<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0011" id="link2HCH0011"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Eleven: Experience and Thinking </h2>
<p>1. The Nature of Experience. The nature of experience can be understood
only by noting that it includes an active and a passive element peculiarly
combined. On the active hand, experience is trying—a meaning which
is made explicit in the connected term experiment. On the passive, it is
undergoing. When we experience something we act upon it, we do something
with it; then we suffer or undergo the consequences. We do something to
the thing and then it does something to us in return: such is the peculiar
combination. The connection of these two phases of experience measures the
fruitfulness or value of the experience. Mere activity does not constitute
experience. It is dispersive, centrifugal, dissipating. Experience as
trying involves change, but change is meaningless transition unless it is
consciously connected with the return wave of consequences which flow from
it. When an activity is continued into the undergoing of consequences,
when the change made by action is reflected back into a change made in us,
the mere flux is loaded with significance. We learn something. It is not
experience when a child merely sticks his finger into a flame; it is
experience when the movement is connected with the pain which he undergoes
in consequence. Henceforth the sticking of the finger into flame means a
burn. Being burned is a mere physical change, like the burning of a stick
of wood, if it is not perceived as a consequence of some other action.
Blind and capricious impulses hurry us on heedlessly from one thing to
another. So far as this happens, everything is writ in water. There is
none of that cumulative growth which makes an experience in any vital
sense of that term. On the other hand, many things happen to us in the way
of pleasure and pain which we do not connect with any prior activity of
our own. They are mere accidents so far as we are concerned. There is no
before or after to such experience; no retrospect nor outlook, and
consequently no meaning. We get nothing which may be carried over to
foresee what is likely to happen next, and no gain in ability to adjust
ourselves to what is coming—no added control. Only by courtesy can
such an experience be called experience. To "learn from experience" is to
make a backward and forward connection between what we do to things and
what we enjoy or suffer from things in consequence. Under such conditions,
doing becomes a trying; an experiment with the world to find out what it
is like; the undergoing becomes instruction—discovery of the
connection of things.</p>
<p>Two conclusions important for education follow. (1) Experience is
primarily an active-passive affair; it is not primarily cognitive. But (2)
the measure of the value of an experience lies in the perception of
relationships or continuities to which it leads up. It includes cognition
in the degree in which it is cumulative or amounts to something, or has
meaning. In schools, those under instruction are too customarily looked
upon as acquiring knowledge as theoretical spectators, minds which
appropriate knowledge by direct energy of intellect. The very word pupil
has almost come to mean one who is engaged not in having fruitful
experiences but in absorbing knowledge directly. Something which is called
mind or consciousness is severed from the physical organs of activity. The
former is then thought to be purely intellectual and cognitive; the latter
to be an irrelevant and intruding physical factor. The intimate union of
activity and undergoing its consequences which leads to recognition of
meaning is broken; instead we have two fragments: mere bodily action on
one side, and meaning directly grasped by "spiritual" activity on the
other.</p>
<p>It would be impossible to state adequately the evil results which have
flowed from this dualism of mind and body, much less to exaggerate them.
Some of the more striking effects, may, however, be enumerated. (a) In
part bodily activity becomes an intruder. Having nothing, so it is
thought, to do with mental activity, it becomes a distraction, an evil to
be contended with. For the pupil has a body, and brings it to school along
with his mind. And the body is, of necessity, a wellspring of energy; it
has to do something. But its activities, not being utilized in occupation
with things which yield significant results, have to be frowned upon. They
lead the pupil away from the lesson with which his "mind" ought to be
occupied; they are sources of mischief. The chief source of the "problem
of discipline" in schools is that the teacher has often to spend the
larger part of the time in suppressing the bodily activities which take
the mind away from its material. A premium is put on physical quietude; on
silence, on rigid uniformity of posture and movement; upon a machine-like
simulation of the attitudes of intelligent interest. The teachers'
business is to hold the pupils up to these requirements and to punish the
inevitable deviations which occur.</p>
<p>The nervous strain and fatigue which result with both teacher and pupil
are a necessary consequence of the abnormality of the situation in which
bodily activity is divorced from the perception of meaning. Callous
indifference and explosions from strain alternate. The neglected body,
having no organized fruitful channels of activity, breaks forth, without
knowing why or how, into meaningless boisterousness, or settles into
equally meaningless fooling—both very different from the normal play
of children. Physically active children become restless and unruly; the
more quiescent, so-called conscientious ones spend what energy they have
in the negative task of keeping their instincts and active tendencies
suppressed, instead of in a positive one of constructive planning and
execution; they are thus educated not into responsibility for the
significant and graceful use of bodily powers, but into an enforced duty
not to give them free play. It may be seriously asserted that a chief
cause for the remarkable achievements of Greek education was that it was
never misled by false notions into an attempted separation of mind and
body.</p>
<p>(b) Even, however, with respect to the lessons which have to be learned by
the application of "mind," some bodily activities have to be used. The
senses—especially the eye and ear—have to be employed to take
in what the book, the map, the blackboard, and the teacher say. The lips
and vocal organs, and the hands, have to be used to reproduce in speech
and writing what has been stowed away. The senses are then regarded as a
kind of mysterious conduit through which information is conducted from the
external world into the mind; they are spoken of as gateways and avenues
of knowledge. To keep the eyes on the book and the ears open to the
teacher's words is a mysterious source of intellectual grace. Moreover,
reading, writing, and figuring—important school arts—demand
muscular or motor training. The muscles of eye, hand, and vocal organs
accordingly have to be trained to act as pipes for carrying knowledge back
out of the mind into external action. For it happens that using the
muscles repeatedly in the same way fixes in them an automatic tendency to
repeat.</p>
<p>The obvious result is a mechanical use of the bodily activities which (in
spite of the generally obtrusive and interfering character of the body in
mental action) have to be employed more or less. For the senses and
muscles are used not as organic participants in having an instructive
experience, but as external inlets and outlets of mind. Before the child
goes to school, he learns with his hand, eye, and ear, because they are
organs of the process of doing something from which meaning results. The
boy flying a kite has to keep his eye on the kite, and has to note the
various pressures of the string on his hand. His senses are avenues of
knowledge not because external facts are somehow "conveyed" to the brain,
but because they are used in doing something with a purpose. The qualities
of seen and touched things have a bearing on what is done, and are alertly
perceived; they have a meaning. But when pupils are expected to use their
eyes to note the form of words, irrespective of their meaning, in order to
reproduce them in spelling or reading, the resulting training is simply of
isolated sense organs and muscles. It is such isolation of an act from a
purpose which makes it mechanical. It is customary for teachers to urge
children to read with expression, so as to bring out the meaning. But if
they originally learned the sensory-motor technique of reading—the
ability to identify forms and to reproduce the sounds they stand for—by
methods which did not call for attention to meaning, a mechanical habit
was established which makes it difficult to read subsequently with
intelligence. The vocal organs have been trained to go their own way
automatically in isolation; and meaning cannot be tied on at will.
Drawing, singing, and writing may be taught in the same mechanical way;
for, we repeat, any way is mechanical which narrows down the bodily
activity so that a separation of body from mind—that is, from
recognition of meaning—is set up. Mathematics, even in its higher
branches, when undue emphasis is put upon the technique of calculation,
and science, when laboratory exercises are given for their own sake,
suffer from the same evil.</p>
<p>(c) On the intellectual side, the separation of "mind" from direct
occupation with things throws emphasis on things at the expense of
relations or connections. It is altogether too common to separate
perceptions and even ideas from judgments. The latter are thought to come
after the former in order to compare them. It is alleged that the mind
perceives things apart from relations; that it forms ideas of them in
isolation from their connections—with what goes before and comes
after. Then judgment or thought is called upon to combine the separated
items of "knowledge" so that their resemblance or causal connection shall
be brought out. As matter of fact, every perception and every idea is a
sense of the bearings, use, and cause, of a thing. We do not really know a
chair or have an idea of it by inventorying and enumerating its various
isolated qualities, but only by bringing these qualities into connection
with something else—the purpose which makes it a chair and not a
table; or its difference from the kind of chair we are accustomed to, or
the "period" which it represents, and so on. A wagon is not perceived when
all its parts are summed up; it is the characteristic connection of the
parts which makes it a wagon. And these connections are not those of mere
physical juxtaposition; they involve connection with the animals that draw
it, the things that are carried on it, and so on. Judgment is employed in
the perception; otherwise the perception is mere sensory excitation or
else a recognition of the result of a prior judgment, as in the case of
familiar objects.</p>
<p>Words, the counters for ideals, are, however, easily taken for ideas. And
in just the degree in which mental activity is separated from active
concern with the world, from doing something and connecting the doing with
what is undergone, words, symbols, come to take the place of ideas. The
substitution is the more subtle because some meaning is recognized. But we
are very easily trained to be content with a minimum of meaning, and to
fail to note how restricted is our perception of the relations which
confer significance. We get so thoroughly used to a kind of pseudo-idea, a
half perception, that we are not aware how half-dead our mental action is,
and how much keener and more extensive our observations and ideas would be
if we formed them under conditions of a vital experience which required us
to use judgment: to hunt for the connections of the thing dealt with.
There is no difference of opinion as to the theory of the matter. All
authorities agree that that discernment of relationships is the genuinely
intellectual matter; hence, the educative matter. The failure arises in
supposing that relationships can become perceptible without experience—without
that conjoint trying and undergoing of which we have spoken. It is assumed
that "mind" can grasp them if it will only give attention, and that this
attention may be given at will irrespective of the situation. Hence the
deluge of half-observations, of verbal ideas, and unassimilated
"knowledge" which afflicts the world. An ounce of experience is better
than a ton of theory simply because it is only in experience that any
theory has vital and verifiable significance. An experience, a very humble
experience, is capable of generating and carrying any amount of theory (or
intellectual content), but a theory apart from an experience cannot be
definitely grasped even as theory. It tends to become a mere verbal
formula, a set of catchwords used to render thinking, or genuine
theorizing, unnecessary and impossible. Because of our education we use
words, thinking they are ideas, to dispose of questions, the disposal
being in reality simply such an obscuring of perception as prevents us
from seeing any longer the difficulty.</p>
<p>2. Reflection in Experience. Thought or reflection, as we have already
seen virtually if not explicitly, is the discernment of the relation
between what we try to do and what happens in consequence. No experience
having a meaning is possible without some element of thought. But we may
contrast two types of experience according to the proportion of reflection
found in them. All our experiences have a phase of "cut and try" in them—what
psychologists call the method of trial and error. We simply do something,
and when it fails, we do something else, and keep on trying till we hit
upon something which works, and then we adopt that method as a rule of
thumb measure in subsequent procedure. Some experiences have very little
else in them than this hit and miss or succeed process. We see that a
certain way of acting and a certain consequence are connected, but we do
not see how they are. We do not see the details of the connection; the
links are missing. Our discernment is very gross. In other cases we push
our observation farther. We analyze to see just what lies between so as to
bind together cause and effect, activity and consequence. This extension
of our insight makes foresight more accurate and comprehensive. The action
which rests simply upon the trial and error method is at the mercy of
circumstances; they may change so that the act performed does not operate
in the way it was expected to. But if we know in detail upon what the
result depends, we can look to see whether the required conditions are
there. The method extends our practical control. For if some of the
conditions are missing, we may, if we know what the needed antecedents for
an effect are, set to work to supply them; or, if they are such as to
produce undesirable effects as well, we may eliminate some of the
superfluous causes and economize effort.</p>
<p>In discovery of the detailed connections of our activities and what
happens in consequence, the thought implied in cut and try experience is
made explicit. Its quantity increases so that its proportionate value is
very different. Hence the quality of the experience changes; the change is
so significant that we may call this type of experience reflective—that
is, reflective par excellence. The deliberate cultivation of this phase of
thought constitutes thinking as a distinctive experience. Thinking, in
other words, is the intentional endeavor to discover specific connections
between something which we do and the consequences which result, so that
the two become continuous. Their isolation, and consequently their purely
arbitrary going together, is canceled; a unified developing situation
takes its place. The occurrence is now understood; it is explained; it is
reasonable, as we say, that the thing should happen as it does.</p>
<p>Thinking is thus equivalent to an explicit rendering of the intelligent
element in our experience. It makes it possible to act with an end in
view. It is the condition of our having aims. As soon as an infant begins
to expect he begins to use something which is now going on as a sign of
something to follow; he is, in however simple a fashion, judging. For he
takes one thing as evidence of something else, and so recognizes a
relationship. Any future development, however elaborate it may be, is only
an extending and a refining of this simple act of inference. All that the
wisest man can do is to observe what is going on more widely and more
minutely and then select more carefully from what is noted just those
factors which point to something to happen. The opposites, once more, to
thoughtful action are routine and capricious behavior. The former accepts
what has been customary as a full measure of possibility and omits to take
into account the connections of the particular things done. The latter
makes the momentary act a measure of value, and ignores the connections of
our personal action with the energies of the environment. It says,
virtually, "things are to be just as I happen to like them at this
instant," as routine says in effect "let things continue just as I have
found them in the past." Both refuse to acknowledge responsibility for the
future consequences which flow from present action. Reflection is the
acceptance of such responsibility.</p>
<p>The starting point of any process of thinking is something going on,
something which just as it stands is incomplete or unfulfilled. Its point,
its meaning lies literally in what it is going to be, in how it is going
to turn out. As this is written, the world is filled with the clang of
contending armies. For an active participant in the war, it is clear that
the momentous thing is the issue, the future consequences, of this and
that happening. He is identified, for the time at least, with the issue;
his fate hangs upon the course things are taking. But even for an onlooker
in a neutral country, the significance of every move made, of every
advance here and retreat there, lies in what it portends. To think upon
the news as it comes to us is to attempt to see what is indicated as
probable or possible regarding an outcome. To fill our heads, like a
scrapbook, with this and that item as a finished and done-for thing, is
not to think. It is to turn ourselves into a piece of registering
apparatus. To consider the bearing of the occurrence upon what may be, but
is not yet, is to think. Nor will the reflective experience be different
in kind if we substitute distance in time for separation in space. Imagine
the war done with, and a future historian giving an account of it. The
episode is, by assumption, past. But he cannot give a thoughtful account
of the war save as he preserves the time sequence; the meaning of each
occurrence, as he deals with it, lies in what was future for it, though
not for the historian. To take it by itself as a complete existence is to
take it unreflectively. Reflection also implies concern with the issue—a
certain sympathetic identification of our own destiny, if only dramatic,
with the outcome of the course of events. For the general in the war, or a
common soldier, or a citizen of one of the contending nations, the
stimulus to thinking is direct and urgent. For neutrals, it is indirect
and dependent upon imagination. But the flagrant partisanship of human
nature is evidence of the intensity of the tendency to identify ourselves
with one possible course of events, and to reject the other as foreign. If
we cannot take sides in overt action, and throw in our little weight to
help determine the final balance, we take sides emotionally and
imaginatively. We desire this or that outcome. One wholly indifferent to
the outcome does not follow or think about what is happening at all. From
this dependence of the act of thinking upon a sense of sharing in the
consequences of what goes on, flows one of the chief paradoxes of thought.
Born in partiality, in order to accomplish its tasks it must achieve a
certain detached impartiality. The general who allows his hopes and
desires to affect his observations and interpretations of the existing
situation will surely make a mistake in calculation. While hopes and fears
may be the chief motive for a thoughtful following of the war on the part
of an onlooker in a neutral country, he too will think ineffectively in
the degree in which his preferences modify the stuff of his observations
and reasonings. There is, however, no incompatibility between the fact
that the occasion of reflection lies in a personal sharing in what is
going on and the fact that the value of the reflection lies upon keeping
one's self out of the data. The almost insurmountable difficulty of
achieving this detachment is evidence that thinking originates in
situations where the course of thinking is an actual part of the course of
events and is designed to influence the result. Only gradually and with a
widening of the area of vision through a growth of social sympathies does
thinking develop to include what lies beyond our direct interests: a fact
of great significance for education.</p>
<p>To say that thinking occurs with reference to situations which are still
going on, and incomplete, is to say that thinking occurs when things are
uncertain or doubtful or problematic. Only what is finished, completed, is
wholly assured. Where there is reflection there is suspense. The object of
thinking is to help reach a conclusion, to project a possible termination
on the basis of what is already given. Certain other facts about thinking
accompany this feature. Since the situation in which thinking occurs is a
doubtful one, thinking is a process of inquiry, of looking into things, of
investigating. Acquiring is always secondary, and instrumental to the act
of inquiring. It is seeking, a quest, for something that is not at hand.
We sometimes talk as if "original research" were a peculiar prerogative of
scientists or at least of advanced students. But all thinking is research,
and all research is native, original, with him who carries it on, even if
everybody else in the world already is sure of what he is still looking
for.</p>
<p>It also follows that all thinking involves a risk. Certainty cannot be
guaranteed in advance. The invasion of the unknown is of the nature of an
adventure; we cannot be sure in advance. The conclusions of thinking, till
confirmed by the event, are, accordingly, more or less tentative or
hypothetical. Their dogmatic assertion as final is unwarranted, short of
the issue, in fact. The Greeks acutely raised the question: How can we
learn? For either we know already what we are after, or else we do not
know. In neither case is learning possible; on the first alternative
because we know already; on the second, because we do not know what to
look for, nor if, by chance, we find it can we tell that it is what we
were after. The dilemma makes no provision for coming to know, for
learning; it assumes either complete knowledge or complete ignorance.
Nevertheless the twilight zone of inquiry, of thinking, exists. The
possibility of hypothetical conclusions, of tentative results, is the fact
which the Greek dilemma overlooked. The perplexities of the situation
suggest certain ways out. We try these ways, and either push our way out,
in which case we know we have found what we were looking for, or the
situation gets darker and more confused—in which case, we know we
are still ignorant. Tentative means trying out, feeling one's way along
provisionally. Taken by itself, the Greek argument is a nice piece of
formal logic. But it is also true that as long as men kept a sharp
disjunction between knowledge and ignorance, science made only slow and
accidental advance. Systematic advance in invention and discovery began
when men recognized that they could utilize doubt for purposes of inquiry
by forming conjectures to guide action in tentative explorations, whose
development would confirm, refute, or modify the guiding conjecture. While
the Greeks made knowledge more than learning, modern science makes
conserved knowledge only a means to learning, to discovery. To recur to
our illustration. A commanding general cannot base his actions upon either
absolute certainty or absolute ignorance. He has a certain amount of
information at hand which is, we will assume, reasonably trustworthy. He
then infers certain prospective movements, thus assigning meaning to the
bare facts of the given situation. His inference is more or less dubious
and hypothetical. But he acts upon it. He develops a plan of procedure, a
method of dealing with the situation. The consequences which directly
follow from his acting this way rather than that test and reveal the worth
of his reflections. What he already knows functions and has value in what
he learns. But will this account apply in the case of the one in a neutral
country who is thoughtfully following as best he can the progress of
events? In form, yes, though not of course in content. It is self-evident
that his guesses about the future indicated by present facts, guesses by
which he attempts to supply meaning to a multitude of disconnected data,
cannot be the basis of a method which shall take effect in the campaign.
That is not his problem. But in the degree in which he is actively
thinking, and not merely passively following the course of events, his
tentative inferences will take effect in a method of procedure appropriate
to his situation. He will anticipate certain future moves, and will be on
the alert to see whether they happen or not. In the degree in which he is
intellectually concerned, or thoughtful, he will be actively on the
lookout; he will take steps which although they do not affect the
campaign, modify in some degree his subsequent actions. Otherwise his
later "I told you so" has no intellectual quality at all; it does not mark
any testing or verification of prior thinking, but only a coincidence that
yields emotional satisfaction—and includes a large factor of
self-deception. The case is comparable to that of an astronomer who from
given data has been led to foresee (infer) a future eclipse. No matter how
great the mathematical probability, the inference is hypothetical—a
matter of probability. 1 The hypothesis as to the date and position of the
anticipated eclipse becomes the material of forming a method of future
conduct. Apparatus is arranged; possibly an expedition is made to some far
part of the globe. In any case, some active steps are taken which actually
change some physical conditions. And apart from such steps and the
consequent modification of the situation, there is no completion of the
act of thinking. It remains suspended. Knowledge, already attained
knowledge, controls thinking and makes it fruitful.</p>
<p>So much for the general features of a reflective experience. They are (i)
perplexity, confusion, doubt, due to the fact that one is implicated in an
incomplete situation whose full character is not yet determined; (ii) a
conjectural anticipation—a tentative interpretation of the given
elements, attributing to them a tendency to effect certain consequences;
(iii) a careful survey (examination, inspection, exploration, analysis) of
all attainable consideration which will define and clarify the problem in
hand; (iv) a consequent elaboration of the tentative hypothesis to make it
more precise and more consistent, because squaring with a wider range of
facts; (v) taking one stand upon the projected hypothesis as a plan of
action which is applied to the existing state of affairs: doing something
overtly to bring about the anticipated result, and thereby testing the
hypothesis. It is the extent and accuracy of steps three and four which
mark off a distinctive reflective experience from one on the trial and
error plane. They make thinking itself into an experience. Nevertheless,
we never get wholly beyond the trial and error situation. Our most
elaborate and rationally consistent thought has to be tried in the world
and thereby tried out. And since it can never take into account all the
connections, it can never cover with perfect accuracy all the
consequences. Yet a thoughtful survey of conditions is so careful, and the
guessing at results so controlled, that we have a right to mark off the
reflective experience from the grosser trial and error forms of action.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM11" id="link2H_SUMM11"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. In determining the place of thinking in experience we first </h2>
<p>noted that experience involves a connection of doing or trying with
something which is undergone in consequence. A separation of the active
doing phase from the passive undergoing phase destroys the vital meaning
of an experience. Thinking is the accurate and deliberate instituting of
connections between what is done and its consequences. It notes not only
that they are connected, but the details of the connection. It makes
connecting links explicit in the form of relationships. The stimulus to
thinking is found when we wish to determine the significance of some act,
performed or to be performed. Then we anticipate consequences. This
implies that the situation as it stands is, either in fact or to us,
incomplete and hence indeterminate. The projection of consequences means a
proposed or tentative solution. To perfect this hypothesis, existing
conditions have to be carefully scrutinized and the implications of the
hypothesis developed—an operation called reasoning. Then the
suggested solution—the idea or theory—has to be tested by
acting upon it. If it brings about certain consequences, certain
determinate changes, in the world, it is accepted as valid. Otherwise it
is modified, and another trial made. Thinking includes all of these steps,—the
sense of a problem, the observation of conditions, the formation and
rational elaboration of a suggested conclusion, and the active
experimental testing. While all thinking results in knowledge, ultimately
the value of knowledge is subordinate to its use in thinking. For we live
not in a settled and finished world, but in one which is going on, and
where our main task is prospective, and where retrospect—and all
knowledge as distinct from thought is retrospect—is of value in the
solidity, security, and fertility it affords our dealings with the future.</p>
<p>1 It is most important for the practice of science that men in many cases
can calculate the degree of probability and the amount of probable error
involved, but that does alter the features of the situation as described.
It refines them.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />