regards the absence of a leisure class. As a further instance might be
cited the Ainu of Yezo, and, more doubtfully, also some Bushman and Eskimo
groups. Some Pueblo communities are less confidently to be included in the
same class. Most, if not all, of the communities here cited may well be
cases of degeneration from a higher barbarism, rather than bearers of a
culture that has never risen above its present level. If so, they are for
the present purpose to be taken with the allowance, but they may serve
none the less as evidence to the same effect as if they were really
"primitive" populations.</p>
<p>These communities that are without a defined leisure class resemble one
another also in certain other features of their social structure and
manner of life. They are small groups and of a simple (archaic) structure;
they are commonly peaceable and sedentary; they are poor; and individual
ownership is not a dominant feature of their economic system. At the same
time it does not follow that these are the smallest of existing
communities, or that their social structure is in all respects the least
differentiated; nor does the class necessarily include all primitive
communities which have no defined system of individual ownership. But it
is to be noted that the class seems to include the most peaceable—perhaps
all the characteristically peaceable—primitive groups of men.
Indeed, the most notable trait common to members of such communities is a
certain amiable inefficiency when confronted with force or fraud.</p>
<p>The evidence afforded by the usages and cultural traits of communities at
a low stage of development indicates that the institution of a leisure
class has emerged gradually during the transition from primitive savagery
to barbarism; or more precisely, during the transition from a peaceable to
a consistently warlike habit of life. The conditions apparently necessary
to its emergence in a consistent form are: (1) the community must be of a
predatory habit of life (war or the hunting of large game or both); that
is to say, the men, who constitute the inchoate leisure class in these
cases, must be habituated to the infliction of injury by force and
stratagem; (2) subsistence must be obtainable on sufficiently easy terms
to admit of the exemption of a considerable portion of the community from
steady application to a routine of labour. The institution of leisure
class is the outgrowth of an early discrimination between employments,
according to which some employments are worthy and others unworthy. Under
this ancient distinction the worthy employments are those which may be
classed as exploit; unworthy are those necessary everyday employments into
which no appreciable element of exploit enters.</p>
<p>This distinction has but little obvious significance in a modern
industrial community, and it has, therefore, received but slight attention
at the hands of economic writers. When viewed in the light of that modern
common sense which has guided economic discussion, it seems formal and
insubstantial. But it persists with great tenacity as a commonplace
preconception even in modern life, as is shown, for instance, by our
habitual aversion to menial employments. It is a distinction of a personal
kind—of superiority and inferiority. In the earlier stages of
culture, when the personal force of the individual counted more
immediately and obviously in shaping the course of events, the element of
exploit counted for more in the everyday scheme of life. Interest centred
about this fact to a greater degree. Consequently a distinction proceeding
on this ground seemed more imperative and more definitive then than is the
case to-day. As a fact in the sequence of development, therefore, the
distinction is a substantial one and rests on sufficiently valid and
cogent grounds.</p>
<p>The ground on which a discrimination between facts is habitually made
changes as the interest from which the facts are habitually viewed
changes. Those features of the facts at hand are salient and substantial
upon which the dominant interest of the time throws its light. Any given
ground of distinction will seem insubstantial to any one who habitually
apprehends the facts in question from a different point of view and values
them for a different purpose. The habit of distinguishing and classifying
the various purposes and directions of activity prevails of necessity
always and everywhere; for it is indispensable in reaching a working
theory or scheme of life. The particular point of view, or the particular
characteristic that is pitched upon as definitive in the classification of
the facts of life depends upon the interest from which a discrimination of
the facts is sought. The grounds of discrimination, and the norm of
procedure in classifying the facts, therefore, progressively change as the
growth of culture proceeds; for the end for which the facts of life are
apprehended changes, and the point of view consequently changes also. So
that what are recognised as the salient and decisive features of a class
of activities or of a social class at one stage of culture will not retain
the same relative importance for the purposes of classification at any
subsequent stage.</p>
<p>But the change of standards and points of view is gradual only, and it
seldom results in the subversion or entire suppression of a standpoint
once accepted. A distinction is still habitually made between industrial
and non-industrial occupations; and this modern distinction is a
transmuted form of the barbarian distinction between exploit and drudgery.
Such employments as warfare, politics, public worship, and public
merrymaking, are felt, in the popular apprehension, to differ
intrinsically from the labour that has to do with elaborating the material
means of life. The precise line of demarcation is not the same as it was
in the early barbarian scheme, but the broad distinction has not fallen
into disuse.</p>
<p>The tacit, common-sense distinction to-day is, in effect, that any effort
is to be accounted industrial only so far as its ultimate purpose is the
utilisation of non-human things. The coercive utilisation of man by man is
not felt to be an industrial function; but all effort directed to enhance
human life by taking advantage of the non-human environment is classed
together as industrial activity. By the economists who have best retained
and adapted the classical tradition, man's "power over nature" is
currently postulated as the characteristic fact of industrial
productivity. This industrial power over nature is taken to include man's
power over the life of the beasts and over all the elemental forces. A
line is in this way drawn between mankind and brute creation.</p>
<p>In other times and among men imbued with a different body of
preconceptions this line is not drawn precisely as we draw it to-day. In
the savage or the barbarian scheme of life it is drawn in a different
place and in another way. In all communities under the barbarian culture
there is an alert and pervading sense of antithesis between two
comprehensive groups of phenomena, in one of which barbarian man includes
himself, and in the other, his victual. There is a felt antithesis between
economic and non-economic phenomena, but it is not conceived in the modern
fashion; it lies not between man and brute creation, but between animate
and inert things.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />