<p>I now proceed to explain the SECOND part of my system, and shew why the
constancy of our perceptions makes us ascribe to them a perfect numerical
identity, tho there be very long intervals betwixt their appearance, and
they have only one of the essential qualities of identity, VIZ,
INVARIABLENESS. That I may avoid all ambiguity and confusion on this head,
I shall observe, that I here account for the opinions and belief of the
vulgar with regard to the existence of body; and therefore must entirely
conform myself to their manner of thinking and of expressing themselves.
Now we have already observd, that however philosophers may distinguish
betwixt the objects and perceptions of the senses; which they suppose
co-existent and resembling; yet this is a distinction, which is not
comprehended by the generality of mankind, who as they perceive only one
being, can never assent to the opinion of a double existence and
representation. Those very sensations, which enter by the eye or ear, are
with them the true objects, nor can they readily conceive that this pen or
paper, which is immediately perceivd, represents another, which is
different from, but resembling it. In order, therefore, to accommodate
myself to their notions, I shall at first suppose; that there is only a
single existence, which I shall call indifferently OBJECT or PERCEPTION,
according as it shall seem best to suit my purpose, understanding by both
of them what any common man means by a hat, or shoe, or stone, or any
other impression, conveyd to him by his senses. I shall be sure to give
warning, when I return to a more philosophical way of speaking and
thinking.</p>
<p>To enter, therefore, upon the question concerning the source of the error
and deception with regard to identity, when we attribute it to our
resembling perceptions, notwithstanding their interruption; I must here
recal an observation, which I have already provd and explaind [Part II.
Sect. 5.]. Nothing is more apt to make us mistake one idea for another,
than any relation betwixt them, which associates them together in the
imagination, and makes it pass with facility from one to the other. Of all
relations, that of resemblance is in this respect the most efficacious;
and that because it not only causes an association of ideas, but also of
dispositions, and makes us conceive the one idea by an act or operation of
the mind, similar to that by which we conceive the other. This
circumstance I have observd to be of great moment; and we may establish it
for a general rule, that whatever ideas place the mind in the same
disposition or in similar ones, are very apt to be confounded. The mind
readily passes from one to the other, and perceives not the change without
a strict attention, of which, generally speaking, it is wholly incapable.</p>
<p>In order to apply this general maxim, we must first examine the
disposition of the mind in viewing any object which preserves a perfect
identity, and then find some other object, that is confounded with it, by
causing a similar disposition. When we fix our thought on any object, and
suppose it to continue the same for some time; it is evident we suppose
the change to lie only in the time, and never exert ourselves to produce
any new image or idea of the object. The faculties of the mind repose
themselves in a manner, and take no more exercise, than what is necessary
to continue that idea, of which we were formerly possest, and which
subsists without variation or interruption. The passage from one moment to
another is scarce felt, and distinguishes not itself by a different
perception or idea, which may require a different direction of the
spirits, in order to its conception.</p>
<p>Now what other objects, beside identical ones, are capable of placing the
mind in the same disposition, when it considers them, and of causing the
same uninterrupted passage of the imagination from one idea to another?
This question is of the last importance. For if we can find any such
objects, we may certainly conclude, from the foregoing principle, that
they are very naturally confounded with identical ones, and are taken for
them in most of our reasonings. But though this question be very
important, it is not very difficult nor doubtful. For I immediately reply,
that a succession of related objects places the mind in this disposition,
and is considered with the same smooth and uninterrupted progress of the
imagination, as attends the view of the same invariable object. The very
nature and essence of relation is to connect our ideas with each other,
and upon the appearance of one, to facilitate the transition to its
correlative. The passage betwixt related ideas is, therefore, so smooth
and easy, that it produces little alteration on the mind, and seems like
the continuation of the same action; and as the continuation of the same
action is an effect of the continued view of the same object, it is for
this reason we attribute sameness to every succession of related objects.
The thought slides along the succession with equal facility, as if it
considered only one object; and therefore confounds the succession with
the identity.</p>
<p>We shall afterwards see many instances of this tendency of relation to
make us ascribe an identity to different objects; but shall here confine
ourselves to the present subject. We find by experience, that there is
such a constancy in almost all the impressions of the senses, that their
interruption produces no alteration on them, and hinders them not from
returning the same in appearance and in situation as at their first
existence. I survey the furniture of my chamber; I shut my eyes, and
afterwards open them; and find the new perceptions to resemble perfectly
those, which formerly struck my senses. This resemblance is observed in a
thousand instances, and naturally connects together our ideas of these
interrupted perceptions by the strongest relation, and conveys the mind
with an easy transition from one to another. An easy transition or passage
of the imagination, along the ideas of these different and interrupted
perceptions, is almost the same disposition of mind with that in which we
consider one constant and uninterrupted perception. It is therefore very
natural for us to mistake the one for the other.</p>
<p>[FN 9 This reasoning, it must be confest, is somewhat<br/>
abstruse, and difficult to be comprehended; but it is<br/>
remarkable, that this very difficulty may be converted into<br/>
a proof of the reasoning. We may observe, that there are two<br/>
relations, and both of them resemblances, which contribute<br/>
to our mistaking the succession of our interrupted<br/>
perceptions for an identical object. The first is, the<br/>
resemblance of the perceptions: The second is the<br/>
resemblance, which the act of the mind in surveying a<br/>
succession of resembling objects bears to that in surveying<br/>
an identical object. Now these resemblances we are apt to<br/>
confound with each other; and it is natural we shoud,<br/>
according to this very reasoning. But let us keep them<br/>
distinct, and we shall find no difficulty in conceiving the<br/>
precedent argument.]<br/></p>
<p>The persons, who entertain this opinion concerning the identity of our
resembling perceptions, are in general an the unthinking and
unphilosophical part of mankind, (that is, all of us, at one time or
other) and consequently such as suppose their perceptions to be their only
objects, and never think of a double existence internal and external,
representing and represented. The very image, which is present to the
senses, is with us the real body; and it is to these interrupted images we
ascribe a perfect identity. But as the interruption of the appearance
seems contrary to the identity, and naturally leads us to regard these
resembling perceptions as different from each other, we here find
ourselves at a loss how to reconcile such opposite opinions. The smooth
passage of the imagination along the ideas of the resembling perceptions
makes us ascribe to them a perfect identity. The interrupted manner of
their appearance makes us consider them as so many resembling, but still
distinct beings, which appear after certain intervals. The perplexity
arising from this contradiction produces a propension to unite these
broken appearances by the fiction of a continued existence, which is the
third part of that hypothesis I proposed to explain.</p>
<p>Nothing is more certain from experience, than that any contradiction
either to the sentiments or passions gives a sensible uneasiness, whether
it proceeds from without or from within; from the opposition of external
objects, or from the combat of internal principles. On the contrary,
whatever strikes in with the natural propensities, and either externally
forwards their satisfaction, or internally concurs with their movements,
is sure to give a sensible pleasure. Now there being here an opposition
betwixt the notion of the identity of resembling perceptions, and the
interruption of their appearance, the mind must be uneasy in that
situation, and will naturally seek relief from the uneasiness. Since the
uneasiness arises from the opposition of two contrary principles, it must
look for relief by sacrificing the one to the other. But as the smooth
passage of our thought along our resembling perceptions makes us ascribe
to them an identity, we can never without reluctance yield up that
opinion. We must, therefore, turn to the other side, and suppose that our
perceptions are no longer interrupted, but preserve a continued as well as
an invariable existence, and are by that means entirely the same. But here
the interruptions in the appearance of these perceptions are so long and
frequent, that it is impossible to overlook them; and as the appearance of
a perception in the mind and its existence seem at first sight entirely
the same, it may be doubted, whether we can ever assent to so palpable a
contradiction, and suppose a perception to exist without being present to
the mind. In order to clear up this matter, and learn how the interruption
in the appearance of a perception implies not necessarily an interruption
in its existence, it will be proper to touch upon some principles, which
we shall have occasion to explain more fully afterwards. [Sect. 6.]</p>
<p>We may begin with observing, that the difficulty in the present case is
not concerning the matter of fact, or whether the mind forms such a
conclusion concerning the continued existence of its perceptions, but only
concerning the manner in which the conclusion is formed, and principles
from which it is derived. It is certain, that almost all mankind, and even
philosophers themselves, for the greatest part of their lives, take their
perceptions to be their only objects, and suppose, that the very being,
which is intimately present to the mind, is the real body or material
existence. It is also certain, that this very perception or object is
supposed to have a continued uninterrupted being, and neither to be
annihilated by our absence, nor to be brought into existence by our
presence. When we are absent from it, we say it still exists, but that we
do not feel, we do not see it. When we are present, we say we feel, or see
it. Here then may arise two questions; First, How we can satisfy ourselves
in supposing a perception to be absent from the mind without being
annihilated. Secondly, After what manner we conceive an object to become
present to the mind, without some new creation of a perception or image;
and what we mean by this seeing, and feeling, and perceiving.</p>
<p>As to the first question; we may observe, that what we call a mind, is
nothing but a heap or collection of different perceptions, united together
by certain relations, and supposed, though falsely, to be endowed with a
perfect simplicity and identity. Now as every perception is
distinguishable from another, and may be considered as separately
existent; it evidently follows, that there is no absurdity in separating
any particular perception from the mind; that is, in breaking off all its
relations, with that connected mass of perceptions, which constitute a
thinking being.</p>
<p>The same reasoning affords us an answer to the second question. If the
name of perception renders not this separation from a mind absurd and
contradictory, the name of object, standing for the very same thing, can
never render their conjunction impossible. External objects are seen, and
felt, and become present to the mind; that is, they acquire such a
relation to a connected heap of perceptions, as to influence them very
considerably in augmenting their number by present reflections and
passions, and in storing the memory with ideas. The same continued and
uninterrupted Being may, therefore, be sometimes present to the mind, and
sometimes absent from it, without any real or essential change in the
Being itself. An interrupted appearance to the senses implies not
necessarily an interruption in the existence. The supposition of the
continued existence of sensible objects or perceptions involves no
contradiction. We may easily indulge our inclination to that supposition.
When the exact resemblance of our perceptions makes us ascribe to them an
identity, we may remove the seeming interruption by feigning a continued
being, which may fill those intervals, and preserve a perfect and entire
identity to our perceptions.</p>
<p>But as we here not only feign but believe this continued existence, the
question is, from whence arises such a belief; and this question leads us
to the fourth member of this system. It has been proved already, that
belief in general consists in nothing, but the vivacity of an idea; and
that an idea may acquire this vivacity by its relation to some present
impression. Impressions are naturally the most vivid perceptions of the
mind; and this quality is in part conveyed by the relation to every
connected idea. The relation causes a smooth passage from the impression
to the idea, and even gives a propensity to that passage. The mind falls
so easily from the one perception to the other, that it scarce perceives
the change, but retains in the second a considerable share of the vivacity
of the first. It is excited by the lively impression; and this vivacity is
conveyed to the related idea, without any great diminution in the passage,
by reason of the smooth transition and the propensity of the imagination.</p>
<p>But suppose, that this propensity arises from some other principle,
besides that of relation; it is evident it must still have the same
effect, and convey the vivacity from the impression to the idea. Now this
is exactly the present case. Our memory presents us with a vast number of
instances of perceptions perfectly resembling each other, that return at
different distances of time, and after considerable interruptions. This
resemblance gives us a propension to consider these interrupted
perceptions as the same; and also a propension to connect them by a
continued existence, in order to justify this identity, and avoid the
contradiction, in which the interrupted appearance of these perceptions
seems necessarily to involve us. Here then we have a propensity to feign
the continued existence of all sensible objects; and as this propensity
arises from some lively impressions of the memory, it bestows a vivacity
on that fiction: or in other words, makes us believe the continued
existence of body. If sometimes we ascribe a continued existence to
objects, which are perfectly new to us, and of whose constancy and
coherence we have no experience, it is because the manner, in which they
present themselves to our senses, resembles that of constant and coherent
objects; and this resemblance is a source of reasoning and analogy, and
leads us to attribute the same qualities to similar objects.</p>
<p>I believe an intelligent reader will find less difficulty to assent to
this system, than to comprehend it fully and distinctly, and will allow,
after a little reflection, that every part carries its own proof along
with it. It is indeed evident, that as the vulgar suppose their
perceptions to be their only objects, and at the same time believe the
continued existence of matter, we must account for the origin of the
belief upon that supposition. Now upon that supposition, it is a false
opinion that any of our objects, or perceptions, are identically the same
after an interruption; and consequently the opinion of their identity can
never arise from reason, but must arise from the imagination. The
imagination is seduced into such an opinion only by means of the
resemblance of certain perceptions; since we find they are only our
resembling perceptions, which we have a propension to suppose the same.
This propension to bestow an identity on our resembling perceptions,
produces the fiction of a continued existence; since that fiction, as well
as the identity, is really false, as is acknowledged by all philosophers,
and has no other effect than to remedy the interruption of our
perceptions, which is the only circumstance that is contrary to their
identity. In the last place this propension causes belief by means of the
present impressions of the memory; since without the remembrance of former
sensations, it is plain we never should have any belief of the continued
existence of body. Thus in examining all these parts, we find that each of
them is supported by the strongest proofs: and that all of them together
form a consistent system, which is perfectly convincing. A strong
propensity or inclination alone, without any present impression, will
sometimes cause a belief or opinion. How much more when aided by that
circumstance?</p>
<p>But though we are led after this manner, by the natural propensity of the
imagination, to ascribe a continued existence to those sensible objects or
perceptions, which we find to resemble each other in their interrupted
appearance; yet a very little reflection and philosophy is sufficient to
make us perceive the fallacy of that opinion. I have already observed,
that there is an intimate connexion betwixt those two principles, of a
continued and of a distinct or independent existence, and that we no
sooner establish the one than the other follows, as a necessary
consequence. It is the opinion of a continued existence, which first takes
place, and without much study or reflection draws the other along with it,
wherever the mind follows its first and most natural tendency. But when we
compare experiments, and reason a little upon them, we quickly perceive,
that the doctrine of the independent existence of our sensible perceptions
is contrary to the plainest experience. This leads us backward upon our
footsteps to perceive our error in attributing a continued existence to
our perceptions, and is the origin of many very curious opinions, which we
shall here endeavour to account for.</p>
<p>It will first be proper to observe a few of those experiments, which
convince us, that our perceptions are not possest of any independent
existence. When we press one eye with a finger, we immediately perceive
all the objects to become double, and one half of them to be removed from
their common and natural position. But as we do not attribute to continued
existence to both these perceptions, and as they are both of the same
nature, we clearly perceive, that all our perceptions are dependent on our
organs, and the disposition of our nerves and animal spirits. This opinion
is confirmed by the seeming encrease and diminution of objects, according
to their distance; by the apparent alterations in their figure; by the
changes in their colour and other qualities from our sickness and
distempers: and by an infinite number of other experiments of the same
kind; from all which we learn, that our sensible perceptions are not
possest of any distinct or independent existence.</p>
<p>The natural consequence of this reasoning should be, that our perceptions
have no more a continued than an independent existence; and indeed
philosophers have so far run into this opinion, that they change their
system, and distinguish, (as we shall do for the future) betwixt
perceptions and objects, of which the former are supposed to be
interrupted, and perishing, and different at every different return; the
latter to be uninterrupted, and to preserve a continued existence and
identity. But however philosophical this new system may be esteemed, I
assert that it is only a palliative remedy, and that it contains all the
difficulties of the vulgar system, with some others, that are peculiar to
itself. There are no principles either of the understanding or fancy,
which lead us directly to embrace this opinion of the double existence of
perceptions and objects, nor can we arrive at it but by passing through
the common hypothesis of the identity and continuance of our interrupted
perceptions. Were we not first perswaded, that our perceptions are our
only objects, and continue to exist even when they no longer make their
appearance to the senses, we should never be led to think, that our
perceptions and objects are different, and that our objects alone preserve
a continued existence. The latter hypothesis has no primary recommendation
either to reason or the imagination, but acquires all its influence on the
imagination from the former. This proposition contains two parts, which we
shall endeavour to prove as distinctly and clearly, as such abstruse
subjects will permit.</p>
<p>As to the first part of the proposition, that this philosophical
hypothesis has no primary recommendation, either to reason, or the
imagination, we may soon satisfy ourselves with regard to reason by the
following reflections. The only existences, of which we are certain, are
perceptions, which being immediately present to us by consciousness,
command our strongest assent, and are the first foundation of all our
conclusions. The only conclusion we can draw from the existence of one
thing to that of another, is by means of the relation of cause and effect,
which shews, that there is a connexion betwixt them, and that the
existence of one is dependent on that of the other. The idea of this
relation is derived from past experience, by which we find, that two
beings are constantly conjoined together, and are always present at once
to the mind. But as no beings are ever present to the mind but
perceptions; it follows that we may observe a conjunction or a relation of
cause and effect between different perceptions, but can never observe it
between perceptions and objects. It is impossible, therefore, that from
the existence or any of the qualities of the former, we can ever form any
conclusion concerning the existence of the latter, or ever satisfy our
reason in this particular.</p>
<p>It is no less certain, that this philosophical system has no primary
recommendation to the imagination, and that that faculty would never, of
itself, and by its original tendency, have fallen upon such a principle. I
confess it will be somewhat difficult to prove this to the fall
satisfaction of the reader; because it implies a negative, which in many
cases will not admit of any positive proof. If any one would take the
pains to examine this question, and would invent a system, to account for
the direct origin of this opinion from the imagination, we should be able,
by the examination of that system, to pronounce a certain judgment in the
present subject. Let it be taken for granted, that our perceptions are
broken, and interrupted, and however like, are still different from each
other; and let any one upon this supposition shew why the fancy, directly
and immediately, proceeds to the belief of another existence, resembling
these perceptions in their nature, but yet continued, and uninterrupted,
and identical; and after he has done this to my satisfaction, I promise to
renounce my present opinion. Mean while I cannot forbear concluding, from
the very abstractedness and difficulty of the first supposition, that it
is an improper subject for the fancy to work upon. Whoever would explain
the origin of the common opinion concerning the continued and distinct
existence of body, must take the mind in its common situation, and must
proceed upon the supposition, that our perceptions are our only objects,
and continue to exist even when they are not perceived. Though this
opinion be false, it is the most natural of any, and has alone any primary
recommendation to the fancy.</p>
<p>As to the second part of the proposition, that the philosophical system
acquires all its influence on the imagination from the vulgar one; we may
observe, that this is a natural and unavoidable consequence of the
foregoing conclusion, that it has no primary recommendation to reason or
the imagination. For as the philosophical system is found by experience to
take hold of many minds, and in particular of all those, who reflect ever
so little on this subject, it must derive all its authority from the
vulgar system; since it has no original authority of its own. The manner,
in which these two systems, though directly contrary, are connected
together, may be explains, as follows.</p>
<p>The imagination naturally runs on in this train of thinking. Our
perceptions are our only objects: Resembling perceptions are the same,
however broken or uninterrupted in their appearance: This appealing
interruption is contrary to the identity: The interruption consequently
extends not beyond the appearance, and the perception or object really
continues to exist, even when absent from us: Our sensible perception s
have, therefore, a continued and uninterrupted existence. But as a little
reflection destroys this conclusion, that our perceptions have a continued
existence, by shewing that they have a dependent one, it would naturally
be expected, that we must altogether reject the opinion, that there is
such a thing in nature as a continued existence, which is preserved even
when it no longer appears to the senses. The case, however, is otherwise.
Philosophers are so far from rejecting the opinion of a continued
existence upon rejecting that of the independence and continuance of our
sensible perceptions, that though all sects agree in the latter sentiment,
the former, which is, in a manner, its necessary consequence, has been
peculiar to a few extravagant sceptics; who after all maintained that
opinion in words only, and were never able to bring themselves sincerely
to believe it.</p>
<p>There is a great difference betwixt such opinions as we form after a calm
and profound reflection, and such as we embrace by a kind of instinct or
natural impulse, on account of their suitableness and conformity to the
mind. If these opinions become contrary, it is not difficult to foresee
which of them will have the advantage. As long as our attention is bent
upon the subject, the philosophical and studyed principle may prevail; but
the moment we relax our thoughts, nature will display herself, and draw us
back to our former opinion. Nay she has sometimes such an influence, that
she can stop our progress, even in the midst of our most profound
reflections, and keep us from running on with all the consequences of any
philosophical opinion. Thus though we clearly perceive the dependence and
interruption of our perceptions, we stop short in our career, and never
upon that account reject the notion of an independent and continued
existence. That opinion has taken such deep root in the imagination, that
it is impossible ever to eradicate it, nor will any strained metaphysical
conviction of the dependence of our perceptions be sufficient for that
purpose.</p>
<p>But though our natural and obvious principles here prevail above our
studied reflections, it is certain there must be sonic struggle and
opposition in the case: at least so long as these rejections retain any
force or vivacity. In order to set ourselves at ease in this particular,
we contrive a new hypothesis, which seems to comprehend both these
principles of reason and imagination. This hypothesis is the
philosophical, one of the double existence of perceptions and objects;
which pleases our reason, in allowing, that our dependent perceptions are
interrupted and different; and at the same time is agreeable to the
imagination, in attributing a continued existence to something else, which
we call objects. This philosophical system, therefore, is the monstrous
offspring of two principles, which are contrary to each other, which are
both at once embraced by the mind, and which are unable mutually to
destroy each other. The imagination tells us, that our resembling
perceptions have a continued and uninterrupted existence, and are not
annihilated by their absence. Reflection tells us, that even our
resembling perceptions are interrupted in their existence, and different
from each other. The contradiction betwixt these opinions we elude by a
new fiction, which is conformable to the hypotheses both of reflection and
fancy, by ascribing these contrary qualities to different existences; the
interruption to perceptions, and the continuance to objects. Nature is
obstinate, and will not quit the field, however strongly attacked by
reason; and at the same time reason is so clear in the point, that there
is no possibility of disguising her. Not being able to reconcile these two
enemies, we endeavour to set ourselves at ease as much as possible, by
successively granting to each whatever it demands, and by feigning a
double existence, where each may find something, that has all the
conditions it desires. Were we fully convinced, that our resembling
perceptions are continued, and identical, and independent, we should never
run into this opinion of a double existence, since we should find
satisfaction in our first supposition, and would not look beyond. Again,
were we fully convinced, that our perceptions are dependent, and
interrupted, and different, we should be as little inclined to embrace the
opinion of a double existence; since in that case we should clearly
perceive the error of our first supposition of a continued existence, and
would never regard it any farther. It is therefore from the intermediate
situation of the mind, that this opinion arises, and from such an
adherence to these two contrary principles, as makes us seek some pretext
to justify our receiving both; which happily at last is found in the
system of a double existence.</p>
<p>Another advantage of this philosophical system is its similarity to the
vulgar one; by which means we can humour our reason for a moment, when it
becomes troublesome and sollicitous; and yet upon its least negligence or
inattention, can easily return to our vulgar and natural notions.
Accordingly we find, that philosophers neglect not this advantage; but
immediately upon leaving their closets, mingle with the rest of mankind in
those exploded opinions, that our perceptions are our only objects, and
continue identically and uninterruptedly the same in all their interrupted
appearances.</p>
<p>There are other particulars of this system, wherein we may remark its
dependence on the fancy, in a very conspicuous manner. Of these, I shall
observe the two following. First, We suppose external objects to resemble
internal perceptions. I have already shewn, that the relation of cause and
effect can never afford us any just conclusion from the existence or
qualities of our perceptions to the existence of external continued
objects: And I shall farther add, that even though they coued afford such
a conclusion, we should never have any reason to infer, that our objects
resemble our perceptions. That opinion, therefore, is derived from nothing
but the quality of the fancy above-explained, (that it borrows all its
ideas from some precedent perception). We never can conceive any thing but
perceptions, and therefore must make every thing resemble them.</p>
<p>Secondly, As we suppose our objects in general to resemble our
perceptions, so we take it for granted, that every particular object
resembles that perception, which it causes. The relation of cause and
effect determines us to join the other of resemblance; and the ideas of
these existences being already united together in the fancy by the former
relation, we naturally add the latter to compleat the union. We have a
strong propensity to compleat every union by joining new relations to
those which we have before observed betwixt any ideas, as we shall have
occasion to observe presently. [Sect. 5.]</p>
<p>Having thus given an account of all the systems both popular and
philosophical, with regard to external existences, I cannot forbear giving
vent to a certain sentiment, which arises upon reviewing those systems. I
begun this subject with premising, that we ought to have an implicit faith
in our senses, and that this would be the conclusion, I should draw from
the whole of my reasoning. But to be ingenuous, I feel myself at present
of a quite contrary sentiment, and am more inclined to repose no faith at
all in my senses, or rather imagination, than to place in it such an
implicit confidence. I cannot conceive how such trivial qualities of the
fancy, conducted by such false suppositions, can ever lead to any solid
and rational system. They are the coherence and constancy of our
perceptions, which produce the opinion of their continued existence;
though these qualities of perceptions have no perceivable connexion with
such an existence. The constancy of our perceptions has the most
considerable effect, and yet is attended with the greatest difficulties.
It is a gross illusion to suppose, that our resembling perceptions are
numerically the same; and it is this illusion, which leads us into the
opinion, that these perceptions are uninterrupted, and are still existent,
even when they are not present to the senses. This is the case with our
popular system. And as to our philosophical one, it is liable to the same
difficulties; and is over-and-above loaded with this absurdity, that it at
once denies and establishes the vulgar supposition. Philosophers deny our
resembling perceptions to be identically the same, and uninterrupted; and
yet have so great a propensity to believe them such, that they arbitrarily
invent a new set of perceptions, to which they attribute these qualities.
I say, a new set of perceptions: For we may well suppose in general, but
it is impossible for us distinctly to conceive, objects to be in their
nature any thing but exactly the same with perceptions. What then can we
look for from this confusion of groundless and extraordinary opinions but
error and falshood? And how can we justify to ourselves any belief we
repose in them?</p>
<p>This sceptical doubt, both with respect to reason and the senses, is a
malady, which can never be radically cured, but must return upon us every
moment, however we may chace it away, and sometimes may seem entirely free
from it. It is impossible upon any system to defend either our
understanding or senses; and we but expose them farther when we endeavour
to justify them in that manner. As the sceptical doubt arises naturally
from a profound and intense reflection on those subjects, it always
encreases, the farther we carry our reflections, whether in opposition or
conformity to it. Carelessness and in-attention alone can afford us any
remedy. For this reason I rely entirely upon them; and take it for
granted, whatever may be the reader's opinion at this present moment, that
an hour hence he will be persuaded there is both an external and internal
world; and going upon that supposition, I intend to examine some general
systems both ancient and modern, which have been proposed of both, before
I proceed to a more particular enquiry concerning our impressions. This
will not, perhaps, in the end be found foreign to our present purpose.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />