<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0009" id="link2HCH0009"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Nine: Natural Development and Social Efficiency as Aims </h2>
<p>1. Nature as Supplying the Aim. We have just pointed out the futility of
trying to establish the aim of education—some one final aim which
subordinates all others to itself. We have indicated that since general
aims are but prospective points of view from which to survey the existing
conditions and estimate their possibilities, we might have any number of
them, all consistent with one another. As matter of fact, a large number
have been stated at different times, all having great local value. For the
statement of aim is a matter of emphasis at a given time. And we do not
emphasize things which do not require emphasis—that is, such things
as are taking care of themselves fairly well. We tend rather to frame our
statement on the basis of the defects and needs of the contemporary
situation; we take for granted, without explicit statement which would be
of no use, whatever is right or approximately so. We frame our explicit
aims in terms of some alteration to be brought about. It is, then, DO
paradox requiring explanation that a given epoch or generation tends to
emphasize in its conscious projections just the things which it has least
of in actual fact. A time of domination by authority will call out as
response the desirability of great individual freedom; one of disorganized
individual activities the need of social control as an educational aim.</p>
<p>The actual and implicit practice and the conscious or stated aim thus
balance each other. At different times such aims as complete living,
better methods of language study, substitution of things for words, social
efficiency, personal culture, social service, complete development of
personality, encyclopedic knowledge, discipline, a esthetic contemplation,
utility, etc., have served. The following discussion takes up three
statements of recent influence; certain others have been incidentally
discussed in the previous chapters, and others will be considered later in
a discussion of knowledge and of the values of studies. We begin with a
consideration that education is a process of development in accordance
with nature, taking Rousseau's statement, which opposed natural to social
(See ante, p. 91); and then pass over to the antithetical conception of
social efficiency, which often opposes social to natural.</p>
<p>(1) Educational reformers disgusted with the conventionality and
artificiality of the scholastic methods they find about them are prone to
resort to nature as a standard. Nature is supposed to furnish the law and
the end of development; ours it is to follow and conform to her ways. The
positive value of this conception lies in the forcible way in which it
calls attention to the wrongness of aims which do not have regard to the
natural endowment of those educated. Its weakness is the ease with which
natural in the sense of normal is confused with the physical. The
constructive use of intelligence in foresight, and contriving, is then
discounted; we are just to get out of the way and allow nature to do the
work. Since no one has stated in the doctrine both its truth and falsity
better than Rousseau, we shall turn to him.</p>
<p>"Education," he says, "we receive from three sources—Nature, men,
and things. The spontaneous development of our organs and capacities
constitutes the education of Nature. The use to which we are taught to put
this development constitutes that education given us by Men. The
acquirement of personal experience from surrounding objects constitutes
that of things. Only when these three kinds of education are consonant and
make for the same end, does a man tend towards his true goal. If we are
asked what is this end, the answer is that of Nature. For since the
concurrence of the three kinds of education is necessary to their
completeness, the kind which is entirely independent of our control must
necessarily regulate us in determining the other two." Then he defines
Nature to mean the capacities and dispositions which are inborn, "as they
exist prior to the modification due to constraining habits and the
influence of the opinion of others."</p>
<p>The wording of Rousseau will repay careful study. It contains as
fundamental truths as have been uttered about education in conjunction
with a curious twist. It would be impossible to say better what is said in
the first sentences. The three factors of educative development are (a)
the native structure of our bodily organs and their functional activities;
(b) the uses to which the activities of these organs are put under the
influence of other persons; (c) their direct interaction with the
environment. This statement certainly covers the ground. His other two
propositions are equally sound; namely, (a) that only when the three
factors of education are consonant and cooperative does adequate
development of the individual occur, and (b) that the native activities of
the organs, being original, are basic in conceiving consonance. But it
requires but little reading between the lines, supplemented by other
statements of Rousseau, to perceive that instead of regarding these three
things as factors which must work together to some extent in order that
any one of them may proceed educatively, he regards them as separate and
independent operations. Especially does he believe that there is an
independent and, as he says, "spontaneous" development of the native
organs and faculties. He thinks that this development can go on
irrespective of the use to which they are put. And it is to this separate
development that education coming from social contact is to be
subordinated. Now there is an immense difference between a use of native
activities in accord with those activities themselves—as distinct
from forcing them and perverting them—and supposing that they have a
normal development apart from any use, which development furnishes the
standard and norm of all learning by use. To recur to our previous
illustration, the process of acquiring language is a practically perfect
model of proper educative growth. The start is from native activities of
the vocal apparatus, organs of hearing, etc. But it is absurd to suppose
that these have an independent growth of their own, which left to itself
would evolve a perfect speech. Taken literally, Rousseau's principle would
mean that adults should accept and repeat the babblings and noises of
children not merely as the beginnings of the development of articulate
speech—which they are—but as furnishing language itself—the
standard for all teaching of language.</p>
<p>The point may be summarized by saying that Rousseau was right, introducing
a much-needed reform into education, in holding that the structure and
activities of the organs furnish the conditions of all teaching of the use
of the organs; but profoundly wrong in intimating that they supply not
only the conditions but also the ends of their development. As matter of
fact, the native activities develop, in contrast with random and
capricious exercise, through the uses to which they are put. And the
office of the social medium is, as we have seen, to direct growth through
putting powers to the best possible use. The instinctive activities may be
called, metaphorically, spontaneous, in the sense that the organs give a
strong bias for a certain sort of operation,—a bias so strong that
we cannot go contrary to it, though by trying to go contrary we may
pervert, stunt, and corrupt them. But the notion of a spontaneous normal
development of these activities is pure mythology. The natural, or native,
powers furnish the initiating and limiting forces in all education; they
do not furnish its ends or aims. There is no learning except from a
beginning in unlearned powers, but learning is not a matter of the
spontaneous overflow of the unlearned powers. Rousseau's contrary opinion
is doubtless due to the fact that he identified God with Nature; to him
the original powers are wholly good, coming directly from a wise and good
creator. To paraphrase the old saying about the country and the town, God
made the original human organs and faculties, man makes the uses to which
they are put. Consequently the development of the former furnishes the
standard to which the latter must be subordinated. When men attempt to
determine the uses to which the original activities shall be put, they
interfere with a divine plan. The interference by social arrangements with
Nature, God's work, is the primary source of corruption in individuals.</p>
<p>Rousseau's passionate assertion of the intrinsic goodness of all natural
tendencies was a reaction against the prevalent notion of the total
depravity of innate human nature, and has had a powerful influence in
modifying the attitude towards children's interests. But it is hardly
necessary to say that primitive impulses are of themselves neither good
nor evil, but become one or the other according to the objects for which
they are employed. That neglect, suppression, and premature forcing of
some instincts at the expense of others, are responsible for many
avoidable ills, there can be no doubt. But the moral is not to leave them
alone to follow their own "spontaneous development," but to provide an
environment which shall organize them.</p>
<p>Returning to the elements of truth contained in Rousseau's statements, we
find that natural development, as an aim, enables him to point the means
of correcting many evils in current practices, and to indicate a number of
desirable specific aims. (1) Natural development as an aim fixes attention
upon the bodily organs and the need of health and vigor. The aim of
natural development says to parents and teachers: Make health an aim;
normal development cannot be had without regard to the vigor of the body—an
obvious enough fact and yet one whose due recognition in practice would
almost automatically revolutionize many of our educational practices.
"Nature" is indeed a vague and metaphorical term, but one thing that
"Nature" may be said to utter is that there are conditions of educational
efficiency, and that till we have learned what these conditions are and
have learned to make our practices accord with them, the noblest and most
ideal of our aims are doomed to suffer—are verbal and sentimental
rather than efficacious.</p>
<p>(2) The aim of natural development translates into the aim of respect for
physical mobility. In Rousseau's words: "Children are always in motion; a
sedentary life is injurious." When he says that "Nature's intention is to
strengthen the body before exercising the mind" he hardly states the fact
fairly. But if he had said that nature's "intention" (to adopt his
poetical form of speech) is to develop the mind especially by exercise of
the muscles of the body he would have stated a positive fact. In other
words, the aim of following nature means, in the concrete, regard for the
actual part played by use of the bodily organs in explorations, in
handling of materials, in plays and games. (3) The general aim translates
into the aim of regard for individual differences among children. Nobody
can take the principle of consideration of native powers into account
without being struck by the fact that these powers differ in different
individuals. The difference applies not merely to their intensity, but
even more to their quality and arrangement. As Rouseau said: "Each
individual is born with a distinctive temperament. We indiscriminately
employ children of different bents on the same exercises; their education
destroys the special bent and leaves a dull uniformity. Therefore after we
have wasted our efforts in stunting the true gifts of nature we see the
short-lived and illusory brilliance we have substituted die away, while
the natural abilities we have crushed do not revive."</p>
<p>Lastly, the aim of following nature means to note the origin, the waxing,
and waning, of preferences and interests. Capacities bud and bloom
irregularly; there is no even four-abreast development. We must strike
while the iron is hot. Especially precious are the first dawnings of
power. More than we imagine, the ways in which the tendencies of early
childhood are treated fix fundamental dispositions and condition the turn
taken by powers that show themselves later. Educational concern with the
early years of life—as distinct from inculcation of useful arts—dates
almost entirely from the time of the emphasis by Pestalozzi and Froebel,
following Rousseau, of natural principles of growth. The irregularity of
growth and its significance is indicated in the following passage of a
student of the growth of the nervous system. "While growth continues,
things bodily and mental are lopsided, for growth is never general, but is
accentuated now at one spot, now at another. The methods which shall
recognize in the presence of these enormous differences of endowment the
dynamic values of natural inequalities of growth, and utilize them,
preferring irregularity to the rounding out gained by pruning will most
closely follow that which takes place in the body and thus prove most
effective." 1 Observation of natural tendencies is difficult under
conditions of restraint. They show themselves most readily in a child's
spontaneous sayings and doings,—that is, in those he engages in when
not put at set tasks and when not aware of being under observation. It
does not follow that these tendencies are all desirable because they are
natural; but it does follow that since they are there, they are operative
and must be taken account of. We must see to it that the desirable ones
have an environment which keeps them active, and that their activity shall
control the direction the others take and thereby induce the disuse of the
latter because they lead to nothing. Many tendencies that trouble parents
when they appear are likely to be transitory, and sometimes too much
direct attention to them only fixes a child's attention upon them. At all
events, adults too easily assume their own habits and wishes as standards,
and regard all deviations of children's impulses as evils to be
eliminated. That artificiality against which the conception of following
nature is so largely a protest, is the outcome of attempts to force
children directly into the mold of grown-up standards.</p>
<p>In conclusion, we note that the early history of the idea of following
nature combined two factors which had no inherent connection with one
another. Before the time of Rousseau educational reformers had been
inclined to urge the importance of education by ascribing practically
unlimited power to it. All the differences between peoples and between
classes and persons among the same people were said to be due to
differences of training, of exercise, and practice. Originally, mind,
reason, understanding is, for all practical purposes, the same in all.
This essential identity of mind means the essential equality of all and
the possibility of bringing them all to the same level. As a protest
against this view, the doctrine of accord with nature meant a much less
formal and abstract view of mind and its powers. It substituted specific
instincts and impulses and physiological capacities, differing from
individual to individual (just as they differ, as Rousseau pointed out,
even in dogs of the same litter), for abstract faculties of discernment,
memory, and generalization. Upon this side, the doctrine of educative
accord with nature has been reinforced by the development of modern
biology, physiology, and psychology. It means, in effect, that great as is
the significance of nurture, of modification, and transformation through
direct educational effort, nature, or unlearned capacities, affords the
foundation and ultimate resources for such nurture. On the other hand, the
doctrine of following nature was a political dogma. It meant a rebellion
against existing social institutions, customs, and ideals (See ante, p.
91). Rousseau's statement that everything is good as it comes from the
hands of the Creator has its signification only in its contrast with the
concluding part of the same sentence: "Everything degenerates in the hands
of man." And again he says: "Natural man has an absolute value; he is a
numerical unit, a complete integer and has no relation save to himself and
to his fellow man. Civilized man is only a relative unit, the numerator of
a fraction whose value depends upon its dominator, its relation to the
integral body of society. Good political institutions are those which make
a man unnatural." It is upon this conception of the artificial and harmful
character of organized social life as it now exists 2 that he rested the
notion that nature not merely furnishes prime forces which initiate growth
but also its plan and goal. That evil institutions and customs work almost
automatically to give a wrong education which the most careful schooling
cannot offset is true enough; but the conclusion is not to education apart
from the environment, but to provide an environment in which native powers
will be put to better uses.</p>
<p>2. Social Efficiency as Aim. A conception which made nature supply the end
of a true education and society the end of an evil one, could hardly fail
to call out a protest. The opposing emphasis took the form of a doctrine
that the business of education is to supply precisely what nature fails to
secure; namely, habituation of an individual to social control;
subordination of natural powers to social rules. It is not surprising to
find that the value in the idea of social efficiency resides largely in
its protest against the points at which the doctrine of natural
development went astray; while its misuse comes when it is employed to
slur over the truth in that conception. It is a fact that we must look to
the activities and achievements of associated life to find what the
development of power—that is to say, efficiency—means. The
error is in implying that we must adopt measures of subordination rather
than of utilization to secure efficiency. The doctrine is rendered adequate
when we recognize that social efficiency is attained not by negative
constraint but by positive use of native individual capacities in
occupations having a social meaning. (1) Translated into specific aims,
social efficiency indicates the importance of industrial competency.
Persons cannot live without means of subsistence; the ways in which these
means are employed and consumed have a profound influence upon all the
relationships of persons to one another. If an individual is not able to
earn his own living and that of the children dependent upon him, he is a
drag or parasite upon the activities of others. He misses for himself one
of the most educative experiences of life. If he is not trained in the
right use of the products of industry, there is grave danger that he may
deprave himself and injure others in his possession of wealth. No scheme
of education can afford to neglect such basic considerations. Yet in the
name of higher and more spiritual ideals, the arrangements for higher
education have often not only neglected them, but looked at them with
scorn as beneath the level of educative concern. With the change from an
oligarchical to a democratic society, it is natural that the significance
of an education which should have as a result ability to make one's way
economically in the world, and to manage economic resources usefully
instead of for mere display and luxury, should receive emphasis.</p>
<p>There is, however, grave danger that in insisting upon this end, existing
economic conditions and standards will be accepted as final. A democratic
criterion requires us to develop capacity to the point of competency to
choose and make its own career. This principle is violated when the
attempt is made to fit individuals in advance for definite industrial
callings, selected not on the basis of trained original capacities, but on
that of the wealth or social status of parents. As a matter of fact,
industry at the present time undergoes rapid and abrupt changes through
the evolution of new inventions. New industries spring up, and old ones
are revolutionized. Consequently an attempt to train for too specific a
mode of efficiency defeats its own purpose. When the occupation changes
its methods, such individuals are left behind with even less ability to
readjust themselves than if they had a less definite training. But, most
of all, the present industrial constitution of society is, like every
society which has ever existed, full of inequities. It is the aim of
progressive education to take part in correcting unfair privilege and
unfair deprivation, not to perpetuate them. Wherever social control means
subordination of individual activities to class authority, there is danger
that industrial education will be dominated by acceptance of the status
quo. Differences of economic opportunity then dictate what the future
callings of individuals are to be. We have an unconscious revival of the
defects of the Platonic scheme (ante, p. 89) without its enlightened
method of selection.</p>
<p>(2) Civic efficiency, or good citizenship. It is, of course, arbitrary to
separate industrial competency from capacity in good citizenship. But the
latter term may be used to indicate a number of qualifications which are
vaguer than vocational ability. These traits run from whatever make an
individual a more agreeable companion to citizenship in the political
sense: it denotes ability to judge men and measures wisely and to take a
determining part in making as well as obeying laws. The aim of civic
efficiency has at least the merit of protecting us from the notion of a
training of mental power at large. It calls attention to the fact that
power must be relative to doing something, and to the fact that the things
which most need to be done are things which involve one's relationships
with others.</p>
<p>Here again we have to be on guard against understanding the aim too
narrowly. An over-definite interpretation would at certain periods have
excluded scientific discoveries, in spite of the fact that in the last
analysis security of social progress depends upon them. For scientific men
would have been thought to be mere theoretical dreamers, totally lacking
in social efficiency. It must be borne in mind that ultimately social
efficiency means neither more nor less than capacity to share in a give
and take of experience. It covers all that makes one's own experience more
worth while to others, and all that enables one to participate more richly
in the worthwhile experiences of others. Ability to produce and to enjoy
art, capacity for recreation, the significant utilization of leisure, are
more important elements in it than elements conventionally associated
oftentimes with citizenship. In the broadest sense, social efficiency is
nothing less than that socialization of mind which is actively concerned
in making experiences more communicable; in breaking down the barriers of
social stratification which make individuals impervious to the interests
of others. When social efficiency is confined to the service rendered by
overt acts, its chief constituent (because its only guarantee) is omitted,—intelligent
sympathy or good will. For sympathy as a desirable quality is something
more than mere feeling; it is a cultivated imagination for what men have
in common and a rebellion at whatever unnecessarily divides them. What is
sometimes called a benevolent interest in others may be but an unwitting
mask for an attempt to dictate to them what their good shall be, instead
of an endeavor to free them so that they may seek and find the good of
their own choice. Social efficiency, even social service, are hard and
metallic things when severed from an active acknowledgment of the
diversity of goods which life may afford to different persons, and from
faith in the social utility of encouraging every individual to make his
own choice intelligent.</p>
<p>3. Culture as Aim. Whether or not social efficiency is an aim which is
consistent with culture turns upon these considerations. Culture means at
least something cultivated, something ripened; it is opposed to the raw
and crude. When the "natural" is identified with this rawness, culture is
opposed to what is called natural development. Culture is also something
personal; it is cultivation with respect to appreciation of ideas and art
and broad human interests. When efficiency is identified with a narrow
range of acts, instead of with the spirit and meaning of activity, culture
is opposed to efficiency. Whether called culture or complete development
of personality, the outcome is identical with the true meaning of social
efficiency whenever attention is given to what is unique in an individual—and
he would not be an individual if there were not something incommensurable
about him. Its opposite is the mediocre, the average. Whenever distinctive
quality is developed, distinction of personality results, and with it
greater promise for a social service which goes beyond the supply in
quantity of material commodities. For how can there be a society really
worth serving unless it is constituted of individuals of significant
personal qualities?</p>
<p>The fact is that the opposition of high worth of personality to social
efficiency is a product of a feudally organized society with its rigid
division of inferior and superior. The latter are supposed to have time
and opportunity to develop themselves as human beings; the former are
confined to providing external products. When social efficiency as
measured by product or output is urged as an ideal in a would-be
democratic society, it means that the depreciatory estimate of the masses
characteristic of an aristocratic community is accepted and carried over.
But if democracy has a moral and ideal meaning, it is that a social return
be demanded from all and that opportunity for development of distinctive
capacities be afforded all. The separation of the two aims in education is
fatal to democracy; the adoption of the narrower meaning of efficiency
deprives it of its essential justification.</p>
<p>The aim of efficiency (like any educational aim) must be included within
the process of experience. When it is measured by tangible external
products, and not by the achieving of a distinctively valuable experience,
it becomes materialistic. Results in the way of commodities which may be
the outgrowth of an efficient personality are, in the strictest sense,
by-products of education: by-products which are inevitable and important,
but nevertheless by-products. To set up an external aim strengthens by
reaction the false conception of culture which identifies it with
something purely "inner." And the idea of perfecting an "inner"
personality is a sure sign of social divisions. What is called inner is
simply that which does not connect with others—which is not capable
of free and full communication. What is termed spiritual culture has
usually been futile, with something rotten about it, just because it has
been conceived as a thing which a man might have internally—and
therefore exclusively. What one is as a person is what one is as
associated with others, in a free give and take of intercourse. This
transcends both the efficiency which consists in supplying products to
others and the culture which is an exclusive refinement and polish.</p>
<p>Any individual has missed his calling, farmer, physician, teacher,
student, who does not find that the accomplishments of results of value to
others is an accompaniment of a process of experience inherently worth
while. Why then should it be thought that one must take his choice between
sacrificing himself to doing useful things for others, or sacrificing them
to pursuit of his own exclusive ends, whether the saving of his own soul
or the building of an inner spiritual life and personality? What happens
is that since neither of these things is persistently possible, we get a
compromise and an alternation. One tries each course by turns. There is no
greater tragedy than that so much of the professedly spiritual and
religious thought of the world has emphasized the two ideals of
self-sacrifice and spiritual self-perfecting instead of throwing its
weight against this dualism of life. The dualism is too deeply established
to be easily overthrown; for that reason, it is the particular task of
education at the present time to struggle in behalf of an aim in which
social efficiency and personal culture are synonyms instead of
antagonists.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM9" id="link2H_SUMM9"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. General or comprehensive aims are points of view for surveying </h2>
<p>the specific problems of education. Consequently it is a test of the value
of the manner in which any large end is stated to see if it will translate
readily and consistently into the procedures which are suggested by
another. We have applied this test to three general aims: Development
according to nature, social efficiency, and culture or personal mental
enrichment. In each case we have seen that the aims when partially stated
come into conflict with each other. The partial statement of natural
development takes the primitive powers in an alleged spontaneous
development as the end-all. From this point of view training which renders
them useful to others is an abnormal constraint; one which profoundly
modifies them through deliberate nurture is corrupting. But when we
recognize that natural activities mean native activities which develop
only through the uses in which they are nurtured, the conflict disappears.
Similarly a social efficiency which is defined in terms of rendering
external service to others is of necessity opposed to the aim of enriching
the meaning of experience, while a culture which is taken to consist in an
internal refinement of a mind is opposed to a socialized disposition. But
social efficiency as an educational purpose should mean cultivation of
power to join freely and fully in shared or common activities. This is
impossible without culture, while it brings a reward in culture, because
one cannot share in intercourse with others without learning—without
getting a broader point of view and perceiving things of which one would
otherwise be ignorant. And there is perhaps no better definition of
culture than that it is the capacity for constantly expanding the range
and accuracy of one's perception of meanings.</p>
<h3> 1 Donaldson, Growth of Brain, p. 356. </h3>
<p>2 We must not forget that Rousseau had the idea of a radically different
sort of society, a fraternal society whose end should be identical with
the good of all its members, which he thought to be as much better than
existing states as these are worse than the state of nature.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />