<SPAN name="startofbook"></SPAN>
<h1><SPAN name="Page_3" id="Page_3"></SPAN>THE STORY OF ALCHEMY AND<br/> THE BEGINNINGS OF CHEMISTRY</h1>
<h3> BY</h3>
<h2>M. M. PATTISON MUIR, M.A.</h2>
<h5>"It is neither religious nor wise to judge that of which you know nothing."<br/>
<i>A Brief Guide to the Celestial Ruby</i>, by PHILALETHES (17th century)</h5>
<h2><SPAN name="PREFACE" id="PREFACE"></SPAN>PREFACE.</h2>
<p>The Story of Alchemy and the Beginnings of
Chemistry is very interesting in itself. It is also
a pregnant example of the contrast between the
scientific and the emotional methods of regarding
nature; and it admirably illustrates the differences between
well-grounded, suggestive, hypotheses, and baseless speculations.</p>
<p>I have tried to tell the story so that it may be intelligible to the
ordinary reader.</p>
<hr class="full"/>
<h2><SPAN name="CHAPTER_I" id="CHAPTER_I"></SPAN>CHAPTER I</h2>
<h3>THE EXPLANATION OF MATERIAL CHANGES GIVEN BY THE GREEK THINKERS.</h3>
<p>For thousands of years before men had any
accurate and exact knowledge of the changes of
material things, they had thought about these
changes, regarded them as revelations of spiritual
truths, built on them theories of things in heaven
and earth (and a good many things in neither),
and used them in manufactures, arts, and handicrafts,
especially in one very curious manufacture
wherein not the thousandth fragment of a grain
of the finished article was ever produced.</p>
<p>The accurate and systematic study of the
changes which material things undergo is called
chemistry; we may, perhaps, describe alchemy
as the superficial, and what may be called subjective,
examination of these changes, and the
speculative systems, and imaginary arts and
manufactures, founded on that examination.</p>
<p>We are assured by many old writers that
Adam was the first alchemist, and we are told
by one of the initiated that Adam was created
<SPAN name="Page_10" id="Page_10"></SPAN>on the sixth day, being the 15th of March, of
the first year of the world; certainly alchemy
had a long life, for chemistry did not begin until
about the middle of the 18th century.</p>
<p>No branch of science has had so long a period
of incubation as chemistry. There must be
some extraordinary difficulty in the way of disentangling
the steps of those changes wherein
substances of one kind are produced from substances
totally unlike them. To inquire how
those of acute intellects and much learning
regarded such occurrences in the times when
man's outlook on the world was very different
from what it is now, ought to be interesting,
and the results of that inquiry must surely be
instructive.</p>
<p>If the reader turns to a modern book on
chemistry (for instance, <i>The Story of the
Chemical Elements</i>, in this series), he will find,
at first, superficial descriptions of special instances
of those occurrences which are the
subject of the chemist's study; he will learn
that only certain parts of such events are dealt
with in chemistry; more accurate descriptions
will then be given of changes which occur in
nature, or can be produced by altering the
ordinary conditions, and the reader will be
taught to see certain points of likeness between
these changes; he will be shown how to disentangle
chemical occurrences, to find their
similarities and differences; and, gradually, he
will feel his way to general statements, which
are more or less rigorous and accurate expressions
of what holds good in a large number of chemical
<SPAN name="Page_11" id="Page_11"></SPAN>processes; finally, he will discover that some
generalisations have been made which are exact
and completely accurate descriptions applicable
to every case of chemical change.</p>
<p>But if we turn to the writings of the alchemists,
we are in a different world. There is nothing
even remotely resembling what one finds in a
modern book on chemistry.</p>
<p>Here are a few quotations from alchemical writings<SPAN name="FNanchor_1_1" id="FNanchor_1_1"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_1_1"><sup>1</sup></SPAN>:</p>
<div class="blkquot"><p>"It is necessary to deprive matter of its qualities
in order to draw out its soul.... Copper
is like a man; it has a soul and a body ... the
soul is the most subtile part ... that is to say,
the tinctorial spirit. The body is the ponderable,
material, terrestrial thing, endowed with a shadow....
After a series of suitable treatments copper
becomes without shadow and better than gold....
The elements grow and are transmuted,
because it is their qualities, not their substances
which are contrary." (Stephanus of Alexandria,
about 620 A.D.)</p>
<p>"If we would elicit our Medecine from the
precious metals, we must destroy the particular
metalic form, without impairing its specific properties.
The specific properties of the metal
have their abode in its spiritual part, which
resides in homogeneous water. Thus we must
destroy the particular form of gold, and change
it into its generic homogeneous water, in which
<SPAN name="Page_12" id="Page_12"></SPAN>the spirit of gold is preserved; this spirit afterwards
restores the consistency of its water, and
brings forth a new form (after the necessary putrefaction)
a thousand times more perfect than the
form of gold which it lost by being reincrudated."
(Philalethes, 17th century.)</p>
<p>"The bodily nature of things is a concealing
outward vesture." (Michael Sendivogius, 17th
century.)</p>
<p>"Nothing of true value is located in the body
of a substance, but in the virtue ... the less
there is of body, the more in proportion is the
virtue." (Paracelsus, 16th century.)</p>
<p>"There are four elements, and each has at its
centre another element which makes it what it
is. These are the four pillars of the world....
It is their contrary action which keeps up
the harmony and equilibrium of the mundane
machinery." (Michael Sendivogius.)</p>
<p>"Nature cannot work till it has been supplied
with a material: the first matter is furnished by
God, the second matter by the sage." (Michael
Sendivogius.)</p>
<p>"When corruptible elements are united in a
certain substance, their strife must sooner or
later bring about its decomposition, which is, of
course, followed by putrefaction; in putrefaction,
the impure is separated from the pure; and if
the pure elements are then once more joined
together by the action of natural heat, a much nobler and
higher form of life is produced....
If the hidden central fire, which during life was
in a state of passivity, obtain the mastery, it
attracts to itself all the pure elements, which are
<SPAN name="Page_13" id="Page_13"></SPAN>thus separated from the impure, and form the
nucleus of a far purer form of life." (Michael
Sendivogius.)</p>
<p>"Cause that which is above to be below;
that which is visible to be invisible; that
which is palpable to become impalpable. Again
let that which is below become that which is
above; let the invisible become visible, and the
impalpable become palpable. Here you see the
perfection of our Art, without any defect or
diminution." (Basil Valentine, 15th century.)</p>
<p>"Think most diligently about this; often bear
in mind, observe and comprehend, that all
minerals and metals together, in the same time,
and after the same fashion, and of one and the
same principal matter, are produced and generated.
That matter is no other than a mere
vapour, which is extracted from the elementary
earth by the superior stars, or by a sidereal
distillation of the macrocosm; which sidereal
hot infusion, with an airy sulphurous property,
descending upon inferiors, so acts and operates
as that there is implanted, spiritually and invisibly,
a certain power and virtue in those
metals and minerals; which fume, moreover,
resolves in the earth into a certain water,
wherefrom all metals are thenceforth generated and
ripened to their perfection, and thence proceeds
this or that metal or mineral, according as one of
the three principles acquires dominion, and they
have much or little of sulphur and salt, or an
unequal mixture of these; whence some metals
are fixed—that is, constant or stable; and some
are volatile and easily changeable, as is seen in
<SPAN name="Page_14" id="Page_14"></SPAN>gold, silver, copper, iron, tin, and lead." (Basil
Valentine.)</p>
<p>"To grasp the invisible elements, to attract
them by their material correspondences, to control,
purify, and transform them by the living
power of the Spirit—this is true Alchemy."
(Paracelsus.)</p>
<p>"Destruction perfects that which is good; for
the good cannot appear on account of that which
conceals it.... Each one of the visible metals
is a concealment of the other six metals."
(Paracelsus.)</p>
</div>
<p>These sayings read like sentences in a forgotten
tongue.</p>
<p>Humboldt tells of a parrot which had lived
with a tribe of American Indians, and learnt
scraps of their language; the tribe totally disappeared;
the parrot alone remained, and
babbled words in the language which no living
human being could understand.</p>
<p>Are the words I have quoted unintelligible,
like the parrot's prating? Perhaps the language
may be reconstructed; perhaps it may be found
to embody something worth a hearing. Success
is most likely to come by considering the growth
of alchemy; by trying to find the ideas which
were expressed in the strange tongue; by endeavouring
to look at our surroundings as the
alchemists looked at theirs.</p>
<p>Do what we will, we always, more or less,
construct our own universe. The history of
science may be described as the history of the
attempts, and the failures, of men "to see things
as they are." "Nothing is harder," said the<SPAN name="Page_15" id="Page_15"></SPAN>
Latin poet Lucretius, "than to separate manifest
facts from doubtful, what straightway the
mind adds on of itself."</p>
<p>Observations of the changes which are constantly
happening in the sky, and on the earth,
must have prompted men long ago to ask whether
there are any limits to the changes of things
around them. And this question must have
become more urgent as working in metals,
making colours and dyes, preparing new kinds
of food and drink, producing substances with
smells and tastes unlike those of familiar objects,
and other pursuits like these, made men
acquainted with transformations which seemed
to penetrate to the very foundations of things.</p>
<p>Can one thing be changed into any other
thing; or, are there classes of things within each of
which change is possible, while the passage
from one class to another is not possible? Are all
the varied substances seen, tasted, handled,
smelt, composed of a limited number of essentially
different things; or, is each fundamentally different
from every other substance? Such
questions as these must have pressed for answers
long ago.</p>
<p>Some of the Greek philosophers who lived four
or five hundred years before Christ formed a
theory of the transformations of matter, which is
essentially the theory held by naturalists to-day.</p>
<p>These philosophers taught that to understand
nature we must get beneath the superficial
qualities of things. "According to convention," said
Democritus (born 460 B.C.), "there are a sweet
and a bitter, a hot and a cold, and according to
<SPAN name="Page_16" id="Page_16"></SPAN>convention there is colour. In truth there are
atoms and a void." Those investigators attempted
to connect all the differences which are observed
between the qualities of things with differences of
size, shape, position, and movement of atoms.
They said that all things are formed by the
coalescence of certain unchangeable, indestructible,
and impenetrable particles which they named
atoms; the total number of atoms is constant;
not one of them can be destroyed, nor can
one be created; when a substance ceases to exist and
another is formed, the process is not a destruction
of matter, it is a re-arrangement of atoms.</p>
<p>Only fragments of the writings of the founders
of the atomic theory have come to us. The views
of these philosophers are preserved, and doubtless
amplified and modified, in a Latin poem, <i>Concerning
the Nature of Things</i>, written by Lucretius,
who was born a century before the beginning
of our era. Let us consider the picture given in
that poem of the material universe, and the
method whereby the picture was produced.<SPAN name="FNanchor_2_2" id="FNanchor_2_2"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_2_2"><sup>2</sup></SPAN></p>
<p>All knowledge, said Lucretius, is based on
"the aspect and the law of nature." True knowledge
can be obtained only by the use of the
senses; there is no other method. "From the
senses first has proceeded the knowledge of the
true, and the senses cannot be refuted. Shall
reason, founded on false sense, be able to contradict
[the senses], wholly founded as it is on the
senses? And if they are not true, then all reason
as well is rendered false." The first principle
<SPAN name="Page_17" id="Page_17"></SPAN>in nature is asserted by Lucretius to be that
"Nothing is ever gotten out of nothing." "A
thing never returns to nothing, but all things
after disruption go back to the first bodies of
matter." If there were not imperishable seeds
of things, atoms, "first-beginnings of solid singleness,"
then, Lucretius urges, "infinite time gone
by and lapse of days must have eaten up all
things that are of mortal body."</p>
<p>The first-beginnings, or atoms, of things were
thought of by Lucretius as always moving;
"there is no lowest point in the sum of the
universe" where they can rest; they meet, clash,
rebound, or sometimes join together into groups
of atoms which move about as wholes. Change,
growth, decay, formation, disruption—these are
the marks of all things. "The war of first-beginnings
waged from eternity is carried on
with dubious issue: now here, now there, the
life-bringing elements of things get the mastery,
and are o'ermastered in turn; with the funeral
wail blends the cry which babies raise when they
enter the borders of light; and no night ever
followed day, nor morning night, that heard not,
mingling with the sickly infant's cries, the attendants'
wailings on death and black funeral."</p>
<p>Lucretius pictured the atoms of things as like
the things perceived by the senses; he said that
atoms of different kinds have different shapes,
but the number of shapes is finite, because there
is a limit to the number of different things we
see, smell, taste, and handle; he implies, although
I do not think he definitely asserts, that all atoms
of one kind are identical in every respect.<SPAN name="Page_18" id="Page_18"></SPAN></p>
<p>We now know that many compounds exist
which are formed by the union of the same quantities
by weight of the same elements, and, nevertheless,
differ in properties; modern chemistry
explains this fact by saying that the properties
of a substance depend, not only on the kind of
atoms which compose the minute particles of a
compound, and the number of atoms of each
kind, but also on the mode of arrangement of
the atoms.<SPAN name="FNanchor_3_3" id="FNanchor_3_3"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_3_3"><sup>3</sup></SPAN> The same doctrine was taught by
Lucretius, two thousand years ago. "It often
makes a great difference," he said, "with what
things, and in what positions the same first-beginnings
are held in union, and what motions
they mutually impart and receive." For instance,
certain atoms may be so arranged at one time as
to produce fire, and, at another time, the arrangement
of the same atoms may be such that the
result is a fir-tree. The differences between the
colours of things are said by Lucretius to be due
to differences in the arrangements and motions
of atoms. As the colour of the sea when wind
lashes it into foam is different from the colour
when the waters are at rest, so do the colours
of things change when the atoms whereof the things
are composed change from one arrangement to
another, or from sluggish movements to rapid
and tumultuous motions.</p>
<p>Lucretius pictured a solid substance as a vast
number of atoms squeezed closely together, a
liquid as composed of not so many atoms less
tightly packed, and a gas as a comparatively
<SPAN name="Page_19" id="Page_19"></SPAN>small number of atoms with considerable freedom
of motion. Essentially the same picture is presented
by the molecular theory of to-day.</p>
<p>To meet the objection that atoms are invisible,
and therefore cannot exist, Lucretius enumerates
many things we cannot see although we know
they exist. No one doubts the existence of
winds, heat, cold and smells; yet no one has
seen the wind, or heat, or cold, or a smell.
Clothes become moist when hung near the sea,
and dry when spread in the sunshine; but no
one has seen the moisture entering or leaving
the clothes. A pavement trodden by many feet
is worn away; but the minute particles are removed
without our eyes being able to see them.</p>
<p>Another objector urges—"You say the atoms
are always moving, yet the things we look at,
which you assert to be vast numbers of moving
atoms, are often motionless." Him Lucretius
answers by an analogy. "And herein you need
not wonder at this, that though the first-beginnings
of things are all in motion, yet the sum is
seen to rest in supreme repose, unless when a
thing exhibits motions with its individual body.
For all the nature of first things lies far away
from our senses, beneath their ken; and, therefore,
since they are themselves beyond what you
can see, they must withdraw from sight their
motion as well; and the more so, that the things
which we can see do yet often conceal their
motions when a great distance off. Thus, often,
the woolly flocks as they crop the glad pastures
on a hill, creep on whither the grass, jewelled
with fresh dew, summons or invites each, and
<SPAN name="Page_20" id="Page_20"></SPAN>the lambs, fed to the full, gambol and playfully
butt; all which objects appear to us from a distance
to be blended together, and to rest like a
white spot on a green hill. Again, when mighty
legions fill with their movements all parts of the
plains, waging the mimicry of war, the glitter
lifts itself up to the sky, and the whole earth
round gleams with brass, and beneath a noise is
raised by the mighty tramplings of men, and the
mountains, stricken by the shouting, echo the
voices to the stars of heaven, and horsemen fly
about, and suddenly wheeling, scour across the
middle of the plains, shaking them with the
vehemence of their charge. And yet there is
some spot on the high hills, seen from which
they appear to stand still and to rest on the
plains as a bright spot."</p>
<p>The atomic theory of the Greek thinkers was
constructed by reasoning on natural phenomena.
Lucretius constantly appeals to observed facts
for confirmation of his theoretical teachings, or
refutation of opinions he thought erroneous.
Besides giving a general mental presentation of
the material universe, the theory was applied
to many specific transmutations; but minute
descriptions of what are now called chemical
changes could not be given in terms of the
theory, because no searching examination of so
much as one such change had been made, nor, I
think, one may say, could be made under the
conditions of Greek life. More than two thousand
years passed before investigators began to make
accurate measurements of the quantities of the
substances which take part in those changes
<SPAN name="Page_21" id="Page_21"></SPAN>wherein certain things seem to be destroyed
and other totally different things to be produced;
until accurate knowledge had been obtained of
the quantities of the definite substances which
interact in the transformations of matter, the
atomic theory could not do more than draw the
outlines of a picture of material changes.</p>
<p>A scientific theory has been described as "the
likening of our imaginings to what we actually
observe." So long as we observe only in the
rough, only in a broad and general way, our
imaginings must also be rough, broad, and general.
It was the great glory of the Greek thinkers
about natural events that their observations were
accurate, on the whole, and as far as they went,
and the theory they formed was based on no
trivial or accidental features of the facts, but on
what has proved to be the very essence of the
phenomena they sought to bring into one point of
view; for all the advances made in our own times
in clear knowledge of the transformations of
matter have been made by using, as a guide to
experimental inquiries, the conception that the
differences between the qualities of substances
are connected with differences in the weights
and movements of minute particles; and this
was the central idea of the atomic theory of the
Greek philosophers.</p>
<p>The atomic theory was used by the great
physicists of the later Renaissance, by Galileo,
Gassendi, Newton and others. Our own countryman,
John Dalton, while trying (in the early
years of the 19th century) to form a mental
presentation of the atmosphere in terms of the
<SPAN name="Page_22" id="Page_22"></SPAN>theory of atoms, rediscovered the possibility of
differences between the sizes of atoms, applied
this idea to the facts concerning the quantitative
compositions of compounds which had been
established by others, developed a method for
determining the relative weights of
atoms of different kinds, and started chemistry on the
course which it has followed so successfully.</p>
<p>Instead of blaming the Greek philosophers for
lack of quantitatively accurate experimental inquiry,
we should rather be full of admiring
wonder at the extraordinary acuteness of their
mental vision, and the soundness of their scientific
spirit.</p>
<p>The ancient atomists distinguished the essential
properties of things from their accidental features.
The former cannot be removed, Lucretius said,
without "utter destruction accompanying the
severance"; the latter may be altered "while
the nature of the thing remains unharmed."
As examples of essential properties, Lucretius
mentions "the weight of a stone, the heat of
fire, the fluidity of water." Such things as
liberty, war, slavery, riches, poverty, and the
like, were accounted accidents. Time also was
said to be an accident: it "exists not by itself;
but simply from the things which happen, the sense
apprehends what has been done in time
past, as well as what is present, and what is to
follow after."</p>
<p>As our story proceeds, we shall see that the
chemists of the middle ages, the alchemists,
founded their theory of material changes on the
difference between a supposed essential substratum
<SPAN name="Page_23" id="Page_23"></SPAN>of things, and their qualities which could be taken
off, they said, and put on, as clothes are removed
and replaced.</p>
<p>How different from the clear, harmonious,
orderly, Greek scheme, is any picture we can
form, from such quotations as I have given from
their writings, of the alchemists' conception of the
world. The Greeks likened their imaginings of
nature to the natural facts they observed; the
alchemists created an imaginary world after their own
likeness.</p>
<p>While Christianity was superseding the old
religions, and the theological system of the
Christian Church was replacing the cosmogonies
of the heathen, the contrast between the
power of evil and the power of good was more fully
realised than in the days of the Greeks; a
sharper division was drawn between this world
and another world, and that other world was
divided into two irreconcilable and absolutely
opposite parts. Man came to be regarded as the
centre of a tremendous and never-ceasing battle,
urged between the powers of good and the powers
of evil. The sights and sounds of nature were
regarded as the vestments, or the voices, of the
unseen combatants. Life was at once very real
and the mere shadow of a dream. The conditions
were favourable to the growth of magic; for man
was regarded as the measure of the universe, the
central figure in an awful tragedy.</p>
<p>Magic is an attempt, by thinking and speculating
about what we consider must be the order of
nature, to discover some means of penetrating
into the secret life of natural things, of realising
<SPAN name="Page_24" id="Page_24"></SPAN>the hidden powers and virtues of things, grasping
the concealed thread of unity which is supposed
to run through all phenomena however seemingly
diverse, entering into sympathy with the supposed
inner oneness of life, death, the present, past, and
future. Magic grows, and gathers strength, when
men are sure their theory of the universe must
be the one true theory, and they see only through
the glasses which their theory supplies. "He
who knows himself thoroughly knows God and
all the mysteries of His nature," says a modern
writer on magic. That saying expresses the
fundamental hypothesis, and the method, of
all systems of magic and mysticism. Of such
systems, alchemy was one.</p>
<hr />
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />