<p>The last paragraph incidentally touches upon the fact that everyday speech
can scarcely be employed in discussing this class of aptitudes and
activities without implying deprecation or apology. The fact is
significant as showing the habitual attitude of the dispassionate common
man toward the propensities which express themselves in sports and in
exploit generally. And this is perhaps as convenient a place as any to
discuss that undertone of deprecation which runs through all the
voluminous discourse in defense or in laudation of athletic sports, as
well as of other activities of a predominantly predatory character. The
same apologetic frame of mind is at least beginning to be observable in
the spokesmen of most other institutions handed down from the barbarian
phase of life. Among these archaic institutions which are felt to need
apology are comprised, with others, the entire existing system of the
distribution of wealth, together with the resulting class distinction of
status; all or nearly all forms of consumption that come under the head of
conspicuous waste; the status of women under the patriarchal system; and
many features of the traditional creeds and devout observances, especially
the exoteric expressions of the creed and the naive apprehension of
received observances. What is to be said in this connection of the
apologetic attitude taken in commending sports and the sporting character
will therefore apply, with a suitable change in phraseology, to the
apologies offered in behalf of these other, related elements of our social
heritage.</p>
<p>There is a feeling—usually vague and not commonly avowed in so many
words by the apologist himself, but ordinarily perceptible in the manner
of his discourse—that these sports, as well as the general range of
predaceous impulses and habits of thought which underlie the sporting
character, do not altogether commend themselves to common sense. "As to
the majority of murderers, they are very incorrect characters." This
aphorism offers a valuation of the predaceous temperament, and of the
disciplinary effects of its overt expression and exercise, as seen from
the moralist's point of view. As such it affords an indication of what is
the deliverance of the sober sense of mature men as to the degree of
availability of the predatory habit of mind for the purposes of the
collective life. It is felt that the presumption is against any activity
which involves habituation to the predatory attitude, and that the burden
of proof lies with those who speak for the rehabilitation of the
predaceous temper and for the practices which strengthen it. There is a
strong body of popular sentiment in favor of diversions and enterprises of
the kind in question; but there is at the same time present in the
community a pervading sense that this ground of sentiment wants
legitimation. The required legitimation is ordinarily sought by showing
that although sports are substantially of a predatory, socially
disintegrating effect; although their proximate effect runs in the
direction of reversion to propensities that are industrially
disserviceable; yet indirectly and remotely—by some not readily
comprehensible process of polar induction, or counter-irritation perhaps—sports
are conceived to foster a habit of mind that is serviceable for the social
or industrial purpose. That is to say, although sports are essentially of
the nature of invidious exploit, it is presumed that by some remote and
obscure effect they result in the growth of a temperament conducive to
non-invidious work. It is commonly attempted to show all this empirically
or it is rather assumed that this is the empirical generalization which
must be obvious to any one who cares to see it. In conducting the proof of
this thesis the treacherous ground of inference from cause to effect is
somewhat shrewdly avoided, except so far as to show that the "manly
virtues" spoken of above are fostered by sports. But since it is these
manly virtues that are (economically) in need of legitimation, the chain
of proof breaks off where it should begin. In the most general economic
terms, these apologies are an effort to show that, in spite of the logic
of the thing, sports do in fact further what may broadly be called
workmanship. So long as he has not succeeded in persuading himself or
others that this is their effect the thoughtful apologist for sports will
not rest content, and commonly, it is to be admitted, he does not rest
content. His discontent with his own vindication of the practice in
question is ordinarily shown by his truculent tone and by the eagerness
with which he heaps up asseverations in support of his position. But why
are apologies needed? If there prevails a body of popular sentient in
favor of sports, why is not that fact a sufficient legitimation? The
protracted discipline of prowess to which the race has been subjected
under the predatory and quasi-peaceable culture has transmitted to the men
of today a temperament that finds gratification in these expressions of
ferocity and cunning. So, why not accept these sports as legitimate
expressions of a normal and wholesome human nature? What other norm is
there that is to be lived up to than that given in the aggregate range of
propensities that express themselves in the sentiments of this generation,
including the hereditary strain of prowess? The ulterior norm to which
appeal is taken is the instinct of workmanship, which is an instinct more
fundamental, of more ancient prescription, than the propensity to
predatory emulation. The latter is but a special development of the
instinct of workmanship, a variant, relatively late and ephemeral in spite
of its great absolute antiquity. The emulative predatory impulse—or
the instinct of sportsmanship, as it might well be called—is
essentially unstable in comparison with the primordial instinct of
workmanship out of which it has been developed and differentiated. Tested
by this ulterior norm of life, predatory emulation, and therefore the life
of sports, falls short.</p>
<p>The manner and the measure in which the institution of a leisure class
conduces to the conservation of sports and invidious exploit can of course
not be succinctly stated. From the evidence already recited it appears
that, in sentient and inclinations, the leisure class is more favorable to
a warlike attitude and animus than the industrial classes. Something
similar seems to be true as regards sports. But it is chiefly in its
indirect effects, though the canons of decorous living, that the
institution has its influence on the prevalent sentiment with respect to
the sporting life. This indirect effect goes almost unequivocally in the
direction of furthering a survival of the predatory temperament and
habits; and this is true even with respect to those variants of the
sporting life which the higher leisure-class code of proprieties
proscribes; as, e.g., prize-fighting, cock-fighting, and other like vulgar
expressions of the sporting temper. Whatever the latest authenticated
schedule of detail proprieties may say, the accredited canons of decency
sanctioned by the institution say without equivocation that emulation and
waste are good and their opposites are disreputable. In the crepuscular
light of the social nether spaces the details of the code are not
apprehended with all the facility that might be desired, and these broad
underlying canons of decency are therefore applied somewhat
unreflectingly, with little question as to the scope of their competence
or the exceptions that have been sanctioned in detail.</p>
<p>Addiction to athletic sports, not only in the way of direct participation,
but also in the way of sentiment and moral support, is, in a more or less
pronounced degree, a characteristic of the leisure class; and it is a
trait which that class shares with the lower-class delinquents, and with
such atavistic elements throughout the body of the community as are
endowed with a dominant predaceous trend. Few individuals among the
populations of Western civilized countries are so far devoid of the
predaceous instinct as to find no diversion in contemplating athletic
sports and games, but with the common run of individuals among the
industrial classes the inclination to sports does not assert itself to the
extent of constituting what may fairly be called a sporting habit. With
these classes sports are an occasional diversion rather than a serious
feature of life. This common body of the people can therefore not be said
to cultivate the sporting propensity. Although it is not obsolete in the
average of them, or even in any appreciable number of individuals, yet the
predilection for sports in the commonplace industrial classes is of the
nature of a reminiscence, more or less diverting as an occasional
interest, rather than a vital and permanent interest that counts as a
dominant factor in shaping the organic complex of habits of thought into
which it enters. As it manifests itself in the sporting life of today,
this propensity may not appear to be an economic factor of grave
consequence. Taken simply by itself it does not count for a great deal in
its direct effects on the industrial efficiency or the consumption of any
given individual; but the prevalence and the growth of the type of human
nature of which this propensity is a characteristic feature is a matter of
some consequence. It affects the economic life of the collectivity both as
regards the rate of economic development and as regards the character of
the results attained by the development. For better or worse, the fact
that the popular habits of thought are in any degree dominated by this
type of character can not but greatly affect the scope, direction,
standards, and ideals of the collective economic life, as well as the
degree of adjustment of the collective life to the environment.</p>
<p>Something to a like effect is to be said of other traits that go to make
up the barbarian character. For the purposes of economic theory, these
further barbarian traits may be taken as concomitant variations of that
predaceous temper of which prowess is an expression. In great measure they
are not primarily of an economic character, nor do they have much direct
economic bearing. They serve to indicate the stage of economic evolution
to which the individual possessed of them is adapted. They are of
importance, therefore, as extraneous tests of the degree of adaptation of
the character in which they are comprised to the economic exigencies of
today, but they are also to some extent important as being aptitudes which
themselves go to increase or diminish the economic serviceability of the
individual.</p>
<p>As it finds expression in the life of the barbarian, prowess manifests
itself in two main directions—force and fraud. In varying degrees
these two forms of expression are similarly present in modern warfare, in
the pecuniary occupations, and in sports and games. Both lines of
aptitudes are cultivated and strengthened by the life of sport as well as
by the more serious forms of emulative life. Strategy or cunning is an
element invariably present in games, as also in warlike pursuits and in
the chase. In all of these employments strategy tends to develop into
finesse and chicanery. Chicanery, falsehood, browbeating, hold a
well-secured place in the method of procedure of any athletic contest and
in games generally. The habitual employment of an umpire, and the minute
technical regulations governing the limits and details of permissible
fraud and strategic advantage, sufficiently attest the fact that
fraudulent practices and attempts to overreach one's opponents are not
adventitious features of the game. In the nature of the case habituation
to sports should conduce to a fuller development of the aptitude for
fraud; and the prevalence in the community of that predatory temperament
which inclines men to sports connotes a prevalence of sharp practice and
callous disregard of the interests of others, individually and
collectively. Resort to fraud, in any guise and under any legitimation of
law or custom, is an expression of a narrowly self-regarding habit of
mind. It is needless to dwell at any length on the economic value of this
feature of the sporting character.</p>
<p>In this connection it is to be noted that the most obvious characteristic
of the physiognomy affected by athletic and other sporting men is that of
an extreme astuteness. The gifts and exploits of Ulysses are scarcely
second to those of Achilles, either in their substantial furtherance of
the game or in the �clat which they give the astute sporting man among his
associates. The pantomime of astuteness is commonly the first step in that
assimilation to the professional sporting man which a youth undergoes
after matriculation in any reputable school, of the secondary or the
higher education, as the case may be. And the physiognomy of astuteness,
as a decorative feature, never ceases to receive the thoughtful attention
of men whose serious interest lies in athletic games, races, or other
contests of a similar emulative nature. As a further indication of their
spiritual kinship, it may be pointed out that the members of the lower
delinquent class usually show this physiognomy of astuteness in a marked
degree, and that they very commonly show the same histrionic exaggeration
of it that is often seen in the young candidate for athletic honors. This,
by the way, is the most legible mark of what is vulgarly called
"toughness" in youthful aspirants for a bad name.</p>
<p>The astute man, it may be remarked, is of no economic value to the
community—unless it be for the purpose of sharp practice in dealings
with other communities. His functioning is not a furtherance of the
generic life process. At its best, in its direct economic bearing, it is a
conversion of the economic substance of the collectivity to a growth alien
to the collective life process—very much after the analogy of what
in medicine would be called a benign tumor, with some tendency to
transgress the uncertain line that divides the benign from the malign
growths. The two barbarian traits, ferocity and astuteness, go to make up
the predaceous temper or spiritual attitude. They are the expressions of a
narrowly self-regarding habit of mind. Both are highly serviceable for
individual expediency in a life looking to invidious success. Both also
have a high aesthetic value. Both are fostered by the pecuniary culture.
But both alike are of no use for the purposes of the collective life.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />