<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0007" id="link2HCH0007"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Seven: The Democratic Conception in Education </h2>
<p>For the most part, save incidentally, we have hitherto been concerned with
education as it may exist in any social group. We have now to make
explicit the differences in the spirit, material, and method of education
as it operates in different types of community life. To say that education
is a social function, securing direction and development in the immature
through their participation in the life of the group to which they belong,
is to say in effect that education will vary with the quality of life
which prevails in a group. Particularly is it true that a society which
not only changes but-which has the ideal of such change as will improve
it, will have different standards and methods of education from one which
aims simply at the perpetuation of its own customs. To make the general
ideas set forth applicable to our own educational practice, it is,
therefore, necessary to come to closer quarters with the nature of present
social life.</p>
<p>1. The Implications of Human Association. Society is one word, but many
things. Men associate together in all kinds of ways and for all kinds of
purposes. One man is concerned in a multitude of diverse groups, in which
his associates may be quite different. It often seems as if they had
nothing in common except that they are modes of associated life. Within
every larger social organization there are numerous minor groups: not only
political subdivisions, but industrial, scientific, religious,
associations. There are political parties with differing aims, social
sets, cliques, gangs, corporations, partnerships, groups bound closely
together by ties of blood, and so on in endless variety. In many modern
states and in some ancient, there is great diversity of populations, of
varying languages, religions, moral codes, and traditions. From this
standpoint, many a minor political unit, one of our large cities, for
example, is a congeries of loosely associated societies, rather than an
inclusive and permeating community of action and thought. (See ante, p.
20.)</p>
<p>The terms society, community, are thus ambiguous. They have both a
eulogistic or normative sense, and a descriptive sense; a meaning de jure
and a meaning de facto. In social philosophy, the former connotation is
almost always uppermost. Society is conceived as one by its very nature.
The qualities which accompany this unity, praiseworthy community of
purpose and welfare, loyalty to public ends, mutuality of sympathy, are
emphasized. But when we look at the facts which the term denotes instead
of confining our attention to its intrinsic connotation, we find not
unity, but a plurality of societies, good and bad. Men banded together in
a criminal conspiracy, business aggregations that prey upon the public
while serving it, political machines held together by the interest of
plunder, are included. If it is said that such organizations are not
societies because they do not meet the ideal requirements of the notion of
society, the answer, in part, is that the conception of society is then
made so "ideal" as to be of no use, having no reference to facts; and in
part, that each of these organizations, no matter how opposed to the
interests of other groups, has something of the praiseworthy qualities of
"Society" which hold it together. There is honor among thieves, and a band
of robbers has a common interest as respects its members. Gangs are marked
by fraternal feeling, and narrow cliques by intense loyalty to their own
codes. Family life may be marked by exclusiveness, suspicion, and jealousy
as to those without, and yet be a model of amity and mutual aid within.
Any education given by a group tends to socialize its members, but the
quality and value of the socialization depends upon the habits and aims of
the group. Hence, once more, the need of a measure for the worth of any
given mode of social life. In seeking this measure, we have to avoid two
extremes. We cannot set up, out of our heads, something we regard as an
ideal society. We must base our conception upon societies which actually
exist, in order to have any assurance that our ideal is a practicable one.
But, as we have just seen, the ideal cannot simply repeat the traits which
are actually found. The problem is to extract the desirable traits of
forms of community life which actually exist, and employ them to criticize
undesirable features and suggest improvement. Now in any social group
whatever, even in a gang of thieves, we find some interest held in common,
and we find a certain amount of interaction and cooperative intercourse
with other groups. From these two traits we derive our standard. How
numerous and varied are the interests which are consciously shared? How
full and free is the interplay with other forms of association? If we
apply these considerations to, say, a criminal band, we find that the ties
which consciously hold the members together are few in number, reducible
almost to a common interest in plunder; and that they are of such a nature
as to isolate the group from other groups with respect to give and take of
the values of life. Hence, the education such a society gives is partial
and distorted. If we take, on the other hand, the kind of family life
which illustrates the standard, we find that there are material,
intellectual, aesthetic interests in which all participate and that the
progress of one member has worth for the experience of other members—it
is readily communicable—and that the family is not an isolated
whole, but enters intimately into relationships with business groups, with
schools, with all the agencies of culture, as well as with other similar
groups, and that it plays a due part in the political organization and in
return receives support from it. In short, there are many interests
consciously communicated and shared; and there are varied and free points
of contact with other modes of association.</p>
<p>I. Let us apply the first element in this criterion to a despotically
governed state. It is not true there is no common interest in such an
organization between governed and governors. The authorities in command
must make some appeal to the native activities of the subjects, must call
some of their powers into play. Talleyrand said that a government could do
everything with bayonets except sit on them. This cynical declaration is
at least a recognition that the bond of union is not merely one of
coercive force. It may be said, however, that the activities appealed to
are themselves unworthy and degrading—that such a government calls
into functioning activity simply capacity for fear. In a way, this
statement is true. But it overlooks the fact that fear need not be an
undesirable factor in experience. Caution, circumspection, prudence,
desire to foresee future events so as to avert what is harmful, these
desirable traits are as much a product of calling the impulse of fear into
play as is cowardice and abject submission. The real difficulty is that
the appeal to fear is isolated. In evoking dread and hope of specific
tangible reward—say comfort and ease—many other capacities are
left untouched. Or rather, they are affected, but in such a way as to
pervert them. Instead of operating on their own account they are reduced
to mere servants of attaining pleasure and avoiding pain.</p>
<p>This is equivalent to saying that there is no extensive number of common
interests; there is no free play back and forth among the members of the
social group. Stimulation and response are exceedingly one-sided. In order
to have a large number of values in common, all the members of the group
must have an equable opportunity to receive and to take from others. There
must be a large variety of shared undertakings and experiences. Otherwise,
the influences which educate some into masters, educate others into
slaves. And the experience of each party loses in meaning, when the free
interchange of varying modes of life-experience is arrested. A separation
into a privileged and a subject-class prevents social endosmosis. The
evils thereby affecting the superior class are less material and less
perceptible, but equally real. Their culture tends to be sterile, to be
turned back to feed on itself; their art becomes a showy display and
artificial; their wealth luxurious; their knowledge overspecialized; their
manners fastidious rather than humane.</p>
<p>Lack of the free and equitable intercourse which springs from a variety of
shared interests makes intellectual stimulation unbalanced. Diversity of
stimulation means novelty, and novelty means challenge to thought. The
more activity is restricted to a few definite lines—as it is when
there are rigid class lines preventing adequate interplay of experiences—the
more action tends to become routine on the part of the class at a
disadvantage, and capricious, aimless, and explosive on the part of the
class having the materially fortunate position. Plato defined a slave as
one who accepts from another the purposes which control his conduct. This
condition obtains even where there is no slavery in the legal sense. It is
found wherever men are engaged in activity which is socially serviceable,
but whose service they do not understand and have no personal interest in.
Much is said about scientific management of work. It is a narrow view
which restricts the science which secures efficiency of operation to
movements of the muscles. The chief opportunity for science is the
discovery of the relations of a man to his work—including his
relations to others who take part—which will enlist his intelligent
interest in what he is doing. Efficiency in production often demands
division of labor. But it is reduced to a mechanical routine unless
workers see the technical, intellectual, and social relationships involved
in what they do, and engage in their work because of the motivation
furnished by such perceptions. The tendency to reduce such things as
efficiency of activity and scientific management to purely technical
externals is evidence of the one-sided stimulation of thought given to
those in control of industry—those who supply its aims. Because of
their lack of all-round and well-balanced social interest, there is not
sufficient stimulus for attention to the human factors and relationships
in industry. Intelligence is narrowed to the factors concerned with
technical production and marketing of goods. No doubt, a very acute and
intense intelligence in these narrow lines can be developed, but the
failure to take into account the significant social factors means none the
less an absence of mind, and a corresponding distortion of emotional life.
II. This illustration (whose point is to be extended to all associations
lacking reciprocity of interest) brings us to our second point. The
isolation and exclusiveness of a gang or clique brings its antisocial
spirit into relief. But this same spirit is found wherever one group has
interests "of its own" which shut it out from full interaction with other
groups, so that its prevailing purpose is the protection of what it has
got, instead of reorganization and progress through wider relationships.
It marks nations in their isolation from one another; families which
seclude their domestic concerns as if they had no connection with a larger
life; schools when separated from the interest of home and community; the
divisions of rich and poor; learned and unlearned. The essential point is
that isolation makes for rigidity and formal institutionalizing of life,
for static and selfish ideals within the group. That savage tribes regard
aliens and enemies as synonymous is not accidental. It springs from the
fact that they have identified their experience with rigid adherence to
their past customs. On such a basis it is wholly logical to fear
intercourse with others, for such contact might dissolve custom. It would
certainly occasion reconstruction. It is a commonplace that an alert and
expanding mental life depends upon an enlarging range of contact with the
physical environment. But the principle applies even more significantly to
the field where we are apt to ignore it—the sphere of social
contacts. Every expansive era in the history of mankind has coincided with
the operation of factors which have tended to eliminate distance between
peoples and classes previously hemmed off from one another. Even the
alleged benefits of war, so far as more than alleged, spring from the fact
that conflict of peoples at least enforces intercourse between them and
thus accidentally enables them to learn from one another, and thereby to
expand their horizons. Travel, economic and commercial tendencies, have at
present gone far to break down external barriers; to bring peoples and
classes into closer and more perceptible connection with one another. It
remains for the most part to secure the intellectual and emotional
significance of this physical annihilation of space.</p>
<p>2. The Democratic Ideal. The two elements in our criterion both point to
democracy. The first signifies not only more numerous and more varied
points of shared common interest, but greater reliance upon the
recognition of mutual interests as a factor in social control. The second
means not only freer interaction between social groups (once isolated so
far as intention could keep up a separation) but change in social habit—its
continuous readjustment through meeting the new situations produced by
varied intercourse. And these two traits are precisely what characterize
the democratically constituted society.</p>
<p>Upon the educational side, we note first that the realization of a form of
social life in which interests are mutually interpenetrating, and where
progress, or readjustment, is an important consideration, makes a
democratic community more interested than other communities have cause to
be in deliberate and systematic education. The devotion of democracy to
education is a familiar fact. The superficial explanation is that a
government resting upon popular suffrage cannot be successful unless those
who elect and who obey their governors are educated. Since a democratic
society repudiates the principle of external authority, it must find a
substitute in voluntary disposition and interest; these can be created
only by education. But there is a deeper explanation. A democracy is more
than a form of government; it is primarily a mode of associated living, of
conjoint communicated experience. The extension in space of the number of
individuals who participate in an interest so that each has to refer his
own action to that of others, and to consider the action of others to give
point and direction to his own, is equivalent to the breaking down of
those barriers of class, race, and national territory which kept men from
perceiving the full import of their activity. These more numerous and more
varied points of contact denote a greater diversity of stimuli to which an
individual has to respond; they consequently put a premium on variation in
his action. They secure a liberation of powers which remain suppressed as
long as the incitations to action are partial, as they must be in a group
which in its exclusiveness shuts out many interests.</p>
<p>The widening of the area of shared concerns, and the liberation of a
greater diversity of personal capacities which characterize a democracy,
are not of course the product of deliberation and conscious effort. On the
contrary, they were caused by the development of modes of manufacture and
commerce, travel, migration, and intercommunication which flowed from the
command of science over natural energy. But after greater
individualization on one hand, and a broader community of interest on the
other have come into existence, it is a matter of deliberate effort to
sustain and extend them. Obviously a society to which stratification into
separate classes would be fatal, must see to it that intellectual
opportunities are accessible to all on equable and easy terms. A society
marked off into classes need he specially attentive only to the education
of its ruling elements. A society which is mobile, which is full of
channels for the distribution of a change occurring anywhere, must see to
it that its members are educated to personal initiative and adaptability.
Otherwise, they will be overwhelmed by the changes in which they are
caught and whose significance or connections they do not perceive. The
result will be a confusion in which a few will appropriate to themselves
the results of the blind and externally directed activities of others.</p>
<p>3. The Platonic Educational Philosophy. Subsequent chapters will be
devoted to making explicit the implications of the democratic ideas in
education. In the remaining portions of this chapter, we shall consider
the educational theories which have been evolved in three epochs when the
social import of education was especially conspicuous. The first one to be
considered is that of Plato. No one could better express than did he the
fact that a society is stably organized when each individual is doing that
for which he has aptitude by nature in such a way as to be useful to
others (or to contribute to the whole to which he belongs); and that it is
the business of education to discover these aptitudes and progressively to
train them for social use. Much which has been said so far is borrowed
from what Plato first consciously taught the world. But conditions which
he could not intellectually control led him to restrict these ideas in
their application. He never got any conception of the indefinite plurality
of activities which may characterize an individual and a social group, and
consequently limited his view to a limited number of classes of capacities
and of social arrangements. Plato's starting point is that the
organization of society depends ultimately upon knowledge of the end of
existence. If we do not know its end, we shall be at the mercy of accident
and caprice. Unless we know the end, the good, we shall have no criterion
for rationally deciding what the possibilities are which should be
promoted, nor how social arrangements are to be ordered. We shall have no
conception of the proper limits and distribution of activities—what
he called justice—as a trait of both individual and social
organization. But how is the knowledge of the final and permanent good to
be achieved? In dealing with this question we come upon the seemingly
insuperable obstacle that such knowledge is not possible save in a just
and harmonious social order. Everywhere else the mind is distracted and
misled by false valuations and false perspectives. A disorganized and
factional society sets up a number of different models and standards.
Under such conditions it is impossible for the individual to attain
consistency of mind. Only a complete whole is fully self-consistent. A
society which rests upon the supremacy of some factor over another
irrespective of its rational or proportionate claims, inevitably leads
thought astray. It puts a premium on certain things and slurs over others,
and creates a mind whose seeming unity is forced and distorted. Education
proceeds ultimately from the patterns furnished by institutions, customs,
and laws. Only in a just state will these be such as to give the right
education; and only those who have rightly trained minds will be able to
recognize the end, and ordering principle of things. We seem to be caught
in a hopeless circle. However, Plato suggested a way out. A few men,
philosophers or lovers of wisdom—or truth—may by study learn
at least in outline the proper patterns of true existence. If a powerful
ruler should form a state after these patterns, then its regulations could
be preserved. An education could be given which would sift individuals,
discovering what they were good for, and supplying a method of assigning
each to the work in life for which his nature fits him. Each doing his own
part, and never transgressing, the order and unity of the whole would be
maintained.</p>
<p>It would be impossible to find in any scheme of philosophic thought a more
adequate recognition on one hand of the educational significance of social
arrangements and, on the other, of the dependence of those arrangements
upon the means used to educate the young. It would be impossible to find a
deeper sense of the function of education in discovering and developing
personal capacities, and training them so that they would connect with the
activities of others. Yet the society in which the theory was propounded
was so undemocratic that Plato could not work out a solution for the
problem whose terms he clearly saw.</p>
<p>While he affirmed with emphasis that the place of the individual in
society should not be determined by birth or wealth or any conventional
status, but by his own nature as discovered in the process of education,
he had no perception of the uniqueness of individuals. For him they fall
by nature into classes, and into a very small number of classes at that.
Consequently the testing and sifting function of education only shows to
which one of three classes an individual belongs. There being no
recognition that each individual constitutes his own class, there could be
no recognition of the infinite diversity of active tendencies and
combinations of tendencies of which an individual is capable. There were
only three types of faculties or powers in the individual's constitution.
Hence education would soon reach a static limit in each class, for only
diversity makes change and progress.</p>
<p>In some individuals, appetites naturally dominate; they are assigned to
the laboring and trading class, which expresses and supplies human wants.
Others reveal, upon education, that over and above appetites, they have a
generous, outgoing, assertively courageous disposition. They become the
citizen-subjects of the state; its defenders in war; its internal
guardians in peace. But their limit is fixed by their lack of reason,
which is a capacity to grasp the universal. Those who possess this are
capable of the highest kind of education, and become in time the
legislators of the state—for laws are the universals which control
the particulars of experience. Thus it is not true that in intent, Plato
subordinated the individual to the social whole. But it is true that
lacking the perception of the uniqueness of every individual, his
incommensurability with others, and consequently not recognizing that a
society might change and yet be stable, his doctrine of limited powers and
classes came in net effect to the idea of the subordination of
individuality. We cannot better Plato's conviction that an individual is
happy and society well organized when each individual engages in those
activities for which he has a natural equipment, nor his conviction that
it is the primary office of education to discover this equipment to its
possessor and train him for its effective use. But progress in knowledge
has made us aware of the superficiality of Plato's lumping of individuals
and their original powers into a few sharply marked-off classes; it has
taught us that original capacities are indefinitely numerous and variable.
It is but the other side of this fact to say that in the degree in which
society has become democratic, social organization means utilization of
the specific and variable qualities of individuals, not stratification by
classes. Although his educational philosophy was revolutionary, it was
none the less in bondage to static ideals. He thought that change or
alteration was evidence of lawless flux; that true reality was
unchangeable. Hence while he would radically change the existing state of
society, his aim was to construct a state in which change would
subsequently have no place. The final end of life is fixed; given a state
framed with this end in view, not even minor details are to be altered.
Though they might not be inherently important, yet if permitted they would
inure the minds of men to the idea of change, and hence be dissolving and
anarchic. The breakdown of his philosophy is made apparent in the fact
that he could not trust to gradual improvements in education to bring
about a better society which should then improve education, and so on
indefinitely. Correct education could not come into existence until an
ideal state existed, and after that education would be devoted simply to
its conservation. For the existence of this state he was obliged to trust
to some happy accident by which philosophic wisdom should happen to
coincide with possession of ruling power in the state.</p>
<p>4. The "Individualistic" Ideal of the Eighteenth Century. In the
eighteenth-century philosophy we find ourselves in a very different circle
of ideas. "Nature" still means something antithetical to existing social
organization; Plato exercised a great influence upon Rousseau. But the
voice of nature now speaks for the diversity of individual talent and for
the need of free development of individuality in all its variety.
Education in accord with nature furnishes the goal and the method of
instruction and discipline. Moreover, the native or original endowment was
conceived, in extreme cases, as nonsocial or even as antisocial. Social
arrangements were thought of as mere external expedients by which these
nonsocial individuals might secure a greater amount of private happiness
for themselves. Nevertheless, these statements convey only an inadequate
idea of the true significance of the movement. In reality its chief
interest was in progress and in social progress. The seeming antisocial
philosophy was a somewhat transparent mask for an impetus toward a wider
and freer society—toward cosmopolitanism. The positive ideal was
humanity. In membership in humanity, as distinct from a state, man's
capacities would be liberated; while in existing political organizations
his powers were hampered and distorted to meet the requirements and
selfish interests of the rulers of the state. The doctrine of extreme
individualism was but the counterpart, the obverse, of ideals of the
indefinite perfectibility of man and of a social organization having a
scope as wide as humanity. The emancipated individual was to become the
organ and agent of a comprehensive and progressive society.</p>
<p>The heralds of this gospel were acutely conscious of the evils of the
social estate in which they found themselves. They attributed these evils
to the limitations imposed upon the free powers of man. Such limitation
was both distorting and corrupting. Their impassioned devotion to
emancipation of life from external restrictions which operated to the
exclusive advantage of the class to whom a past feudal system consigned
power, found intellectual formulation in a worship of nature. To give
"nature" full swing was to replace an artificial, corrupt, and inequitable
social order by a new and better kingdom of humanity. Unrestrained faith
in Nature as both a model and a working power was strengthened by the
advances of natural science. Inquiry freed from prejudice and artificial
restraints of church and state had revealed that the world is a scene of
law. The Newtonian solar system, which expressed the reign of natural law,
was a scene of wonderful harmony, where every force balanced with every
other. Natural law would accomplish the same result in human relations, if
men would only get rid of the artificial man-imposed coercive
restrictions.</p>
<p>Education in accord with nature was thought to be the first step in
insuring this more social society. It was plainly seen that economic and
political limitations were ultimately dependent upon limitations of
thought and feeling. The first step in freeing men from external chains
was to emancipate them from the internal chains of false beliefs and
ideals. What was called social life, existing institutions, were too false
and corrupt to be intrusted with this work. How could it be expected to
undertake it when the undertaking meant its own destruction? "Nature" must
then be the power to which the enterprise was to be left. Even the extreme
sensationalistic theory of knowledge which was current derived itself from
this conception. To insist that mind is originally passive and empty was
one way of glorifying the possibilities of education. If the mind was a
wax tablet to be written upon by objects, there were no limits to the
possibility of education by means of the natural environment. And since
the natural world of objects is a scene of harmonious "truth," this
education would infallibly produce minds filled with the truth.</p>
<p>5. Education as National and as Social. As soon as the first enthusiasm
for freedom waned, the weakness of the theory upon the constructive side
became obvious. Merely to leave everything to nature was, after all, but
to negate the very idea of education; it was to trust to the accidents of
circumstance. Not only was some method required but also some positive
organ, some administrative agency for carrying on the process of
instruction. The "complete and harmonious development of all powers,"
having as its social counterpart an enlightened and progressive humanity,
required definite organization for its realization. Private individuals
here and there could proclaim the gospel; they could not execute the work.
A Pestalozzi could try experiments and exhort philanthropically inclined
persons having wealth and power to follow his example. But even Pestalozzi
saw that any effective pursuit of the new educational ideal required the
support of the state. The realization of the new education destined to
produce a new society was, after all, dependent upon the activities of
existing states. The movement for the democratic idea inevitably became a
movement for publicly conducted and administered schools.</p>
<p>So far as Europe was concerned, the historic situation identified the
movement for a state-supported education with the nationalistic movement
in political life—a fact of incalculable significance for subsequent
movements. Under the influence of German thought in particular, education
became a civic function and the civic function was identified with the
realization of the ideal of the national state. The "state" was
substituted for humanity; cosmopolitanism gave way to nationalism. To form
the citizen, not the "man," became the aim of education. 1 The historic
situation to which reference is made is the after-effects of the
Napoleonic conquests, especially in Germany. The German states felt (and
subsequent events demonstrate the correctness of the belief) that
systematic attention to education was the best means of recovering and
maintaining their political integrity and power. Externally they were weak
and divided. Under the leadership of Prussian statesmen they made this
condition a stimulus to the development of an extensive and thoroughly
grounded system of public education.</p>
<p>This change in practice necessarily brought about a change in theory. The
individualistic theory receded into the background. The state furnished
not only the instrumentalities of public education but also its goal. When
the actual practice was such that the school system, from the elementary
grades through the university faculties, supplied the patriotic citizen
and soldier and the future state official and administrator and furnished
the means for military, industrial, and political defense and expansion,
it was impossible for theory not to emphasize the aim of social
efficiency. And with the immense importance attached to the nationalistic
state, surrounded by other competing and more or less hostile states, it
was equally impossible to interpret social efficiency in terms of a vague
cosmopolitan humanitarianism. Since the maintenance of a particular
national sovereignty required subordination of individuals to the superior
interests of the state both in military defense and in struggles for
international supremacy in commerce, social efficiency was understood to
imply a like subordination. The educational process was taken to be one of
disciplinary training rather than of personal development. Since, however,
the ideal of culture as complete development of personality persisted,
educational philosophy attempted a reconciliation of the two ideas. The
reconciliation took the form of the conception of the "organic" character
of the state. The individual in his isolation is nothing; only in and
through an absorption of the aims and meaning of organized institutions
does he attain true personality. What appears to be his subordination to
political authority and the demand for sacrifice of himself to the
commands of his superiors is in reality but making his own the objective
reason manifested in the state—the only way in which he can become
truly rational. The notion of development which we have seen to be
characteristic of institutional idealism (as in the Hegelian philosophy)
was just such a deliberate effort to combine the two ideas of complete
realization of personality and thoroughgoing "disciplinary" subordination
to existing institutions. The extent of the transformation of educational
philosophy which occurred in Germany in the generation occupied by the
struggle against Napoleon for national independence, may be gathered from
Kant, who well expresses the earlier individual-cosmopolitan ideal. In his
treatise on Pedagogics, consisting of lectures given in the later years of
the eighteenth century, he defines education as the process by which man
becomes man. Mankind begins its history submerged in nature—not as
Man who is a creature of reason, while nature furnishes only instinct and
appetite. Nature offers simply the germs which education is to develop and
perfect. The peculiarity of truly human life is that man has to create
himself by his own voluntary efforts; he has to make himself a truly
moral, rational, and free being. This creative effort is carried on by the
educational activities of slow generations. Its acceleration depends upon
men consciously striving to educate their successors not for the existing
state of affairs but so as to make possible a future better humanity. But
there is the great difficulty. Each generation is inclined to educate its
young so as to get along in the present world instead of with a view to
the proper end of education: the promotion of the best possible
realization of humanity as humanity. Parents educate their children so
that they may get on; princes educate their subjects as instruments of
their own purposes.</p>
<p>Who, then, shall conduct education so that humanity may improve? We must
depend upon the efforts of enlightened men in their private capacity. "All
culture begins with private men and spreads outward from them. Simply
through the efforts of persons of enlarged inclinations, who are capable
of grasping the ideal of a future better condition, is the gradual
approximation of human nature to its end possible. Rulers are simply
interested in such training as will make their subjects better tools for
their own intentions." Even the subsidy by rulers of privately conducted
schools must be carefully safeguarded. For the rulers' interest in the
welfare of their own nation instead of in what is best for humanity, will
make them, if they give money for the schools, wish to draw their plans.
We have in this view an express statement of the points characteristic of
the eighteenth century individualistic cosmopolitanism. The full
development of private personality is identified with the aims of humanity
as a whole and with the idea of progress. In addition we have an explicit
fear of the hampering influence of a state-conducted and state-regulated
education upon the attainment of these ideas. But in less than two decades
after this time, Kant's philosophic successors, Fichte and Hegel,
elaborated the idea that the chief function of the state is educational;
that in particular the regeneration of Germany is to be accomplished by an
education carried on in the interests of the state, and that the private
individual is of necessity an egoistic, irrational being, enslaved to his
appetites and to circumstances unless he submits voluntarily to the
educative discipline of state institutions and laws. In this spirit,
Germany was the first country to undertake a public, universal, and
compulsory system of education extending from the primary school through
the university, and to submit to jealous state regulation and supervision
all private educational enterprises. Two results should stand out from
this brief historical survey. The first is that such terms as the
individual and the social conceptions of education are quite meaningless
taken at large, or apart from their context. Plato had the ideal of an
education which should equate individual realization and social coherency
and stability. His situation forced his ideal into the notion of a society
organized in stratified classes, losing the individual in the class. The
eighteenth century educational philosophy was highly individualistic in
form, but this form was inspired by a noble and generous social ideal:
that of a society organized to include humanity, and providing for the
indefinite perfectibility of mankind. The idealistic philosophy of Germany
in the early nineteenth century endeavored again to equate the ideals of a
free and complete development of cultured personality with social
discipline and political subordination. It made the national state an
intermediary between the realization of private personality on one side
and of humanity on the other. Consequently, it is equally possible to
state its animating principle with equal truth either in the classic terms
of "harmonious development of all the powers of personality" or in the
more recent terminology of "social efficiency." All this reinforces the
statement which opens this chapter: The conception of education as a
social process and function has no definite meaning until we define the
kind of society we have in mind. These considerations pave the way for our
second conclusion. One of the fundamental problems of education in and for
a democratic society is set by the conflict of a nationalistic and a wider
social aim. The earlier cosmopolitan and "humanitarian" conception
suffered both from vagueness and from lack of definite organs of execution
and agencies of administration. In Europe, in the Continental states
particularly, the new idea of the importance of education for human
welfare and progress was captured by national interests and harnessed to
do a work whose social aim was definitely narrow and exclusive. The social
aim of education and its national aim were identified, and the result was
a marked obscuring of the meaning of a social aim.</p>
<p>This confusion corresponds to the existing situation of human intercourse.
On the one hand, science, commerce, and art transcend national boundaries.
They are largely international in quality and method. They involve
interdependencies and cooperation among the peoples inhabiting different
countries. At the same time, the idea of national sovereignty has never
been as accentuated in politics as it is at the present time. Each nation
lives in a state of suppressed hostility and incipient war with its
neighbors. Each is supposed to be the supreme judge of its own interests,
and it is assumed as matter of course that each has interests which are
exclusively its own. To question this is to question the very idea of
national sovereignty which is assumed to be basic to political practice
and political science. This contradiction (for it is nothing less) between
the wider sphere of associated and mutually helpful social life and the
narrower sphere of exclusive and hence potentially hostile pursuits and
purposes, exacts of educational theory a clearer conception of the meaning
of "social" as a function and test of education than has yet been
attained. Is it possible for an educational system to be conducted by a
national state and yet the full social ends of the educative process not
be restricted, constrained, and corrupted? Internally, the question has to
face the tendencies, due to present economic conditions, which split
society into classes some of which are made merely tools for the higher
culture of others. Externally, the question is concerned with the
reconciliation of national loyalty, of patriotism, with superior devotion
to the things which unite men in common ends, irrespective of national
political boundaries. Neither phase of the problem can be worked out by
merely negative means. It is not enough to see to it that education is not
actively used as an instrument to make easier the exploitation of one
class by another. School facilities must be secured of such amplitude and
efficiency as will in fact and not simply in name discount the effects of
economic inequalities, and secure to all the wards of the nation equality
of equipment for their future careers. Accomplishment of this end demands
not only adequate administrative provision of school facilities, and such
supplementation of family resources as will enable youth to take advantage
of them, but also such modification of traditional ideals of culture,
traditional subjects of study and traditional methods of teaching and
discipline as will retain all the youth under educational influences until
they are equipped to be masters of their own economic and social careers.
The ideal may seem remote of execution, but the democratic ideal of
education is a farcical yet tragic delusion except as the ideal more and
more dominates our public system of education. The same principle has
application on the side of the considerations which concern the relations
of one nation to another. It is not enough to teach the horrors of war and
to avoid everything which would stimulate international jealousy and
animosity. The emphasis must be put upon whatever binds people together in
cooperative human pursuits and results, apart from geographical
limitations. The secondary and provisional character of national
sovereignty in respect to the fuller, freer, and more fruitful association
and intercourse of all human beings with one another must be instilled as
a working disposition of mind. If these applications seem to be remote
from a consideration of the philosophy of education, the impression shows
that the meaning of the idea of education previously developed has not
been adequately grasped. This conclusion is bound up with the very idea of
education as a freeing of individual capacity in a progressive growth
directed to social aims. Otherwise a democratic criterion of education can
only be inconsistently applied.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM7" id="link2H_SUMM7"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. Since education is a social process, and there are many kinds </h2>
<p>of societies, a criterion for educational criticism and construction
implies a particular social ideal. The two points selected by which to
measure the worth of a form of social life are the extent in which the
interests of a group are shared by all its members, and the fullness and
freedom with which it interacts with other groups. An undesirable society,
in other words, is one which internally and externally sets up barriers to
free intercourse and communication of experience. A society which makes
provision for participation in its good of all its members on equal terms
and which secures flexible readjustment of its institutions through
interaction of the different forms of associated life is in so far
democratic. Such a society must have a type of education which gives
individuals a personal interest in social relationships and control, and
the habits of mind which secure social changes without introducing
disorder. Three typical historic philosophies of education were considered
from this point of view. The Platonic was found to have an ideal formally
quite similar to that stated, but which was compromised in its working out
by making a class rather than an individual the social unit. The so-called
individualism of the eighteenth-century enlightenment was found to involve
the notion of a society as broad as humanity, of whose progress the
individual was to be the organ. But it lacked any agency for securing the
development of its ideal as was evidenced in its falling back upon Nature.
The institutional idealistic philosophies of the nineteenth century
supplied this lack by making the national state the agency, but in so
doing narrowed the conception of the social aim to those who were members
of the same political unit, and reintroduced the idea of the subordination
of the individual to the institution. 1 There is a much neglected strain
in Rousseau tending intellectually in this direction. He opposed the
existing state of affairs on the ground that it formed neither the citizen
nor the man. Under existing conditions, he preferred to try for the latter
rather than for the former. But there are many sayings of his which point
to the formation of the citizen as ideally the higher, and which indicate
that his own endeavor, as embodied in the Emile, was simply the best
makeshift the corruption of the times permitted him to sketch.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />