<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0028" id="link2H_4_0028"></SPAN></p>
<h2> SECT. VIII. OF THE CAUSES OF BELIEF. </h2>
<p>Having thus explained the nature of belief, and shewn that it consists in
a lively idea related to a present impression; let us now proceed to
examine from what principles it is derived, and what bestows the vivacity
on the idea.</p>
<p>I would willingly establish it as a general maxim in the science of human
nature, that when any impression becomes present to us, it not only
transports the mind to such ideas as are related to it, but likewise
communicates to them a share of its force and vivacity. All the operations
of the mind depend in a great measure on its disposition, when it performs
them; and according as the spirits are more or less elevated, and the
attention more or less fixed, the action will always have more or less
vigour and vivacity. When therefore any object is presented, which
elevates and enlivens the thought, every action, to which the mind applies
itself, will be more strong and vivid, as Tong as that disposition
continues, Now it is evident the continuance of the disposition depends
entirely on the objects, about which the mind is employed; and that any
new object naturally gives a new direction to the spirits, and changes the
disposition; as on the contrary, when the mind fixes constantly on the
same object, or passes easily and insensibly along related objects, the
disposition has a much longer duration. Hence it happens, that when the
mind is once inlivened by a present impression, it proceeds to form a more
lively idea of the related objects, by a natural transition of the
disposition from the one to the other. The change of the objects is so
easy, that the mind is scarce sensible of it, but applies itself to the
conception of the related idea with all the force and vivacity it acquired
from the present impression.</p>
<p>If in considering the nature of relation, and that facility of transition,
which is essential to it, we can satisfy ourselves concerning the reality
of this phaenomenon, it is well: But I must confess I place my chief
confidence in experience to prove so material a principle. We may,
therefore, observe, as the first experiment to our present purpose, that
upon the appearance of the picture of an absent friend, our idea of him is
evidently inlivened by the resemblance, and that every passion, which that
idea occasions, whether of joy or sorrow, acquires new force and vigour.
In producing this effect there concur both a relation and a present
impression. Where the picture bears him no resemblance, or at least was
not intended for him, it never so much as conveys our thought to him: And
where it is absent, as well as the person; though the mind may pass from
the thought of the one to that of the other; it feels its idea to be
rather weekend than inlivened by that transition. We take a pleasure in
viewing the picture of a friend, when it is set before us; but when it is
removed, rather choose to consider him directly, than by reflexion in an
image, which is equally distinct and obscure.</p>
<p>The ceremonies of the Roman Catholic religion may be considered as
experiments of the same nature. The devotees of that strange superstition
usually plead in excuse of the mummeries, with which they are upbraided,
that they feel the good effect of those external motions, and postures,
and actions, in enlivening their devotion, and quickening their fervour,
which otherwise would decay away, if directed entirely to distant and
immaterial objects. We shadow out the objects of our faith, say they, in
sensible types and images, and render them more present to us by the
immediate presence of these types, than it is possible for us to do,
merely by an intellectual view and contemplation. Sensible objects have
always a greater influence on the fancy than any other; and this influence
they readily convey to those ideas, to which they are related, and which
they Resemble. I shall only infer from these practices, and this
reasoning, that the effect of resemblance in inlivening the idea is very
common; and as in every case a resemblance and a present impression must
concur, we are abundantly supplyed with experiments to prove the reality
of the foregoing principle.</p>
<p>We may add force to these experiments by others of a different kind, in
considering the effects of contiguity, as well as of resemblance. It is
certain, that distance diminishes the force of every idea, and that upon
our approach to any object; though it does not discover itself to our
senses; it operates upon the mind with an influence that imitates an
immediate impression. The thinking on any object readily transports the
mind to what is contiguous; but it is only the actual presence of an
object, that transports it with a superior vivacity. When I am a few miles
from home, whatever relates to it touches me more nearly than when I am
two hundred leagues distant; though even at that distance the reflecting
on any thing in the neighbourhood of my friends and family naturally
produces an idea of them. But as in this latter case, both the objects of
the mind are ideas; notwithstanding there is an easy transition betwixt
them; that transition alone is not able to give a superior vivacity to any
of the ideas, for want of some immediate impression. [FN 6.]</p>
<p>[FN 6. NATURANE NOBIS, IN QUIT, DATUM DICAM, AN ERRORE<br/>
QUODAM, UT, CUM EA LOCA VIDEAMUS, IN QUIBUS MEMORIA DIGNOS<br/>
VIROS ACCEPERIMUS MULTURN ESSE VERSATOS, MAGIS MOVEAMUR,<br/>
QUAM SIQUANDO EORUM IPSORUM AUT JACTA AUDIAMUS, AUT SCRIPTUM<br/>
ALIQUOD LEGAMUS? VELUT EGO NUNC MOVEOR. VENIT ENIM MIHI<br/>
PLATONIS IN MENTEM: QUEM ACCIPIMUS PRIMURN HIC DISPUTARE<br/>
SOLITUM: CUJUS ETIAM ILLI HORTULI PROPINQUI NON MEMORIAM<br/>
SOLUM MIHI AFFERUNT, SED IPSUM VIDENTUR IN CONSPECTU MEO HIC<br/>
PONERE. HIC SPEUSIPPUS, HIC XENOCRATES, HIC EJUS AUDITOR<br/>
POLEMO; CUJUS IPSA ILLA SESSIO FUIT, QUAM VIDEAMUS. EQUIDEM<br/>
ETIAM CURIAM NOSTRAM, HOSTILIAM DICO, NON HANC NOVAM, QUAE<br/>
MIHI MINOR ESSE VIDETUR POST QUAM EST MAJOR, SOLE BARN<br/>
INTUENS SCIPIONEM, CATONEM, LACLIUM, NOSTRUM VERO IN PRIMIS<br/>
AVUM COGITARE. TANTA VIS ADMONITIONIS INEST IN LOCIS; UT NON<br/>
SINE CAUSA EX HIS MEMORIAE DUCTA SIT DISCIPLINA. Cicero de<br/>
Finibus, lib. 5.<br/>
<br/>
{"Should I, he said, "attribute to instinct or to some kind<br/>
of illusion the fact that when we see those places in which<br/>
we are told notable men spent much of their time, we are<br/>
more powerfully affected than when we hear of the exploits<br/>
of the men themselves or read something written? This is<br/>
just what is happening to me now; for I am reminded of Plato<br/>
who, we are told, was the first to make a practice of<br/>
holding discussions here. Those gardens of his near by do<br/>
not merely put me in mind of him; they seem to set the man<br/>
himself before my very eyes. Speusippus was here; so was<br/>
Xenocrates; so was his pupil, Polemo, and that very seat<br/>
which we may view was his.<br/>
<br/>
"Then again, when I looked at our Senate-house (I mean the<br/>
old building of Hostilius, not this new one; when it was<br/>
enlarged, it diminished in my estimation), I used to think<br/>
of Scipio, Cato, Laelius and in particular of my own<br/>
grandfather.<br/>
<br/>
"Such is the power of places to evoke associations; so it is<br/>
with good reason that they are used as a basis for memory<br/>
training."}]<br/></p>
<p>No one can doubt but causation has the same influence as the other two
relations; of resemblance and contiguity. Superstitious people are fond of
the relicks of saints and holy men, for the same reason that they seek
after types and images, in order to enliven their devotion, and give them
a more intimate and strong conception of those exemplary lives, which they
desire to imitate. Now it is evident, one of the best relicks a devotee
coued procure, would be the handywork of a saint; and if his cloaths and
furniture are ever to be considered in this light, it is because they were
once at his disposal, and were moved and affected by him; in which respect
they are to be considered as imperfect effects, and as connected with him
by a shorter chain of consequences than any of those, from which we learn
the reality of his existence. This phaenomenon clearly proves, that a
present impression with a relation of causation may, inliven any idea, and
consequently produce belief or assent, according to the precedent
definition of it.</p>
<p>But why need we seek for other arguments to prove, that a present
impression with a relation or transition of the fancy may inliven any
idea, when this very instance of our reasonings from cause and effect will
alone suffice to that purpose? It is certain we must have an idea of every
matter of fact, which we believe. It is certain, that this idea arises
only from a relation to a present impression. It is certain, that the
belief super-adds nothing to the idea, but only changes our manner of
conceiving it, and renders it more strong and lively. The present
conclusion concerning the influence of relation is the immediate
consequence of all these steps; and every step appears to me sure end
infallible. There enters nothing into this operation of the mind but a
present impression, a lively idea, and a relation or association in the
fancy betwixt the impression and idea; so that there can be no suspicion
of mistake.</p>
<p>In order to put this whole affair in a fuller light, let us consider it as
a question in natural philosophy, which we must determine by experience
and observation. I suppose there is an object presented, from which I draw
a certain conclusion, and form to myself ideas, which I am said to believe
or assent to. Here it is evident, that however that object, which is
present to my senses, and that other, whose existence I infer by
reasoning, may be thought to influence each other by their particular
powers or qualities; yet as the phenomenon of belief, which we at present
examine, is merely internal, these powers and qualities, being entirely
unknown, can have no hand in producing it. It is the present impression,
which is to be considered as the true and real cause of the idea, and of
the belief which attends it. We must therefore endeavour to discover by
experiments the particular qualities, by which it is enabled to produce so
extraordinary an effect.</p>
<p>First then I observe, that the present impression has not this effect by
its own proper power and efficacy, and when considered alone, as a single
perception, limited to the present moment. I find, that an impression,
from which, on its first appearance, I can draw no conclusion, may
afterwards become the foundation of belief, when I have had experience of
its usual consequences. We must in every case have observed the same
impression in past instances, and have found it to be constantly conjoined
with some other impression. This is confirmed by such a multitude of
experiments, that it admits not of the smallest doubt.</p>
<p>From a second observation I conclude, that the belief, which attends the
present impression, and is produced by a number of past impressions and
conjunctions; that this belief, I say, arises immediately, without any new
operation of the reason or imagination. Of this I can be certain, because
I never am conscious of any such operation, and find nothing in the
subject, on which it can be founded. Now as we call every thing CUSTOM,
which proceeds from a past repetition, without any new reasoning or
conclusion, we-may establish it as a certain truth, that all the belief,
which follows upon any present impression, is derived solely from that
origin. When we are accustomed to see two impressions conjoined together,
the appearance or idea of the one immediately carries us to the idea of
the other.</p>
<p>Being fully satisfyed on this head, I make a third set of experiments, in
order to know, whether any thing be requisite, beside the customary
transition, towards the production of this phaenomenon of belief. I
therefore change the first impression into an idea; and observe, that
though the customary transition to the correlative idea still remains, yet
there is in reality no belief nor perswasion. A present impression, then,
is absolutely requisite to this whole operation; and when after this I
compare an impression with an idea, and find that their only difference
consists in their different degrees of force and vivacity, I conclude upon
the whole, that belief is a more vivid and intense conception of an idea,
proceeding from its relation to a present impression.</p>
<p>Thus all probable reasoning is nothing but a species of sensation. It is
not solely in poetry and music, we must follow our taste and sentiment,
but likewise in philosophy. When I am convinced of any principle, it is
only an idea, which strikes more strongly upon me. When I give the
preference to one set of arguments above another, I do nothing but decide
from my feeling concerning the superiority of their influence. Objects
have no discoverable connexion together; nor is it from any other
principle but custom operating upon the imagination, that we can draw any
inference from the appearance of one to the existence of another.</p>
<p>It will here be worth our observation, that the past experience, on which
all our judgments concerning cause and effect depend, may operate on our
mind in such an insensible manner as never to be taken notice of, and may
even in some measure be unknown to us. A person, who stops short in his
journey upon meeting a river in his way, foresees the consequences of his
proceeding forward; and his knowledge of these consequences is conveyed to
him by past experience, which informs him of such certain conjunctions of
causes and effects. But can we think, that on this occasion he reflects on
any past experience, and calls to remembrance instances, that he has seen
or heard of, in order to discover the effects of water on animal bodies?
No surely; this is not the method, in which he proceeds in his reasoning.
The idea of sinking is so closely connected with that of water, and the
idea of suffocating with that of sinking, that the mind makes the
transition without the assistance of the memory. The custom operates
before we have time for reflection. The objects seem so inseparable, that
we interpose not a moment's delay in passing from the one to the other.
But as this transition proceeds from experience, and not from any primary
connexion betwixt the ideas, we must necessarily acknowledge, that
experience may produce a belief and a judgment of causes and effects by a
secret operation, and without being once thought of. This removes all
pretext, if there yet remains any, for asserting that the mind is
convinced by reasoning of that principle, that instances of which we have
no experience, must necessarily resemble those, of which we have. For we
here find, that the understanding or imagination can draw inferences from
past experience, without reflecting on it; much more without forming any
principle concerning it, or reasoning upon that principle.</p>
<p>In general we may observe, that in all the most established and uniform
conjunctions of causes and effects, such as those of gravity, impulse,
solidity, &c. the mind never carries its view expressly to consider
any past experience: Though in other associations of objects, which are
more rare and unusual, it may assist the custom and transition of ideas by
this reflection. Nay we find in some cases, that the reflection produces
the belief without the custom; or more properly speaking, that the
reflection produces the custom in an oblique and artificial manner. I
explain myself. It is certain, that not only in philosophy, but even in
common life, we may attain the knowledge of a particular cause merely by
one experiment, provided it be made with judgment, and after a careful
removal of all foreign and superfluous circumstances. Now as after one
experiment of this kind, the mind, upon the appearance either of the cause
or the effect, can draw an inference concerning the existence of its
correlative; and as a habit can never be acquired merely by one instance;
it may be thought, that belief cannot in this case be esteemed the effect
of custom. But this difficulty will vanish, if we consider, that though we
are here supposed to have had only one experiment of a particular effect,
yet we have many millions to convince us of this principle; that like
objects placed in like circumstances, will always produce like effects;
and as this principle has established itself by a sufficient custom, it
bestows an evidence and firmness on any opinion, to which it can be
applied. The connexion of the ideas is not habitual after one experiment:
but this connexion is comprehended under another principle, that is
habitual; which brings us back to our hypothesis. In all cases we transfer
our experience to instances, of which we have no experience, either
expressly or tacitly, either directly or indirectly.</p>
<p>I must not conclude this subject without observing, that it is very
difficult to talk of the operations of the mind with perfect propriety and
exactness; because common language has seldom made any very nice
distinctions among them, but has generally called by the same term all
such as nearly resemble each other. And as this is a source almost
inevitable of obscurity and confusion in the author; so it may frequently
give rise to doubts and objections in the reader, which otherwise he would
never have dreamed of. Thus my general position, that an opinion or belief
is nothing but a strong and lively idea derived from a present impression
related to it, maybe liable to the following objection, by reason of a
little ambiguity in those words strong and lively. It may be said, that
not only an impression may give rise to reasoning, but that an idea may
also have the same influence; especially upon my principle, that all our
ideas are derived from correspondent impressions. For suppose I form at
present an idea, of which I have forgot the correspondent impression, I am
able to conclude from this idea, that such an impression did once exist;
and as this conclusion is attended with belief, it may be asked, from
whence are the qualities of force and vivacity derived, which constitute
this belief? And to this I answer very readily, from the present idea. For
as this idea is not here considered, as the representation of any absent
object, but as a real perception in the mind, of which we are intimately
conscious, it must be able to bestow on whatever is related to it the same
quality, call it firmness, or solidity, or force, or vivacity, with which
the mind reflects upon it, and is assured of its present existence. The
idea here supplies the place of an impression, and is entirely the same,
so far as regards our present purpose.</p>
<p>Upon the same principles we need not be surprized to hear of the
remembrance of an idea: that is, of the idea of an idea, and of its force
and vivacity superior to the loose conceptions of the imagination. In
thinking of our past thoughts we not only delineate out the objects, of
which we were thinking, but also conceive the action of the mind in the
meditation, that certain JE-NE-SCAI-QUOI, of which it is impossible to
give any definition or description, but which every one sufficiently
understands. When the memory offers an idea of this, and represents it as
past, it is easily conceived how that idea may have more vigour and
firmness, than when we think of a past thought, of which we have no
remembrance.</p>
<p>After this any one will understand how we may form the idea of an
impression and of an idea, and how we way believe the existence of an
impression and of an idea.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />