<p>This contention of the leisure-class spokesmen of the humanities seems to
be substantially sound. In point of substantial fact, the gratification
and the culture, or the spiritual attitude or habit of mind, resulting
from an habitual contemplation of the anthropomorphism, clannishness, and
leisurely self-complacency of the gentleman of an early day, or from a
familiarity with the animistic superstitions and the exuberant truculence
of the Homeric heroes, for instance, is, aesthetically considered, more
legitimate than the corresponding results derived from a matter-of-fact
knowledge of things and a contemplation of latter-day civic or workmanlike
efficiency. There can be but little question that the first-named habits
have the advantage in respect of aesthetic or honorific value, and
therefore in respect of the "worth" which is made the basis of award in
the comparison. The content of the canons of taste, and more particularly
of the canons of honor, is in the nature of things a resultant of the past
life and circumstances of the race, transmitted to the later generation by
inheritance or by tradition; and the fact that the protracted dominance of
a predatory, leisure-class scheme of life has profoundly shaped the habit
of mind and the point of view of the race in the past, is a sufficient
basis for an aesthetically legitimate dominance of such a scheme of life
in very much of what concerns matters of taste in the present. For the
purpose in hand, canons of taste are race habits, acquired through a more
or less protracted habituation to the approval or disapproval of the kind
of things upon which a favorable or unfavorable judgment of taste is
passed. Other things being equal, the longer and more unbroken the
habituation, the more legitimate is the canon of taste in question. All
this seems to be even truer of judgments regarding worth or honor than of
judgments of taste generally.</p>
<p>But whatever may be the aesthetic legitimacy of the derogatory judgment
passed on the newer learning by the spokesmen of the humanities, and
however substantial may be the merits of the contention that the classic
lore is worthier and results in a more truly human culture and character,
it does not concern the question in hand. The question in hand is as to
how far these branches of learning, and the point of view for which they
stand in the educational system, help or hinder an efficient collective
life under modern industrial circumstances—how far they further a
more facile adaptation to the economic situation of today. The question is
an economic, not an aesthetic one; and the leisure-class standards of
learning which find expression in the deprecatory attitude of the higher
schools towards matter-of-fact knowledge are, for the present purpose, to
be valued from this point of view only. For this purpose the use of such
epithets as "noble", "base", "higher", "lower", etc., is significant only
as showing the animus and the point of view of the disputants; whether
they contend for the worthiness of the new or of the old. All these
epithets are honorific or humilific terms; that is to say, they are terms
of invidious comparison, which in the last analysis fall under the
category of the reputable or the disreputable; that is, they belong within
the range of ideas that characterizes the scheme of life of the regime of
status; that is, they are in substance an expression of sportsmanship—of
the predatory and animistic habit of mind; that is, they indicate an
archaic point of view and theory of life, which may fit the predatory
stage of culture and of economic organization from which they have sprung,
but which are, from the point of view of economic efficiency in the
broader sense, disserviceable anachronisms.</p>
<p>The classics, and their position of prerogative in the scheme of education
to which the higher seminaries of learning cling with such a fond
predilection, serve to shape the intellectual attitude and lower the
economic efficiency of the new learned generation. They do this not only
by holding up an archaic ideal of manhood, but also by the discrimination
which they inculcate with respect to the reputable and the disreputable in
knowledge. This result is accomplished in two ways: (1) by inspiring an
habitual aversion to what is merely useful, as contrasted with what is
merely honorific in learning, and so shaping the tastes of the novice that
he comes in good faith to find gratification of his tastes solely, or
almost solely, in such exercise of the intellect as normally results in no
industrial or social gain; and (2) by consuming the learner's time and
effort in acquiring knowledge which is of no use except in so far as this
learning has by convention become incorporated into the sum of learning
required of the scholar, and has thereby affected the terminology and
diction employed in the useful branches of knowledge. Except for this
terminological difficulty—which is itself a consequence of the vogue
of the classics of the past—a knowledge of the ancient languages,
for instance, would have no practical bearing for any scientist or any
scholar not engaged on work primarily of a linguistic character. Of
course, all this has nothing to say as to the cultural value of the
classics, nor is there any intention to disparage the discipline of the
classics or the bent which their study gives to the student. That bent
seems to be of an economically disserviceable kind, but this fact—somewhat
notorious indeed—need disturb no one who has the good fortune to
find comfort and strength in the classical lore. The fact that classical
learning acts to derange the learner's workmanlike attitudes should fall
lightly upon the apprehension of those who hold workmanship of small
account in comparison with the cultivation of decorous ideals: Iam fides
et pax et honos pudorque Priscus et neglecta redire virtus Audet.</p>
<p>Owing to the circumstance that this knowledge has become part of the
elementary requirements in our system of education, the ability to use and
to understand certain of the dead languages of southern Europe is not only
gratifying to the person who finds occasion to parade his accomplishments
in this respect, but the evidence of such knowledge serves at the same
time to recommend any savant to his audience, both lay and learned. It is
currently expected that a certain number of years shall have been spent in
acquiring this substantially useless information, and its absence creates
a presumption of hasty and precarious learning, as well as of a vulgar
practicality that is equally obnoxious to the conventional standards of
sound scholarship and intellectual force.</p>
<p>The case is analogous to what happens in the purchase of any article of
consumption by a purchaser who is not an expert judge of materials or of
workmanship. He makes his estimate of value of the article chiefly on the
ground of the apparent expensiveness of the finish of those decorative
parts and features which have no immediate relation to the intrinsic
usefulness of the article; the presumption being that some sort of
ill-defined proportion subsists between the substantial value of an
article and the expense of adornment added in order to sell it. The
presumption that there can ordinarily be no sound scholarship where a
knowledge of the classics and humanities is wanting leads to a conspicuous
waste of time and labor on the part of the general body of students in
acquiring such knowledge. The conventional insistence on a modicum of
conspicuous waste as an incident of all reputable scholarship has affected
our canons of taste and of serviceability in matters of scholarship in
much the same way as the same principle has influenced our judgment of the
serviceability of manufactured goods.</p>
<p>It is true, since conspicuous consumption has gained more and more on
conspicuous leisure as a means of repute, the acquisition of the dead
languages is no longer so imperative a requirement as it once was, and its
talismanic virtue as a voucher of scholarship has suffered a concomitant
impairment. But while this is true, it is also true that the classics have
scarcely lost in absolute value as a voucher of scholastic respectability,
since for this purpose it is only necessary that the scholar should be
able to put in evidence some learning which is conventionally recognized
as evidence of wasted time; and the classics lend themselves with great
facility to this use. Indeed, there can be little doubt that it is their
utility as evidence of wasted time and effort, and hence of the pecuniary
strength necessary in order to afford this waste, that has secured to the
classics their position of prerogative in the scheme of higher learning,
and has led to their being esteemed the most honorific of all learning.
They serve the decorative ends of leisure-class learning better than any
other body of knowledge, and hence they are an effective means of
reputability.</p>
<p>In this respect the classics have until lately had scarcely a rival. They
still have no dangerous rival on the continent of Europe, but lately,
since college athletics have won their way into a recognized standing as
an accredited field of scholarly accomplishment, this latter branch of
learning—if athletics may be freely classed as learning—has
become a rival of the classics for the primacy in leisure-class education
in American and English schools. Athletics have an obvious advantage over
the classics for the purpose of leisure-class learning, since success as
an athlete presumes, not only waste of time, but also waste of money, as
well as the possession of certain highly unindustrial archaic traits of
character and temperament. In the German universities the place of
athletics and Greek-letter fraternities, as a leisure-class scholarly
occupation, has in some measure been supplied by a skilled and graded
inebriety and a perfunctory duelling.</p>
<p>The leisure class and its standard of virtue—archaism and waste—can
scarcely have been concerned in the introduction of the classics into the
scheme of the higher learning; but the tenacious retention of the classics
by the higher schools, and the high degree of reputability which still
attaches to them, are no doubt due to their conforming so closely to the
requirements of archaism and waste.</p>
<p>"Classic" always carries this connotation of wasteful and archaic, whether
it is used to denote the dead languages or the obsolete or obsolescent
forms of thought and diction in the living language, or to denote other
items of scholarly activity or apparatus to which it is applied with less
aptness. So the archaic idiom of the English language is spoken of as
"classic" English. Its use is imperative in all speaking and writing upon
serious topics, and a facile use of it lends dignity to even the most
commonplace and trivial string of talk. The newest form of English diction
is of course never written; the sense of that leisure-class propriety
which requires archaism in speech is present even in the most illiterate
or sensational writers in sufficient force to prevent such a lapse. On the
other hand, the highest and most conventionalized style of archaic diction
is—quite characteristically—properly employed only in
communications between an anthropomorphic divinity and his subjects.
Midway between these extremes lies the everyday speech of leisure-class
conversation and literature.</p>
<p>Elegant diction, whether in writing or speaking, is an effective means of
reputability. It is of moment to know with some precision what is the
degree of archaism conventionally required in speaking on any given topic.
Usage differs appreciably from the pulpit to the market-place; the latter,
as might be expected, admits the use of relatively new and effective words
and turns of expression, even by fastidious persons. A discriminative
avoidance of neologisms is honorific, not only because it argues that time
has been wasted in acquiring the obsolescent habit of speech, but also as
showing that the speaker has from infancy habitually associated with
persons who have been familiar with the obsolescent idiom. It thereby goes
to show his leisure-class antecedents. Great purity of speech is
presumptive evidence of several lives spent in other than vulgarly useful
occupations; although its evidence is by no means entirely conclusive to
this point.</p>
<p>As felicitous an instance of futile classicism as can well be found,
outside of the Far East, is the conventional spelling of the English
language. A breach of the proprieties in spelling is extremely annoying
and will discredit any writer in the eyes of all persons who are possessed
of a developed sense of the true and beautiful. English orthography
satisfies all the requirements of the canons of reputability under the law
of conspicuous waste. It is archaic, cumbrous, and ineffective; its
acquisition consumes much time and effort; failure to acquire it is easy
of detection. Therefore it is the first and readiest test of reputability
in learning, and conformity to its ritual is indispensable to a blameless
scholastic life.</p>
<p>On this head of purity of speech, as at other points where a conventional
usage rests on the canons of archaism and waste, the spokesmen for the
usage instinctively take an apologetic attitude. It is contended, in
substance, that a punctilious use of ancient and accredited locutions will
serve to convey thought more adequately and more precisely than would be
the straightforward use of the latest form of spoken English; whereas it
is notorious that the ideas of today are effectively expressed in the
slang of today. Classic speech has the honorific virtue of dignity; it
commands attention and respect as being the accredited method of
communication under the leisure-class scheme of life, because it carries a
pointed suggestion of the industrial exemption of the speaker. The
advantage of the accredited locutions lies in their reputability; they are
reputable because they are cumbrous and out of date, and therefore argue
waste of time and exemption from the use and the need of direct and
forcible speech.</p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />