<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0020" id="link2HCH0020"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER VI. BOLDNESS </h2>
<p>THE place and part which boldness takes in the dynamic system of powers,
where it stands opposed to Foresight and prudence, has been stated in the
chapter on the certainty of the result in order thereby to show, that
theory has no right to restrict it by virtue of its legislative power.</p>
<p>But this noble impulse, with which the human soul raises itself above the
most formidable dangers, is to be regarded as an active principle
peculiarly belonging to War. In fact, in what branch of human activity
should boldness have a right of citizenship if not in War?</p>
<p>From the transport-driver and the drummer up to the General, it is the
noblest of virtues, the true steel which gives the weapon its edge and
brilliancy.</p>
<p>Let us admit in fact it has in War even its own prerogatives. Over and
above the result of the calculation of space, time, and quantity, we must
allow a certain percentage which boldness derives from the weakness of
others, whenever it gains the mastery. It is therefore, virtually, a
creative power. This is not difficult to demonstrate philosophically. As
often as boldness encounters hesitation, the probability of the result is
of necessity in its favour, because the very state of hesitation implies a
loss of equilibrium already. It is only when it encounters cautious
foresight—which we may say is just as bold, at all events just as
strong and powerful as itself—that it is at a disadvantage; such
cases, however, rarely occur. Out of the whole multitude of prudent men in
the world, the great majority are so from timidity.</p>
<p>Amongst large masses, boldness is a force, the special cultivation of
which can never be to the detriment of other forces, because the great
mass is bound to a higher will by the frame-work and joints of the order
of battle and of the service, and therefore is guided by an intelligent
power which is extraneous. Boldness is therefore here only like a spring
held down until its action is required.</p>
<p>The higher the rank the more necessary it is that boldness should be
accompanied by a reflective mind, that it may not be a mere blind outburst
of passion to no purpose; for with increase of rank it becomes always less
a matter of self-sacrifice and more a matter of the preservation of
others, and the good of the whole. Where regulations of the service, as a
kind of second nature, prescribe for the masses, reflection must be the
guide of the General, and in his case individual boldness in action may
easily become a fault. Still, at the same time, it is a fine failing, and
must not be looked at in the same light as any other. Happy the Army in
which an untimely boldness frequently manifests itself; it is an exuberant
growth which shows a rich soil. Even foolhardiness, that is boldness
without an object, is not to be despised; in point of fact it is the same
energy of feeling, only exercised as a kind of passion without any
co-operation of the intelligent faculties. It is only when it strikes at
the root of obedience, when it treats with contempt the orders of superior
authority, that it must be repressed as a dangerous evil, not on its own
account but on account of the act of disobedience, for there is nothing in
War which is of GREATER IMPORTANCE THAN OBEDIENCE.</p>
<p>The reader will readily agree with us that, supposing an equal degree of
discernment to be forthcoming in a certain number of cases, a thousand
times as many of them will end in disaster through over-anxiety as through
boldness.</p>
<p>One would suppose it natural that the interposition of a reasonable object
should stimulate boldness, and therefore lessen its intrinsic merit, and
yet the reverse is the case in reality.</p>
<p>The intervention of lucid thought or the general supremacy of mind
deprives the emotional forces of a great part of their power. On that
account BOLDNESS BECOMES OF RARER OCCURRENCE THE HIGHER WE ASCEND THE
SCALE OF RANK, for whether the discernment and the understanding do or do
not increase with these ranks still the Commanders, in their several
stations as they rise, are pressed upon more and more severely by
objective things, by relations and claims from without, so that they
become the more perplexed the lower the degree of their individual
intelligence. This so far as regards War is the chief foundation of the
truth of the French proverb:—</p>
<p>"Tel brille au second qui s' e'clipse an premier."</p>
<p>Almost all the Generals who are represented in history as merely having
attained to mediocrity, and as wanting in decision when in supreme
command, are men celebrated in their antecedent career for their boldness
and decision.(*)</p>
<p>(*) Beaulieu, Benedek, Bazaine, Buller, Melas, Mack. &c. &c.<br/></p>
<p>In those motives to bold action which arise from the pressure of necessity
we must make a distinction. Necessity has its degrees of intensity. If it
lies near at hand, if the person acting is in the pursuit of his object
driven into great dangers in order to escape others equally great, then we
can only admire his resolution, which still has also its value. If a young
man to show his skill in horsemanship leaps across a deep cleft, then he
is bold; if he makes the same leap pursued by a troop of head-chopping
Janissaries he is only resolute. But the farther off the necessity from
the point of action, the greater the number of relations intervening which
the mind has to traverse; in order to realise them, by so much the less
does necessity take from boldness in action. If Frederick the Great, in
the year 1756, saw that War was inevitable, and that he could only escape
destruction by being beforehand with his enemies, it became necessary for
him to commence the War himself, but at the same time it was certainly
very bold: for few men in his position would have made up their minds to
do so.</p>
<p>Although Strategy is only the province of Generals-in-Chief or Commanders
in the higher positions, still boldness in all the other branches of an
Army is as little a matter of indifference to it as their other military
virtues. With an Army belonging to a bold race, and in which the spirit of
boldness has been always nourished, very different things may be
undertaken than with one in which this virtue, is unknown; for that reason
we have considered it in connection with an Army. But our subject is
specially the boldness of the General, and yet we have not much to say
about it after having described this military virtue in a general way to
the best of our ability.</p>
<p>The higher we rise in a position of command, the more of the mind,
understanding, and penetration predominate in activity, the more therefore
is boldness, which is a property of the feelings, kept in subjection, and
for that reason we find it so rarely in the highest positions, but then,
so much the more should it be admired. Boldness, directed by an overruling
intelligence, is the stamp of the hero: this boldness does not consist in
venturing directly against the nature of things, in a downright contempt
of the laws of probability, but, if a choice is once made, in the rigorous
adherence to that higher calculation which genius, the tact of judgment,
has gone over with the speed of lightning. The more boldness lends wings
to the mind and the discernment, so much the farther they will reach in
their flight, so much the more comprehensive will be the view, the more
exact the result, but certainly always only in the sense that with greater
objects greater dangers are connected. The ordinary man, not to speak of
the weak and irresolute, arrives at an exact result so far as such is
possible without ocular demonstration, at most after diligent reflection
in his chamber, at a distance from danger and responsibility. Let danger
and responsibility draw close round him in every direction, then he loses
the power of comprehensive vision, and if he retains this in any measure
by the influence of others, still he will lose his power of DECISION,
because in that point no one can help him.</p>
<p>We think then that it is impossible to imagine a distinguished General
without boldness, that is to say, that no man can become one who is not
born with this power of the soul, and we therefore look upon it as the
first requisite for such a career. How much of this inborn power,
developed and moderated through education and the circumstances of life,
is left when the man has attained a high position, is the second question.
The greater this power still is, the stronger will genius be on the wing,
the higher will be its flight. The risks become always greater, but the
purpose grows with them. Whether its lines proceed out of and get their
direction from a distant necessity, or whether they converge to the
keystone of a building which ambition has planned, whether Frederick or
Alexander acts, is much the same as regards the critical view. If the one
excites the imagination more because it is bolder, the other pleases the
understanding most, because it has in it more absolute necessity.</p>
<p>We have still to advert to one very important circumstance.</p>
<p>The spirit of boldness can exist in an Army, either because it is in the
people, or because it has been generated in a successful War conducted by
able Generals. In the latter case it must of course be dispensed with at
the commencement.</p>
<p>Now in our days there is hardly any other means of educating the spirit of
a people in this respect, except by War, and that too under bold Generals.
By it alone can that effeminacy of feeling be counteracted, that
propensity to seek for the enjoyment of comfort, which cause degeneracy in
a people rising in prosperity and immersed in an extremely busy commerce.</p>
<p>A Nation can hope to have a strong position in the political world only if
its character and practice in actual War mutually support each other in
constant reciprocal action.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0021" id="link2HCH0021"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER VII. PERSEVERANCE </h2>
<p>THE reader expects to hear of angles and lines, and finds, instead of
these citizens of the scientific world, only people out of common life,
such as he meets with every day in the street. And yet the author cannot
make up his mind to become a hair's breadth more mathematical than the
subject seems to him to require, and he is not alarmed at the surprise
which the reader may show.</p>
<p>In War more than anywhere else in the world things happen differently to
what we had expected, and look differently when near, to what they did at
a distance. With what serenity the architect can watch his work gradually
rising and growing into his plan. The doctor although much more at the
mercy of mysterious agencies and chances than the architect, still knows
enough of the forms and effects of his means. In War, on the other hand,
the Commander of an immense whole finds himself in a constant whirlpool of
false and true information, of mistakes committed through fear, through
negligence, through precipitation, of contraventions of his authority,
either from mistaken or correct motives, from ill will, true or false
sense of duty, indolence or exhaustion, of accidents which no mortal could
have foreseen. In short, he is the victim of a hundred thousand
impressions, of which the most have an intimidating, the fewest an
encouraging tendency. By long experience in War, the tact is acquired of
readily appreciating the value of these incidents; high courage and
stability of character stand proof against them, as the rock resists the
beating of the waves. He who would yield to these impressions would never
carry out an undertaking, and on that account PERSEVERANCE in the proposed
object, as long as there is no decided reason against it, is a most
necessary counterpoise. Further, there is hardly any celebrated enterprise
in War which was not achieved by endless exertion, pains, and privations;
and as here the weakness of the physical and moral man is ever disposed to
yield, only an immense force of will, which manifests itself in
perseverance admired by present and future generations, can conduct to our
goal.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0022" id="link2HCH0022"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER VIII. SUPERIORITY OF NUMBERS </h2>
<p>THIS is in tactics, as well as in Strategy, the most general principle of
victory, and shall be examined by us first in its generality, for which we
may be permitted the following exposition:</p>
<p>Strategy fixes the point where, the time when, and the numerical force
with which the battle is to be fought. By this triple determination it has
therefore a very essential influence on the issue of the combat. If
tactics has fought the battle, if the result is over, let it be victory or
defeat, Strategy makes such use of it as can be made in accordance with
the great object of the War. This object is naturally often a very distant
one, seldom does it lie quite close at hand. A series of other objects
subordinate themselves to it as means. These objects, which are at the
same time means to a higher purpose, may be practically of various kinds;
even the ultimate aim of the whole War may be a different one in every
case. We shall make ourselves acquainted with these things according as we
come to know the separate objects which they come, in contact with; and it
is not our intention here to embrace the whole subject by a complete
enumeration of them, even if that were possible. We therefore let the
employment of the battle stand over for the present.</p>
<p>Even those things through which Strategy has an influence on the issue of
the combat, inasmuch as it establishes the same, to a certain extent
decrees them, are not so simple that they can be embraced in one single
view. For as Strategy appoints time, place and force, it can do so in
practice in many ways, each of which influences in a different manner the
result of the combat as well as its consequences. Therefore we shall only
get acquainted with this also by degrees, that is, through the subjects
which more closely determine the application.</p>
<p>If we strip the combat of all modifications which it may undergo according
to its immediate purpose and the circumstances from which it proceeds,
lastly if we set aside the valour of the troops, because that is a given
quantity, then there remains only the bare conception of the combat, that
is a combat without form, in which we distinguish nothing but the number
of the combatants.</p>
<p>This number will therefore determine victory. Now from the number of
things above deducted to get to this point, it is shown that the
superiority in numbers in a battle is only one of the factors employed to
produce victory that therefore so far from having with the superiority in
number obtained all, or even only the principal thing, we have perhaps got
very little by it, according as the other circumstances which co-operate
happen to vary.</p>
<p>But this superiority has degrees, it may be imagined as twofold, threefold
or fourfold, and every one sees, that by increasing in this way, it must
(at last) overpower everything else.</p>
<p>In such an aspect we grant, that the superiority in numbers is the most
important factor in the result of a combat, only it must be sufficiently
great to be a counterpoise to all the other co-operating circumstances.
The direct result of this is, that the greatest possible number of troops
should be brought into action at the decisive point.</p>
<p>Whether the troops thus brought are sufficient or not, we have then done
in this respect all that our means allowed. This is the first principle in
Strategy, therefore in general as now stated, it is just as well suited
for Greeks and Persians, or for Englishmen and Mahrattas, as for French
and Germans. But we shall take a glance at our relations in Europe, as
respects War, in order to arrive at some more definite idea on this
subject.</p>
<p>Here we find Armies much more alike in equipment, organisation, and
practical skill of every kind. There only remains a difference in the
military virtue of Armies, and in the talent of Generals which may
fluctuate with time from side to side. If we go through the military
history of modern Europe, we find no example of a Marathon.</p>
<p>Frederick the Great beat 80,000 Austrians at Leuthen with about 30,000
men, and at Rosbach with 25,000 some 50,000 allies; these are however the
only instances of victories gained against an enemy double, or more than
double in numbers. Charles XII, in the battle of Narva, we cannot well
quote, for the Russians were at that time hardly to be regarded as
Europeans, also the principal circumstances, even of the battle, are too
little known. Buonaparte had at Dresden 120,000 against 220,000, therefore
not the double. At Kollin, Frederick the Great did not succeed, with
30,000 against 50,000 Austrians, neither did Buonaparte in the desperate
battle of Leipsic, where he was 160,000 strong, against 280,000.</p>
<p>From this we may infer, that it is very difficult in the present state of
Europe, for the most talented General to gain a victory over an enemy
double his strength. Now if we see double numbers prove such a weight in
the scale against the greatest Generals, we may be sure, that in ordinary
cases, in small as well as great combats, an important superiority of
numbers, but which need not be over two to one, will be sufficient to
ensure the victory, however disadvantageous other circumstances may be.
Certainly, we may imagine a defile which even tenfold would not suffice to
force, but in such a case it can be no question of a battle at all.</p>
<p>We think, therefore, that under our conditions, as well as in all similar
ones, the superiority at the decisive point is a matter of capital
importance, and that this subject, in the generality of cases, is
decidedly the most important of all. The strength at the decisive point
depends on the absolute strength of the Army, and on skill in making use
of it.</p>
<p>The first rule is therefore to enter the field with an Army as strong as
possible. This sounds very like a commonplace, but still it is really not
so.</p>
<p>In order to show that for a long time the strength of forces was by no
means regarded as a chief point, we need only observe, that in most, and
even in the most detailed histories of the Wars in the eighteenth century,
the strength of the Armies is either not given at all, or only
incidentally, and in no case is any special value laid upon it. Tempelhof
in his history of the Seven Years' War is the earliest writer who gives it
regularly, but at the same time he does it only very superficially.</p>
<p>Even Massenbach, in his manifold critical observations on the Prussian
campaigns of 1793-94 in the Vosges, talks a great deal about hills and
valleys, roads and footpaths, but does not say a syllable about mutual
strength.</p>
<p>Another proof lies in a wonderful notion which haunted the heads of many
critical historians, according to which there was a certain size of an
Army which was the best, a normal strength, beyond which the forces in
excess were burdensome rather than serviceable.(*)</p>
<p>(*) Tempelhof and Montalembert are the first we recollect as<br/>
examples—the first in a passage of his first part, page<br/>
148; the other in his correspondence relative to the plan of<br/>
operations of the Russians in 1759.<br/></p>
<p>Lastly, there are a number of instances to be found, in which all the
available forces were not really brought into the battle,(*) or into the
War, because the superiority of numbers was not considered to have that
importance which in the nature of things belongs to it.</p>
<p>(*) The Prussians at Jena, 1806. Wellington at Waterloo.</p>
<p>If we are thoroughly penetrated with the conviction that with a
considerable superiority of numbers everything possible is to be effected,
then it cannot fail that this clear conviction reacts on the preparations
for the War, so as to make us appear in the field with as many troops as
possible, and either to give us ourselves the superiority, or at least to
guard against the enemy obtaining it. So much for what concerns the
absolute force with which the War is to be conducted.</p>
<p>The measure of this absolute force is determined by the Government; and
although with this determination the real action of War commences, and it
forms an essential part of the Strategy of the War, still in most cases
the General who is to command these forces in the War must regard their
absolute strength as a given quantity, whether it be that he has had no
voice in fixing it, or that circumstances prevented a sufficient expansion
being given to it.</p>
<p>There remains nothing, therefore, where an absolute superiority is not
attainable, but to produce a relative one at the decisive point, by making
skilful use of what we have.</p>
<p>The calculation of space and time appears as the most essential thing to
this end—and this has caused that subject to be regarded as one
which embraces nearly the whole art of using military forces. Indeed, some
have gone so far as to ascribe to great strategists and tacticians a
mental organ peculiarly adapted to this point.</p>
<p>But the calculation of time and space, although it lies universally at the
foundation of Strategy, and is to a certain extent its daily bread, is
still neither the most difficult, nor the most decisive one.</p>
<p>If we take an unprejudiced glance at military history, we shall find that
the instances in which mistakes in such a calculation have proved the
cause of serious losses are very rare, at least in Strategy. But if the
conception of a skilful combination of time and space is fully to account
for every instance of a resolute and active Commander beating several
separate opponents with one and the same army (Frederick the Great,
Buonaparte), then we perplex ourselves unnecessarily with conventional
language. For the sake of clearness and the profitable use of conceptions,
it is necessary that things should always be called by their right names.</p>
<p>The right appreciation of their opponents (Daun, Schwartzenberg), the
audacity to leave for a short space of time a small force only before
them, energy in forced marches, boldness in sudden attacks, the
intensified activity which great souls acquire in the moment of danger,
these are the grounds of such victories; and what have these to do with
the ability to make an exact calculation of two such simple things as time
and space?</p>
<p>But even this ricochetting play of forces, "when the victories at Rosbach
and Montmirail give the impulse to victories at Leuthen and Montereau," to
which great Generals on the defensive have often trusted, is still, if we
would be clear and exact, only a rare occurrence in history.</p>
<p>Much more frequently the relative superiority—that is, the skilful
assemblage of superior forces at the decisive point—has its
foundation in the right appreciation of those points, in the judicious
direction which by that means has been given to the forces from the very
first, and in the resolution required to sacrifice the unimportant to the
advantage of the important—that is, to keep the forces concentrated
in an overpowering mass. In this, Frederick the Great and Buonaparte are
particularly characteristic.</p>
<p>We think we have now allotted to the superiority in numbers the importance
which belongs to it; it is to be regarded as the fundamental idea, always
to be aimed at before all and as far as possible.</p>
<p>But to regard it on this account as a necessary condition of victory would
be a complete misconception of our exposition; in the conclusion to be
drawn from it there lies nothing more than the value which should attach
to numerical strength in the combat. If that strength is made as great as
possible, then the maxim is satisfied; a review of the total relations
must then decide whether or not the combat is to be avoided for want of
sufficient force.(*)</p>
<p>(*) Owing to our freedom from invasion, and to the condition<br/>
which arise in our Colonial Wars, we have not yet, in<br/>
England, arrived at a correct appreciation of the value of<br/>
superior numbers in War, and still adhere to the idea of an<br/>
Army just "big enough," which Clausewitz has so unsparingly<br/>
ridiculed. (EDITOR.)<br/></p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0023" id="link2HCH0023"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER IX. THE SURPRISE </h2>
<p>FROM the subject of the foregoing chapter, the general endeavour to attain
a relative superiority, there follows another endeavour which must
consequently be just as general in its nature: this is the SURPRISE of the
enemy. It lies more or less at the foundation of all undertakings, for
without it the preponderance at the decisive point is not properly
conceivable.</p>
<p>The surprise is, therefore, not only the means to the attainment of
numerical superiority; but it is also to be regarded as a substantive
principle in itself, on account of its moral effect. When it is successful
in a high degree, confusion and broken courage in the enemy's ranks are
the consequences; and of the degree to which these multiply a success,
there are examples enough, great and small. We are not now speaking of the
particular surprise which belongs to the attack, but of the endeavour by
measures generally, and especially by the distribution of forces, to
surprise the enemy, which can be imagined just as well in the defensive,
and which in the tactical defence particularly is a chief point.</p>
<p>We say, surprise lies at the foundation of all undertakings without
exception, only in very different degrees according to the nature of the
undertaking and other circumstances.</p>
<p>This difference, indeed, originates in the properties or peculiarities of
the Army and its Commander, in those even of the Government.</p>
<p>Secrecy and rapidity are the two factors in this product and these suppose
in the Government and the Commander-in-Chief great energy, and on the part
of the Army a high sense of military duty. With effeminacy and loose
principles it is in vain to calculate upon a surprise. But so general,
indeed so indispensable, as is this endeavour, and true as it is that it
is never wholly unproductive of effect, still it is not the less true that
it seldom succeeds to a REMARKABLE degree, and this follows from the
nature of the idea itself. We should form an erroneous conception if we
believed that by this means chiefly there is much to be attained in War.
In idea it promises a great deal; in the execution it generally sticks
fast by the friction of the whole machine.</p>
<p>In tactics the surprise is much more at home, for the very natural reason
that all times and spaces are on a smaller scale. It will, therefore, in
Strategy be the more feasible in proportion as the measures lie nearer to
the province of tactics, and more difficult the higher up they lie towards
the province of policy.</p>
<p>The preparations for a War usually occupy several months; the assembly of
an Army at its principal positions requires generally the formation of
dep�ts and magazines, and long marches, the object of which can be guessed
soon enough.</p>
<p>It therefore rarely happens that one State surprises another by a War, or
by the direction which it gives the mass of its forces. In the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries, when War turned very much upon sieges, it was a
frequent aim, and quite a peculiar and important chapter in the Art of
War, to invest a strong place unexpectedly, but even that only rarely
succeeded.(*)</p>
<p>(*) Railways, steamships, and telegraphs have, however,<br/>
enormously modified the relative importance and<br/>
practicability of surprise. (EDITOR.)<br/></p>
<p>On the other hand, with things which can be done in a day or two, a
surprise is much more conceivable, and, therefore, also it is often not
difficult thus to gain a march upon the enemy, and thereby a position, a
point of country, a road, &c. But it is evident that what surprise
gains in this way in easy execution, it loses in the efficacy, as the
greater the efficacy the greater always the difficulty of execution.
Whoever thinks that with such surprises on a small scale, he may connect
great results—as, for example, the gain of a battle, the capture of
an important magazine—believes in something which it is certainly
very possible to imagine, but for which there is no warrant in history;
for there are upon the whole very few instances where anything great has
resulted from such surprises; from which we may justly conclude that
inherent difficulties lie in the way of their success.</p>
<p>Certainly, whoever would consult history on such points must not depend on
sundry battle steeds of historical critics, on their wise dicta and
self-complacent terminology, but look at facts with his own eyes. There
is, for instance, a certain day in the campaign in Silesia, 1761, which,
in this respect, has attained a kind of notoriety. It is the 22nd July, on
which Frederick the Great gained on Laudon the march to Nossen, near
Neisse, by which, as is said, the junction of the Austrian and Russian
armies in Upper Silesia became impossible, and, therefore, a period of
four weeks was gained by the King. Whoever reads over this occurrence
carefully in the principal histories,(*) and considers it impartially,
will, in the march of the 22nd July, never find this importance; and
generally in the whole of the fashionable logic on this subject, he will
see nothing but contradictions; but in the proceedings of Laudon, in this
renowned period of manoeuvres, much that is unaccountable. How could one,
with a thirst for truth, and clear conviction, accept such historical
evidence?</p>
<p>(*) Tempelhof, The Veteran, Frederick the Great. Compare<br/>
also (Clausewitz) "Hinterlassene Werke," vol. x., p. 158.<br/></p>
<p>When we promise ourselves great effects in a campaign from the principle
of surprising, we think upon great activity, rapid resolutions, and forced
marches, as the means of producing them; but that these things, even when
forthcoming in a very high degree, will not always produce the desired
effect, we see in examples given by Generals, who may be allowed to have
had the greatest talent in the use of these means, Frederick the Great and
Buonaparte. The first when he left Dresden so suddenly in July 1760, and
falling upon Lascy, then turned against Dresden, gained nothing by the
whole of that intermezzo, but rather placed his affairs in a condition
notably worse, as the fortress Glatz fell in the meantime.</p>
<p>In 1813, Buonaparte turned suddenly from Dresden twice against Bluecher,
to say nothing of his incursion into Bohemia from Upper Lusatia, and both
times without in the least attaining his object. They were blows in the
air which only cost him time and force, and might have placed him in a
dangerous position in Dresden.</p>
<p>Therefore, even in this field, a surprise does not necessarily meet with
great success through the mere activity, energy, and resolution of the
Commander; it must be favoured by other circumstances. But we by no means
deny that there can be success; we only connect with it a necessity of
favourable circumstances, which, certainly do not occur very frequently,
and which the Commander can seldom bring about himself.</p>
<p>Just those two Generals afford each a striking illustration of this. We
take first Buonaparte in his famous enterprise against Bluecher's Army in
February 1814, when it was separated from the Grand Army, and descending
the Marne. It would not be easy to find a two days' march to surprise the
enemy productive of greater results than this; Bluecher's Army, extended
over a distance of three days' march, was beaten in detail, and suffered a
loss nearly equal to that of defeat in a great battle. This was completely
the effect of a surprise, for if Bluecher had thought of such a near
possibility of an attack from Buonaparte(*) he would have organised his
march quite differently. To this mistake of Bluecher's the result is to be
attributed. Buonaparte did not know all these circumstances, and so there
was a piece of good fortune that mixed itself up in his favour.</p>
<p>(*) Bluecher believed his march to be covered by Pahlen's<br/>
Cossacks, but these had been withdrawn without warning to<br/>
him by the Grand Army Headquarters under Schwartzenberg.<br/></p>
<p>It is the same with the battle of Liegnitz, 1760. Frederick the Great
gained this fine victory through altering during the night a position
which he had just before taken up. Laudon was through this completely
surprised, and lost 70 pieces of artillery and 10,000 men. Although
Frederick the Great had at this time adopted the principle of moving
backwards and forwards in order to make a battle impossible, or at least
to disconcert the enemy's plans, still the alteration of position on the
night of the 14-15 was not made exactly with that intention, but as the
King himself says, because the position of the 14th did not please him.
Here, therefore, also chance was hard at work; without this happy
conjunction of the attack and the change of position in the night, and the
difficult nature of the country, the result would not have been the same.</p>
<p>Also in the higher and highest province of Strategy there are some
instances of surprises fruitful in results. We shall only cite the
brilliant marches of the Great Elector against the Swedes from Franconia
to Pomerania and from the Mark (Brandenburg) to the Pregel in 1757, and
the celebrated passage of the Alps by Buonaparte, 1800. In the latter case
an Army gave up its whole theatre of war by a capitulation, and in 1757
another Army was very near giving up its theatre of war and itself as
well. Lastly, as an instance of a War wholly unexpected, we may bring
forward the invasion of Silesia by Frederick the Great. Great and powerful
are here the results everywhere, but such events are not common in history
if we do not confuse with them cases in which a State, for want of
activity and energy (Saxony 1756, and Russia, 1812), has not completed its
preparations in time.</p>
<p>Now there still remains an observation which concerns the essence of the
thing. A surprise can only be effected by that party which gives the law
to the other; and he who is in the right gives the law. If we surprise the
adversary by a wrong measure, then instead of reaping good results, we may
have to bear a sound blow in return; in any case the adversary need not
trouble himself much about our surprise, he has in our mistake the means
of turning off the evil. As the offensive includes in itself much more
positive action than the defensive, so the surprise is certainly more in
its place with the assailant, but by no means invariably, as we shall
hereafter see. Mutual surprises by the offensive and defensive may
therefore meet, and then that one will have the advantage who has hit the
nail on the head the best.</p>
<p>So should it be, but practical life does not keep to this line so exactly,
and that for a very simple reason. The moral effects which attend a
surprise often convert the worst case into a good one for the side they
favour, and do not allow the other to make any regular determination. We
have here in view more than anywhere else not only the chief Commander,
but each single one, because a surprise has the effect in particular of
greatly loosening unity, so that the individuality of each separate leader
easily comes to light.</p>
<p>Much depends here on the general relation in which the two parties stand
to each other. If the one side through a general moral superiority can
intimidate and outdo the other, then he can make use of the surprise with
more success, and even reap good fruit where properly he should come to
ruin.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0024" id="link2HCH0024"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER X. STRATAGEM </h2>
<p>STRATAGEM implies a concealed intention, and therefore is opposed to
straightforward dealing, in the same way as wit is the opposite of direct
proof. It has therefore nothing in common with means of persuasion, of
self-interest, of force, but a great deal to do with deceit, because that
likewise conceals its object. It is itself a deceit as well when it is
done, but still it differs from what is commonly called deceit, in this
respect that there is no direct breach of word. The deceiver by stratagem
leaves it to the person himself whom he is deceiving to commit the errors
of understanding which at last, flowing into ONE result, suddenly change
the nature of things in his eyes. We may therefore say, as nit is a
sleight of hand with ideas and conceptions, so stratagem is a sleight of
hand with actions.</p>
<p>At first sight it appears as if Strategy had not improperly derived its
name from stratagem; and that, with all the real and apparent changes
which the whole character of War has undergone since the time of the
Greeks, this term still points to its real nature.</p>
<p>If we leave to tactics the actual delivery of the blow, the battle itself,
and look upon Strategy as the art of using this means with skill, then
besides the forces of the character, such as burning ambition which always
presses like a spring, a strong will which hardly bends &c. &c.,
there seems no subjective quality so suited to guide and inspire strategic
activity as stratagem. The general tendency to surprise, treated of in the
foregoing chapter, points to this conclusion, for there is a degree of
stratagem, be it ever so small, which lies at the foundation of every
attempt to surprise.</p>
<p>But however much we feel a desire to see the actors in War outdo each
other in hidden activity, readiness, and stratagem, still we must admit
that these qualities show themselves but little in history, and have
rarely been able to work their way to the surface from amongst the mass of
relations and circumstances.</p>
<p>The explanation of this is obvious, and it is almost identical with the
subject matter of the preceding chapter.</p>
<p>Strategy knows no other activity than the regulating of combat with the
measures which relate to it. It has no concern, like ordinary life, with
transactions which consist merely of words—that is, in expressions,
declarations, &c. But these, which are very inexpensive, are chiefly
the means with which the wily one takes in those he practises upon.</p>
<p>That which there is like it in War, plans and orders given merely as
make-believers, false reports sent on purpose to the enemy—is
usually of so little effect in the strategic field that it is only
resorted to in particular cases which offer of themselves, therefore
cannot be regarded as spontaneous action which emanates from the leader.</p>
<p>But such measures as carrying out the arrangements for a battle, so far as
to impose upon the enemy, require a considerable expenditure of time and
power; of course, the greater the impression to be made, the greater the
expenditure in these respects. And as this is usually not given for the
purpose, very few demonstrations, so-called, in Strategy, effect the
object for which they are designed. In fact, it is dangerous to detach
large forces for any length of time merely for a trick, because there is
always the risk of its being done in vain, and then these forces are
wanted at the decisive point.</p>
<p>The chief actor in War is always thoroughly sensible of this sober truth,
and therefore he has no desire to play at tricks of agility. The bitter
earnestness of necessity presses so fully into direct action that there is
no room for that game. In a word, the pieces on the strategical
chess-board want that mobility which is the element of stratagem and
subtility.</p>
<p>The conclusion which we draw, is that a correct and penetrating eye is a
more necessary and more useful quality for a General than craftiness,
although that also does no harm if it does not exist at the expense of
necessary qualities of the heart, which is only too often the case.</p>
<p>But the weaker the forces become which are under the command of Strategy,
so much the more they become adapted for stratagem, so that to the quite
feeble and little, for whom no prudence, no sagacity is any longer
sufficient at the point where all art seems to forsake him, stratagem
offers itself as a last resource. The more helpless his situation, the
more everything presses towards one single, desperate blow, the more
readily stratagem comes to the aid of his boldness. Let loose from all
further calculations, freed from all concern for the future, boldness and
stratagem intensify each other, and thus collect at one point an
infinitesimal glimmering of hope into a single ray, which may likewise
serve to kindle a flame.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />