<p>The fact that the usages, actions, and views of the well-to-do leisure
class acquire the character of a prescriptive canon of conduct for the
rest of society, gives added weight and reach to the conservative
influence of that class. It makes it incumbent upon all reputable people
to follow their lead. So that, by virtue of its high position as the
avatar of good form, the wealthier class comes to exert a retarding
influence upon social development far in excess of that which the simple
numerical strength of the class would assign it. Its prescriptive example
acts to greatly stiffen the resistance of all other classes against any
innovation, and to fix men's affections upon the good institutions handed
down from an earlier generation. There is a second way in which the
influence of the leisure class acts in the same direction, so far as
concerns hindrance to the adoption of a conventional scheme of life more
in accord with the exigencies of the time. This second method of
upper-class guidance is not in strict consistency to be brought under the
same category as the instinctive conservatism and aversion to new modes of
thought just spoken of; but it may as well be dealt with here, since it
has at least this much in common with the conservative habit of mind that
it acts to retard innovation and the growth of social structure. The code
of proprieties, conventionalities, and usages in vogue at any given time
and among any given people has more or less of the character of an organic
whole; so that any appreciable change in one point of the scheme involves
something of a change or readjustment at other points also, if not a
reorganization all along the line. When a change is made which immediately
touches only a minor point in the scheme, the consequent derangement of
the structure of conventionalities may be inconspicuous; but even in such
a case it is safe to say that some derangement of the general scheme, more
or less far-reaching, will follow. On the other hand, when an attempted
reform involves the suppression or thorough-going remodelling of an
institution of first-rate importance in the conventional scheme, it is
immediately felt that a serious derangement of the entire scheme would
result; it is felt that a readjustment of the structure to the new form
taken on by one of its chief elements would be a painful and tedious, if
not a doubtful process.</p>
<p>In order to realize the difficulty which such a radical change in any one
feature of the conventional scheme of life would involve, it is only
necessary to suggest the suppression of the monogamic family, or of the
agnatic system of consanguinity, or of private property, or of the
theistic faith, in any country of the Western civilization; or suppose the
suppression of ancestor worship in China, or of the caste system in india,
or of slavery in Africa, or the establishment of equality of the sexes in
Mohammedan countries. It needs no argument to show that the derangement of
the general structure of conventionalities in any of these cases would be
very considerable. In order to effect such an innovation a very
far-reaching alteration of men's habits of thought would be involved also
at other points of the scheme than the one immediately in question. The
aversion to any such innovation amounts to a shrinking from an essentially
alien scheme of life.</p>
<p>The revulsion felt by good people at any proposed departure from the
accepted methods of life is a familiar fact of everyday experience. It is
not unusual to hear those persons who dispense salutary advice and
admonition to the community express themselves forcibly upon the
far-reaching pernicious effects which the community would suffer from such
relatively slight changes as the disestablishment of the Anglican Church,
an increased facility of divorce, adoption of female suffrage, prohibition
of the manufacture and sale of intoxicating beverages, abolition or
restriction of inheritances, etc. Any one of these innovations would, we
are told, "shake the social structure to its base," "reduce society to
chaos," "subvert the foundations of morality," "make life intolerable,"
"confound the order of nature," etc. These various locutions are, no
doubt, of the nature of hyperbole; but, at the same time, like all
overstatement, they are evidence of a lively sense of the gravity of the
consequences which they are intended to describe. The effect of these and
like innovations in deranging the accepted scheme of life is felt to be of
much graver consequence than the simple alteration of an isolated item in
a series of contrivances for the convenience of men in society. What is
true in so obvious a degree of innovations of first-rate importance is
true in a less degree of changes of a smaller immediate importance. The
aversion to change is in large part an aversion to the bother of making
the readjustment which any given change will necessitate; and this
solidarity of the system of institutions of any given culture or of any
given people strengthens the instinctive resistance offered to any change
in men's habits of thought, even in matters which, taken by themselves,
are of minor importance. A consequence of this increased reluctance, due
to the solidarity of human institutions, is that any innovation calls for
a greater expenditure of nervous energy in making the necessary
readjustment than would otherwise be the case. It is not only that a
change in established habits of thought is distasteful. The process of
readjustment of the accepted theory of life involves a degree of mental
effort—a more or less protracted and laborious effort to find and to
keep one's bearings under the altered circumstances. This process requires
a certain expenditure of energy, and so presumes, for its successful
accomplishment, some surplus of energy beyond that absorbed in the daily
struggle for subsistence. Consequently it follows that progress is
hindered by underfeeding and excessive physical hardship, no less
effectually than by such a luxurious life as will shut out discontent by
cutting off the occasion for it. The abjectly poor, and all those persons
whose energies are entirely absorbed by the struggle for daily sustenance,
are conservative because they cannot afford the effort of taking thought
for the day after tomorrow; just as the highly prosperous are conservative
because they have small occasion to be discontented with the situation as
it stands today.</p>
<p>From this proposition it follows that the institution of a leisure class
acts to make the lower classes conservative by withdrawing from them as
much as it may of the means of sustenance, and so reducing their
consumption, and consequently their available energy, to such a point as
to make them incapable of the effort required for the learning and
adoption of new habits of thought. The accumulation of wealth at the upper
end of the pecuniary scale implies privation at the lower end of the
scale. It is a commonplace that, wherever it occurs, a considerable degree
of privation among the body of the people is a serious obstacle to any
innovation.</p>
<p>This direct inhibitory effect of the unequal distribution of wealth is
seconded by an indirect effect tending to the same result. As has already
been seen, the imperative example set by the upper class in fixing the
canons of reputability fosters the practice of conspicuous consumption.
The prevalence of conspicuous consumption as one of the main elements in
the standard of decency among all classes is of course not traceable
wholly to the example of the wealthy leisure class, but the practice and
the insistence on it are no doubt strengthened by the example of the
leisure class. The requirements of decency in this matter are very
considerable and very imperative; so that even among classes whose
pecuniary position is sufficiently strong to admit a consumption of goods
considerably in excess of the subsistence minimum, the disposable surplus
left over after the more imperative physical needs are satisfied is not
infrequently diverted to the purpose of a conspicuous decency, rather than
to added physical comfort and fullness of life. Moreover, such surplus
energy as is available is also likely to be expended in the acquisition of
goods for conspicuous consumption or conspicuous boarding. The result is
that the requirements of pecuniary reputability tend (1) to leave but a
scanty subsistence minimum available for other than conspicuous
consumption, and (2) to absorb any surplus energy which may be available
after the bare physical necessities of life have been provided for. The
outcome of the whole is a strengthening of the general conservative
attitude of the community. The institution of a leisure class hinders
cultural development immediately (1) by the inertia proper to the class
itself, (2) through its prescriptive example of conspicuous waste and of
conservatism, and (3) indirectly through that system of unequal
distribution of wealth and sustenance on which the institution itself
rests. To this is to be added that the leisure class has also a material
interest in leaving things as they are. Under the circumstances prevailing
at any given time this class is in a privileged position, and any
departure from the existing order may be expected to work to the detriment
of the class rather than the reverse. The attitude of the class, simply as
influenced by its class interest, should therefore be to let well-enough
alone. This interested motive comes in to supplement the strong
instinctive bias of the class, and so to render it even more consistently
conservative than it otherwise would be.</p>
<p>All this, of course, has nothing to say in the way of eulogy or
deprecation of the office of the leisure class as an exponent and vehicle
of conservatism or reversion in social structure. The inhibition which it
exercises may be salutary or the reverse. Wether it is the one or the
other in any given case is a question of casuistry rather than of general
theory. There may be truth in the view (as a question of policy) so often
expressed by the spokesmen of the conservative element, that without some
such substantial and consistent resistance to innovation as is offered by
the conservative well-to-do classes, social innovation and experiment
would hurry the community into untenable and intolerable situations; the
only possible result of which would be discontent and disastrous reaction.
All this, however, is beside the present argument.</p>
<p>But apart from all deprecation, and aside from all question as to the
indispensability of some such check on headlong innovation, the leisure
class, in the nature of things, consistently acts to retard that
adjustment to the environment which is called social advance or
development. The characteristic attitude of the class may be summed up in
the maxim: "Whatever is, is right" whereas the law of natural selection,
as applied to human institutions, gives the axiom: "Whatever is, is
wrong." Not that the institutions of today are wholly wrong for the
purposes of the life of today, but they are, always and in the nature of
things, wrong to some extent. They are the result of a more or less
inadequate adjustment of the methods of living to a situation which
prevailed at some point in the past development; and they are therefore
wrong by something more than the interval which separates the present
situation from that of the past. "Right" and "wrong" are of course here
used without conveying any rejection as to what ought or ought not to be.
They are applied simply from the (morally colorless) evolutionary
standpoint, and are intended to designate compatibility or incompatibility
with the effective evolutionary process. The institution of a leisure
class, by force or class interest and instinct, and by precept and
prescriptive example, makes for the perpetuation of the existing
maladjustment of institutions, and even favors a reversion to a somewhat
more archaic scheme of life; a scheme which would be still farther out of
adjustment with the exigencies of life under the existing situation even
than the accredited, obsolescent scheme that has come down from the
immediate past.</p>
<p>But after all has been said on the head of conservation of the good old
ways, it remains true that institutions change and develop. There is a
cumulative growth of customs and habits of thought; a selective adaptation
of conventions and methods of life. Something is to be said of the office
of the leisure class in guiding this growth as well as in retarding it;
but little can be said here of its relation to institutional growth except
as it touches the institutions that are primarily and immediately of an
economic character. These institutions—the economic structure—may
be roughly distinguished into two classes or categories, according as they
serve one or the other of two divergent purposes of economic life.</p>
<p>To adapt the classical terminology, they are institutions of acquisition
or of production; or to revert to terms already employed in a different
connection in earlier chapters, they are pecuniary or industrial
institutions; or in still other terms, they are institutions serving
either the invidious or the non-invidious economic interest. The former
category have to do with "business," the latter with industry, taking the
latter word in the mechanical sense. The latter class are not often
recognized as institutions, in great part because they do not immediately
concern the ruling class, and are, therefore, seldom the subject of
legislation or of deliberate convention. When they do receive attention
they are commonly approached from the pecuniary or business side; that
being the side or phase of economic life that chiefly occupies men's
deliberations in our time, especially the deliberations of the upper
classes. These classes have little else than a business interest in things
economic, and on them at the same time it is chiefly incumbent to
deliberate upon the community's affairs.</p>
<p>The relation of the leisure (that is, propertied non-industrial) class to
the economic process is a pecuniary relation—a relation of
acquisition, not of production; of exploitation, not of serviceability.
Indirectly their economic office may, of course, be of the utmost
importance to the economic life process; and it is by no means here
intended to depreciate the economic function of the propertied class or of
the captains of industry. The purpose is simply to point out what is the
nature of the relation of these classes to the industrial process and to
economic institutions. Their office is of a parasitic character, and their
interest is to divert what substance they may to their own use, and to
retain whatever is under their hand. The conventions of the business world
have grown up under the selective surveillance of this principle of
predation or parasitism. They are conventions of ownership; derivatives,
more or less remote, of the ancient predatory culture. But these pecuniary
institutions do not entirely fit the situation of today, for they have
grown up under a past situation differing somewhat from the present. Even
for effectiveness in the pecuniary way, therefore, they are not as apt as
might be. The changed industrial life requires changed methods of
acquisition; and the pecuniary classes have some interest in so adapting
the pecuniary institutions as to give them the best effect for acquisition
of private gain that is compatible with the continuance of the industrial
process out of which this gain arises. Hence there is a more or less
consistent trend in the leisure-class guidance of institutional growth,
answering to the pecuniary ends which shape leisure-class economic life.</p>
<p>The effect of the pecuniary interest and the pecuniary habit of mind upon
the growth of institutions is seen in those enactments and conventions
that make for security of property, enforcement of contracts, facility of
pecuniary transactions, vested interests. Of such bearing are changes
affecting bankruptcy and receiverships, limited liability, banking and
currency, coalitions of laborers or employers, trusts and pools. The
community's institutional furniture of this kind is of immediate
consequence only to the propertied classes, and in proportion as they are
propertied; that is to say, in proportion as they are to be ranked with
the leisure class. But indirectly these conventions of business life are
of the gravest consequence for the industrial process and for the life of
the community. And in guiding the institutional growth in this respect,
the pecuniary classes, therefore, serve a purpose of the most serious
importance to the community, not only in the conservation of the accepted
social scheme, but also in shaping the industrial process proper. The
immediate end of this pecuniary institutional structure and of its
amelioration is the greater facility of peaceable and orderly
exploitation; but its remoter effects far outrun this immediate object.
Not only does the more facile conduct of business permit industry and
extra-industrial life to go on with less perturbation; but the resulting
elimination of disturbances and complications calling for an exercise of
astute discrimination in everyday affairs acts to make the pecuniary class
itself superfluous. As fast as pecuniary transactions are reduced to
routine, the captain of industry can be dispensed with. This consummation,
it is needless to say, lies yet in the indefinite future. The
ameliorations wrought in favor of the pecuniary interest in modern
institutions tend, in another field, to substitute the "soulless"
joint-stock corporation for the captain, and so they make also for the
dispensability, of the great leisure-class function of ownership.
Indirectly, therefore, the bent given to the growth of economic
institutions by the leisure-class influence is of very considerable
industrial consequence.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />