<p>It may be an excess of caution at this day to explain that the barbarian
notion which it is here intended to convey by the term "animate" is not
the same as would be conveyed by the word "living". The term does not
cover all living things, and it does cover a great many others. Such a
striking natural phenomenon as a storm, a disease, a waterfall, are
recognised as "animate"; while fruits and herbs, and even inconspicuous
animals, such as house-flies, maggots, lemmings, sheep, are not ordinarily
apprehended as "animate" except when taken collectively. As here used the
term does not necessarily imply an indwelling soul or spirit. The concept
includes such things as in the apprehension of the animistic savage or
barbarian are formidable by virtue of a real or imputed habit of
initiating action. This category comprises a large number and range of
natural objects and phenomena. Such a distinction between the inert and
the active is still present in the habits of thought of unreflecting
persons, and it still profoundly affects the prevalent theory of human
life and of natural processes; but it does not pervade our daily life to
the extent or with the far-reaching practical consequences that are
apparent at earlier stages of culture and belief.</p>
<p>To the mind of the barbarian, the elaboration and utilisation of what is
afforded by inert nature is activity on quite a different plane from his
dealings with "animate" things and forces. The line of demarcation may be
vague and shifting, but the broad distinction is sufficiently real and
cogent to influence the barbarian scheme of life. To the class of things
apprehended as animate, the barbarian fancy imputes an unfolding of
activity directed to some end. It is this teleological unfolding of
activity that constitutes any object or phenomenon an "animate" fact.
Wherever the unsophisticated savage or barbarian meets with activity that
is at all obtrusive, he construes it in the only terms that are ready to
hand—the terms immediately given in his consciousness of his own
actions. Activity is, therefore, assimilated to human action, and active
objects are in so far assimilated to the human agent. Phenomena of this
character—especially those whose behaviour is notably formidable or
baffling—have to be met in a different spirit and with proficiency
of a different kind from what is required in dealing with inert things. To
deal successfully with such phenomena is a work of exploit rather than of
industry. It is an assertion of prowess, not of diligence.</p>
<p>Under the guidance of this naive discrimination between the inert and the
animate, the activities of the primitive social group tend to fall into
two classes, which would in modern phrase be called exploit and industry.
Industry is effort that goes to create a new thing, with a new purpose
given it by the fashioning hand of its maker out of passive ("brute")
material; while exploit, so far as it results in an outcome useful to the
agent, is the conversion to his own ends of energies previously directed
to some other end by an other agent. We still speak of "brute matter" with
something of the barbarian's realisation of a profound significance in the
term.</p>
<p>The distinction between exploit and drudgery coincides with a difference
between the sexes. The sexes differ, not only in stature and muscular
force, but perhaps even more decisively in temperament, and this must
early have given rise to a corresponding division of labour. The general
range of activities that come under the head of exploit falls to the males
as being the stouter, more massive, better capable of a sudden and violent
strain, and more readily inclined to self assertion, active emulation, and
aggression. The difference in mass, in physiological character, and in
temperament may be slight among the members of the primitive group; it
appears, in fact, to be relatively slight and inconsequential in some of
the more archaic communities with which we are acquainted—as for
instance the tribes of the Andamans. But so soon as a differentiation of
function has well begun on the lines marked out by this difference in
physique and animus, the original difference between the sexes will itself
widen. A cumulative process of selective adaptation to the new
distribution of employments will set in, especially if the habitat or the
fauna with which the group is in contact is such as to call for a
considerable exercise of the sturdier virtues. The habitual pursuit of
large game requires more of the manly qualities of massiveness, agility,
and ferocity, and it can therefore scarcely fail to hasten and widen the
differentiation of functions between the sexes. And so soon as the group
comes into hostile contact with other groups, the divergence of function
will take on the developed form of a distinction between exploit and
industry.</p>
<p>In such a predatory group of hunters it comes to be the able-bodied men's
office to fight and hunt. The women do what other work there is to do—other
members who are unfit for man's work being for this purpose classed with
women. But the men's hunting and fighting are both of the same general
character. Both are of a predatory nature; the warrior and the hunter
alike reap where they have not strewn. Their aggressive assertion of force
and sagacity differs obviously from the women's assiduous and uneventful
shaping of materials; it is not to be accounted productive labour but
rather an acquisition of substance by seizure. Such being the barbarian
man's work, in its best development and widest divergence from women's
work, any effort that does not involve an assertion of prowess comes to be
unworthy of the man. As the tradition gains consistency, the common sense
of the community erects it into a canon of conduct; so that no employment
and no acquisition is morally possible to the self respecting man at this
cultural stage, except such as proceeds on the basis of prowess—force
or fraud. When the predatory habit of life has been settled upon the group
by long habituation, it becomes the able-bodied man's accredited office in
the social economy to kill, to destroy such competitors in the struggle
for existence as attempt to resist or elude him, to overcome and reduce to
subservience those alien forces that assert themselves refractorily in the
environment. So tenaciously and with such nicety is this theoretical
distinction between exploit and drudgery adhered to that in many hunting
tribes the man must not bring home the game which he has killed, but must
send his woman to perform that baser office.</p>
<p>As has already been indicated, the distinction between exploit and
drudgery is an invidious distinction between employments. Those
employments which are to be classed as exploit are worthy, honourable,
noble; other employments, which do not contain this element of exploit,
and especially those which imply subservience or submission, are unworthy,
debasing, ignoble. The concept of dignity, worth, or honour, as applied
either to persons or conduct, is of first-rate consequence in the
development of classes and of class distinctions, and it is therefore
necessary to say something of its derivation and meaning. Its
psychological ground may be indicated in outline as follows.</p>
<p>As a matter of selective necessity, man is an agent. He is, in his own
apprehension, a centre of unfolding impulsive activity—"teleological"
activity. He is an agent seeking in every act the accomplishment of some
concrete, objective, impersonal end. By force of his being such an agent
he is possessed of a taste for effective work, and a distaste for futile
effort. He has a sense of the merit of serviceability or efficiency and of
the demerit of futility, waste, or incapacity. This aptitude or propensity
may be called the instinct of workmanship. Wherever the circumstances or
traditions of life lead to an habitual comparison of one person with
another in point of efficiency, the instinct of workmanship works out in
an emulative or invidious comparison of persons. The extent to which this
result follows depends in some considerable degree on the temperament of
the population. In any community where such an invidious comparison of
persons is habitually made, visible success becomes an end sought for its
own utility as a basis of esteem. Esteem is gained and dispraise is
avoided by putting one's efficiency in evidence. The result is that the
instinct of workmanship works out in an emulative demonstration of force.</p>
<p>During that primitive phase of social development, when the community is
still habitually peaceable, perhaps sedentary, and without a developed
system of individual ownership, the efficiency of the individual can be
shown chiefly and most consistently in some employment that goes to
further the life of the group. What emulation of an economic kind there is
between the members of such a group will be chiefly emulation in
industrial serviceability. At the same time the incentive to emulation is
not strong, nor is the scope for emulation large.</p>
<p>When the community passes from peaceable savagery to a predatory phase of
life, the conditions of emulation change. The opportunity and the
incentive to emulate increase greatly in scope and urgency. The activity
of the men more and more takes on the character of exploit; and an
invidious comparison of one hunter or warrior with another grows
continually easier and more habitual. Tangible evidences of prowess—trophies—find
a place in men's habits of thought as an essential feature of the
paraphernalia of life. Booty, trophies of the chase or of the raid, come
to be prized as evidence of pre-eminent force. Aggression becomes the
accredited form of action, and booty serves as prima facie evidence of
successful aggression. As accepted at this cultural stage, the accredited,
worthy form of self-assertion is contest; and useful articles or services
obtained by seizure or compulsion, serve as a conventional evidence of
successful contest. Therefore, by contrast, the obtaining of goods by
other methods than seizure comes to be accounted unworthy of man in his
best estate. The performance of productive work, or employment in personal
service, falls under the same odium for the same reason. An invidious
distinction in this way arises between exploit and acquisition on the
other hand. Labour acquires a character of irksomeness by virtue of the
indignity imputed to it.</p>
<p>With the primitive barbarian, before the simple content of the notion has
been obscured by its own ramifications and by a secondary growth of
cognate ideas, "honourable" seems to connote nothing else than assertion
of superior force. "Honourable" is "formidable"; "worthy" is "prepotent".
A honorific act is in the last analysis little if anything else than a
recognised successful act of aggression; and where aggression means
conflict with men and beasts, the activity which comes to be especially
and primarily honourable is the assertion of the strong hand. The naive,
archaic habit of construing all manifestations of force in terms of
personality or "will power" greatly fortifies this conventional exaltation
of the strong hand. Honorific epithets, in vogue among barbarian tribes as
well as among peoples of a more advance culture, commonly bear the stamp
of this unsophisticated sense of honour. Epithets and titles used in
addressing chieftains, and in the propitiation of kings and gods, very
commonly impute a propensity for overbearing violence and an irresistible
devastating force to the person who is to be propitiated. This holds true
to an extent also in the more civilised communities of the present day.
The predilection shown in heraldic devices for the more rapacious beasts
and birds of prey goes to enforce the same view.</p>
<p>Under this common-sense barbarian appreciation of worth or honour, the
taking of life—the killing of formidable competitors, whether brute
or human—is honourable in the highest degree. And this high office
of slaughter, as an expression of the slayer's prepotence, casts a glamour
of worth over every act of slaughter and over all the tools and
accessories of the act. Arms are honourable, and the use of them, even in
seeking the life of the meanest creatures of the fields, becomes a
honorific employment. At the same time, employment in industry becomes
correspondingly odious, and, in the common-sense apprehension, the
handling of the tools and implements of industry falls beneath the dignity
of able-bodied men. Labour becomes irksome.</p>
<p>It is here assumed that in the sequence of cultural evolution primitive
groups of men have passed from an initial peaceable stage to a subsequent
stage at which fighting is the avowed and characteristic employment of the
group. But it is not implied that there has been an abrupt transition from
unbroken peace and good-will to a later or higher phase of life in which
the fact of combat occurs for the first time. Neither is it implied that
all peaceful industry disappears on the transition to the predatory phase
of culture. Some fighting, it is safe to say, would be met with at any
early stage of social development. Fights would occur with more or less
frequency through sexual competition. The known habits of primitive
groups, as well as the habits of the anthropoid apes, argue to that
effect, and the evidence from the well-known promptings of human nature
enforces the same view.</p>
<p>It may therefore be objected that there can have been no such initial
stage of peaceable life as is here assumed. There is no point in cultural
evolution prior to which fighting does not occur. But the point in
question is not as to the occurrence of combat, occasional or sporadic, or
even more or less frequent and habitual; it is a question as to the
occurrence of an habitual; it is a question as to the occurrence of an
habitual bellicose frame of mind—a prevalent habit of judging facts
and events from the point of view of the fight. The predatory phase of
culture is attained only when the predatory attitude has become the
habitual and accredited spiritual attitude for the members of the group;
when the fight has become the dominant note in the current theory of life;
when the common-sense appreciation of men and things has come to be an
appreciation with a view to combat.</p>
<p>The substantial difference between the peaceable and the predatory phase
of culture, therefore, is a spiritual difference, not a mechanical one.
The change in spiritual attitude is the outgrowth of a change in the
material facts of the life of the group, and it comes on gradually as the
material circumstances favourable to a predatory attitude supervene. The
inferior limit of the predatory culture is an industrial limit. Predation
can not become the habitual, conventional resource of any group or any
class until industrial methods have been developed to such a degree of
efficiency as to leave a margin worth fighting for, above the subsistence
of those engaged in getting a living. The transition from peace to
predation therefore depends on the growth of technical knowledge and the
use of tools. A predatory culture is similarly impracticable in early
times, until weapons have been developed to such a point as to make man a
formidable animal. The early development of tools and of weapons is of
course the same fact seen from two different points of view.</p>
<p>The life of a given group would be characterised as peaceable so long as
habitual recourse to combat has not brought the fight into the foreground
in men's every day thoughts, as a dominant feature of the life of man. A
group may evidently attain such a predatory attitude with a greater or
less degree of completeness, so that its scheme of life and canons of
conduct may be controlled to a greater or less extent by the predatory
animus. The predatory phase of culture is therefore conceived to come on
gradually, through a cumulative growth of predatory aptitudes habits, and
traditions this growth being due to a change in the circumstances of the
group's life, of such a kind as to develop and conserve those traits of
human nature and those traditions and norms of conduct that make for a
predatory rather than a peaceable life.</p>
<p>The evidence for the hypothesis that there has been such a peaceable stage
of primitive culture is in great part drawn from psychology rather than
from ethnology, and cannot be detailed here. It will be recited in part in
a later chapter, in discussing the survival of archaic traits of human
nature under the modern culture.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />