<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0014" id="link2HCH0014"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Fourteen: The Nature of Subject Matter </h2>
<p>1. Subject Matter of Educator and of Learner. So far as the nature of
subject matter in principle is concerned, there is nothing to add to what
has been said (See ante, p. 134). It consists of the facts observed,
recalled, read, and talked about, and the ideas suggested, in course of a
development of a situation having a purpose. This statement needs to be
rendered more specific by connecting it with the materials of school
instruction, the studies which make up the curriculum. What is the
significance of our definition in application to reading, writing,
mathematics, history, nature study, drawing, singing, physics, chemistry,
modern and foreign languages, and so on? Let us recur to two of the points
made earlier in our discussion. The educator's part in the enterprise of
education is to furnish the environment which stimulates responses and
directs the learner's course. In last analysis, all that the educator can
do is modify stimuli so that response will as surely as is possible result
in the formation of desirable intellectual and emotional dispositions.
Obviously studies or the subject matter of the curriculum have intimately
to do with this business of supplying an environment. The other point is
the necessity of a social environment to give meaning to habits formed. In
what we have termed informal education, subject matter is carried directly
in the matrix of social intercourse. It is what the persons with whom an
individual associates do and say. This fact gives a clew to the
understanding of the subject matter of formal or deliberate instruction. A
connecting link is found in the stories, traditions, songs, and liturgies
which accompany the doings and rites of a primitive social group. They
represent the stock of meanings which have been precipitated out of
previous experience, which are so prized by the group as to be identified
with their conception of their own collective life. Not being obviously a
part of the skill exhibited in the daily occupations of eating, hunting,
making war and peace, constructing rugs, pottery, and baskets, etc., they
are consciously impressed upon the young; often, as in the initiation
ceremonies, with intense emotional fervor. Even more pains are consciously
taken to perpetuate the myths, legends, and sacred verbal formulae of the
group than to transmit the directly useful customs of the group just
because they cannot be picked up, as the latter can be in the ordinary
processes of association.</p>
<p>As the social group grows more complex, involving a greater number of
acquired skills which are dependent, either in fact or in the belief of
the group, upon standard ideas deposited from past experience, the content
of social life gets more definitely formulated for purposes of
instruction. As we have previously noted, probably the chief motive for
consciously dwelling upon the group life, extracting the meanings which
are regarded as most important and systematizing them in a coherent
arrangement, is just the need of instructing the young so as to perpetuate
group life. Once started on this road of selection, formulation, and
organization, no definite limit exists. The invention of writing and of
printing gives the operation an immense impetus. Finally, the bonds which
connect the subject matter of school study with the habits and ideals of
the social group are disguised and covered up. The ties are so loosened
that it often appears as if there were none; as if subject matter existed
simply as knowledge on its own independent behoof, and as if study were
the mere act of mastering it for its own sake, irrespective of any social
values. Since it is highly important for practical reasons to counter-act
this tendency (See ante, p. 8) the chief purposes of our theoretical
discussion are to make clear the connection which is so readily lost from
sight, and to show in some detail the social content and function of the
chief constituents of the course of study.</p>
<p>The points need to be considered from the standpoint of instructor and of
student. To the former, the significance of a knowledge of subject matter,
going far beyond the present knowledge of pupils, is to supply definite
standards and to reveal to him the possibilities of the crude activities
of the immature. (i) The material of school studies translates into
concrete and detailed terms the meanings of current social life which it
is desirable to transmit. It puts clearly before the instructor the
essential ingredients of the culture to be perpetuated, in such an
organized form as to protect him from the haphazard efforts he would be
likely to indulge in if the meanings had not been standardized. (ii) A
knowledge of the ideas which have been achieved in the past as the outcome
of activity places the educator in a position to perceive the meaning of
the seeming impulsive and aimless reactions of the young, and to provide
the stimuli needed to direct them so that they will amount to something.
The more the educator knows of music the more he can perceive the
possibilities of the inchoate musical impulses of a child. Organized
subject matter represents the ripe fruitage of experiences like theirs,
experiences involving the same world, and powers and needs similar to
theirs. It does not represent perfection or infallible wisdom; but it is
the best at command to further new experiences which may, in some respects
at least, surpass the achievements embodied in existing knowledge and
works of art.</p>
<p>From the standpoint of the educator, in other words, the various studies
represent working resources, available capital. Their remoteness from the
experience of the young is not, however, seeming; it is real. The subject
matter of the learner is not, therefore, it cannot be, identical with the
formulated, the crystallized, and systematized subject matter of the
adult; the material as found in books and in works of art, etc. The latter
represents the possibilities of the former; not its existing state. It
enters directly into the activities of the expert and the educator, not
into that of the beginner, the learner. Failure to bear in mind the
difference in subject matter from the respective standpoints of teacher
and student is responsible for most of the mistakes made in the use of
texts and other expressions of preexistent knowledge.</p>
<p>The need for a knowledge of the constitution and functions, in the
concrete, of human nature is great just because the teacher's attitude to
subject matter is so different from that of the pupil. The teacher
presents in actuality what the pupil represents only in posse. That is,
the teacher already knows the things which the student is only learning.
Hence the problem of the two is radically unlike. When engaged in the
direct act of teaching, the instructor needs to have subject matter at his
fingers' ends; his attention should be upon the attitude and response of
the pupil. To understand the latter in its interplay with subject matter
is his task, while the pupil's mind, naturally, should be not on itself
but on the topic in hand. Or to state the same point in a somewhat
different manner: the teacher should be occupied not with subject matter
in itself but in its interaction with the pupils' present needs and
capacities. Hence simple scholarship is not enough. In fact, there are
certain features of scholarship or mastered subject matter—taken by
itself—which get in the way of effective teaching unless the
instructor's habitual attitude is one of concern with its interplay in the
pupil's own experience. In the first place, his knowledge extends
indefinitely beyond the range of the pupil's acquaintance. It involves
principles which are beyond the immature pupil's understanding and
interest. In and of itself, it may no more represent the living world of
the pupil's experience than the astronomer's knowledge of Mars represents
a baby's acquaintance with the room in which he stays. In the second
place, the method of organization of the material of achieved scholarship
differs from that of the beginner. It is not true that the experience of
the young is unorganized—that it consists of isolated scraps. But it
is organized in connection with direct practical centers of interest. The
child's home is, for example, the organizing center of his geographical
knowledge. His own movements about the locality, his journeys abroad, the
tales of his friends, give the ties which hold his items of information
together. But the geography of the geographer, of the one who has already
developed the implications of these smaller experiences, is organized on
the basis of the relationship which the various facts bear to one another—not
the relations which they bear to his house, bodily movements, and friends.
To the one who is learned, subject matter is extensive, accurately
defined, and logically interrelated. To the one who is learning, it is
fluid, partial, and connected through his personal occupations. 1 The
problem of teaching is to keep the experience of the student moving in the
direction of what the expert already knows. Hence the need that the
teacher know both subject matter and the characteristic needs and
capacities of the student.</p>
<p>2. The Development of Subject Matter in the Learner. It is possible,
without doing violence to the facts, to mark off three fairly typical
stages in the growth of subject matter in the experience of the learner.
In its first estate, knowledge exists as the content of intelligent
ability—power to do. This kind of subject matter, or known material,
is expressed in familiarity or acquaintance with things. Then this
material gradually is surcharged and deepened through communicated
knowledge or information. Finally, it is enlarged and worked over into
rationally or logically organized material—that of the one who,
relatively speaking, is expert in the subject.</p>
<p>I. The knowledge which comes first to persons, and that remains most
deeply ingrained, is knowledge of how to do; how to walk, talk, read,
write, skate, ride a bicycle, manage a machine, calculate, drive a horse,
sell goods, manage people, and so on indefinitely. The popular tendency to
regard instinctive acts which are adapted to an end as a sort of
miraculous knowledge, while unjustifiable, is evidence of the strong
tendency to identify intelligent control of the means of action with
knowledge. When education, under the influence of a scholastic conception
of knowledge which ignores everything but scientifically formulated facts
and truths, fails to recognize that primary or initial subject matter
always exists as matter of an active doing, involving the use of the body
and the handling of material, the subject matter of instruction is
isolated from the needs and purposes of the learner, and so becomes just a
something to be memorized and reproduced upon demand. Recognition of the
natural course of development, on the contrary, always sets out with
situations which involve learning by doing. Arts and occupations form the
initial stage of the curriculum, corresponding as they do to knowing how
to go about the accomplishment of ends. Popular terms denoting knowledge
have always retained the connection with ability in action lost by
academic philosophies. Ken and can are allied words. Attention means
caring for a thing, in the sense of both affection and of looking out for
its welfare. Mind means carrying out instructions in action—as a
child minds his mother—and taking care of something—as a nurse
minds the baby. To be thoughtful, considerate, means to heed the claims of
others. Apprehension means dread of undesirable consequences, as well as
intellectual grasp. To have good sense or judgment is to know the conduct
a situation calls for; discernment is not making distinctions for the sake
of making them, an exercise reprobated as hair splitting, but is insight
into an affair with reference to acting. Wisdom has never lost its
association with the proper direction of life. Only in education, never in
the life of farmer, sailor, merchant, physician, or laboratory
experimenter, does knowledge mean primarily a store of information aloof
from doing. Having to do with things in an intelligent way issues in
acquaintance or familiarity. The things we are best acquainted with are
the things we put to frequent use—such things as chairs, tables,
pen, paper, clothes, food, knives and forks on the commonplace level,
differentiating into more special objects according to a person's
occupations in life. Knowledge of things in that intimate and emotional
sense suggested by the word acquaintance is a precipitate from our
employing them with a purpose. We have acted with or upon the thing so
frequently that we can anticipate how it will act and react—such is
the meaning of familiar acquaintance. We are ready for a familiar thing;
it does not catch us napping, or play unexpected tricks with us. This
attitude carries with it a sense of congeniality or friendliness, of ease
and illumination; while the things with which we are not accustomed to
deal are strange, foreign, cold, remote, "abstract."</p>
<p>II. But it is likely that elaborate statements regarding this primary
stage of knowledge will darken understanding. It includes practically all
of our knowledge which is not the result of deliberate technical study.
Modes of purposeful doing include dealings with persons as well as things.
Impulses of communication and habits of intercourse have to be adapted to
maintaining successful connections with others; a large fund of social
knowledge accrues. As a part of this intercommunication one learns much
from others. They tell of their experiences and of the experiences which,
in turn, have been told them. In so far as one is interested or concerned
in these communications, their matter becomes a part of one's own
experience. Active connections with others are such an intimate and vital
part of our own concerns that it is impossible to draw sharp lines, such
as would enable us to say, "Here my experience ends; there yours begins."
In so far as we are partners in common undertakings, the things which
others communicate to us as the consequences of their particular share in
the enterprise blend at once into the experience resulting from our own
special doings. The ear is as much an organ of experience as the eye or
hand; the eye is available for reading reports of what happens beyond its
horizon. Things remote in space and time affect the issue of our actions
quite as much as things which we can smell and handle. They really concern
us, and, consequently, any account of them which assists us in dealing
with things at hand falls within personal experience.</p>
<p>Information is the name usually given to this kind of subject matter. The
place of communication in personal doing supplies us with a criterion for
estimating the value of informational material in school. Does it grow
naturally out of some question with which the student is concerned? Does
it fit into his more direct acquaintance so as to increase its efficacy
and deepen its meaning? If it meets these two requirements, it is
educative. The amount heard or read is of no importance—the more the
better, provided the student has a need for it and can apply it in some
situation of his own.</p>
<p>But it is not so easy to fulfill these requirements in actual practice as
it is to lay them down in theory. The extension in modern times of the
area of intercommunication; the invention of appliances for securing
acquaintance with remote parts of the heavens and bygone events of
history; the cheapening of devices, like printing, for recording and
distributing information—genuine and alleged—have created an
immense bulk of communicated subject matter. It is much easier to swamp a
pupil with this than to work it into his direct experiences. All too
frequently it forms another strange world which just overlies the world of
personal acquaintance. The sole problem of the student is to learn, for
school purposes, for purposes of recitations and promotions, the
constituent parts of this strange world. Probably the most conspicuous
connotation of the word knowledge for most persons to-day is just the body
of facts and truths ascertained by others; the material found in the rows
and rows of atlases, cyclopedias, histories, biographies, books of travel,
scientific treatises, on the shelves of libraries.</p>
<p>The imposing stupendous bulk of this material has unconsciously influenced
men's notions of the nature of knowledge itself. The statements, the
propositions, in which knowledge, the issue of active concern with
problems, is deposited, are taken to be themselves knowledge. The record
of knowledge, independent of its place as an outcome of inquiry and a
resource in further inquiry, is taken to be knowledge. The mind of man is
taken captive by the spoils of its prior victories; the spoils, not the
weapons and the acts of waging the battle against the unknown, are used to
fix the meaning of knowledge, of fact, and truth.</p>
<p>If this identification of knowledge with propositions stating information
has fastened itself upon logicians and philosophers, it is not surprising
that the same ideal has almost dominated instruction. The "course of
study" consists largely of information distributed into various branches
of study, each study being subdivided into lessons presenting in serial
cutoff portions of the total store. In the seventeenth century, the store
was still small enough so that men set up the ideal of a complete
encyclopedic mastery of it. It is now so bulky that the impossibility of
any one man's coming into possession of it all is obvious. But the
educational ideal has not been much affected. Acquisition of a modicum of
information in each branch of learning, or at least in a selected group,
remains the principle by which the curriculum, from elementary school
through college, is formed; the easier portions being assigned to the
earlier years, the more difficult to the later. The complaints of
educators that learning does not enter into character and affect conduct;
the protests against memoriter work, against cramming, against gradgrind
preoccupation with "facts," against devotion to wire-drawn distinctions
and ill-understood rules and principles, all follow from this state of
affairs. Knowledge which is mainly second-hand, other men's knowledge,
tends to become merely verbal. It is no objection to information that it
is clothed in words; communication necessarily takes place through words.
But in the degree in which what is communicated cannot be organized into
the existing experience of the learner, it becomes mere words: that is,
pure sense-stimuli, lacking in meaning. Then it operates to call out
mechanical reactions, ability to use the vocal organs to repeat
statements, or the hand to write or to do "sums."</p>
<p>To be informed is to be posted; it is to have at command the subject
matter needed for an effective dealing with a problem, and for giving
added significance to the search for solution and to the solution itself.
Informational knowledge is the material which can be fallen back upon as
given, settled, established, assured in a doubtful situation. It is a kind
of bridge for mind in its passage from doubt to discovery. It has the
office of an intellectual middleman. It condenses and records in available
form the net results of the prior experiences of mankind, as an agency of
enhancing the meaning of new experiences. When one is told that Brutus
assassinated Caesar, or that the length of the year is three hundred
sixty-five and one fourth days, or that the ratio of the diameter of the
circle to its circumference is 3.1415. . . one receives what is indeed
knowledge for others, but for him it is a stimulus to knowing. His
acquisition of knowledge depends upon his response to what is
communicated.</p>
<p>3. Science or Rationalized Knowledge. Science is a name for knowledge in
its most characteristic form. It represents in its degree, the perfected
outcome of learning,—its consummation. What is known, in a given
case, is what is sure, certain, settled, disposed of; that which we think
with rather than that which we think about. In its honorable sense,
knowledge is distinguished from opinion, guesswork, speculation, and mere
tradition. In knowledge, things are ascertained; they are so and not
dubiously otherwise. But experience makes us aware that there is
difference between intellectual certainty of subject matter and our
certainty. We are made, so to speak, for belief; credulity is natural. The
undisciplined mind is averse to suspense and intellectual hesitation; it
is prone to assertion. It likes things undisturbed, settled, and treats
them as such without due warrant. Familiarity, common repute, and
congeniality to desire are readily made measuring rods of truth. Ignorance
gives way to opinionated and current error,—a greater foe to
learning than ignorance itself. A Socrates is thus led to declare that
consciousness of ignorance is the beginning of effective love of wisdom,
and a Descartes to say that science is born of doubting.</p>
<p>We have already dwelt upon the fact that subject matter, or data, and
ideas have to have their worth tested experimentally: that in themselves
they are tentative and provisional. Our predilection for premature
acceptance and assertion, our aversion to suspended judgment, are signs
that we tend naturally to cut short the process of testing. We are
satisfied with superficial and immediate short-visioned applications. If
these work out with moderate satisfactoriness, we are content to suppose
that our assumptions have been confirmed. Even in the case of failure, we
are inclined to put the blame not on the inadequacy and incorrectness of
our data and thoughts, but upon our hard luck and the hostility of
circumstance. We charge the evil consequence not to the error of our
schemes and our incomplete inquiry into conditions (thereby getting
material for revising the former and stimulus for extending the latter)
but to untoward fate. We even plume ourselves upon our firmness in
clinging to our conceptions in spite of the way in which they work out.</p>
<p>Science represents the safeguard of the race against these natural
propensities and the evils which flow from them. It consists of the
special appliances and methods which the race has slowly worked out in
order to conduct reflection under conditions whereby its procedures and
results are tested. It is artificial (an acquired art), not spontaneous;
learned, not native. To this fact is due the unique, the invaluable place
of science in education, and also the dangers which threaten its right
use. Without initiation into the scientific spirit one is not in
possession of the best tools which humanity has so far devised for
effectively directed reflection. One in that case not merely conducts
inquiry and learning without the use of the best instruments, but fails to
understand the full meaning of knowledge. For he does not become
acquainted with the traits that mark off opinion and assent from
authorized conviction. On the other hand, the fact that science marks the
perfecting of knowing in highly specialized conditions of technique
renders its results, taken by themselves, remote from ordinary experience—a
quality of aloofness that is popularly designated by the term abstract.
When this isolation appears in instruction, scientific information is even
more exposed to the dangers attendant upon presenting ready-made subject
matter than are other forms of information.</p>
<p>Science has been defined in terms of method of inquiry and testing. At
first sight, this definition may seem opposed to the current conception
that science is organized or systematized knowledge. The opposition,
however, is only seeming, and disappears when the ordinary definition is
completed. Not organization but the kind of organization effected by
adequate methods of tested discovery marks off science. The knowledge of a
farmer is systematized in the degree in which he is competent. It is
organized on the basis of relation of means to ends—practically
organized. Its organization as knowledge (that is, in the eulogistic sense
of adequately tested and confirmed) is incidental to its organization with
reference to securing crops, live-stock, etc. But scientific subject
matter is organized with specific reference to the successful conduct of
the enterprise of discovery, to knowing as a specialized undertaking.
Reference to the kind of assurance attending science will shed light upon
this statement. It is rational assurance,—logical warranty. The
ideal of scientific organization is, therefore, that every conception and
statement shall be of such a kind as to follow from others and to lead to
others. Conceptions and propositions mutually imply and support one
another. This double relation of "leading to and confirming" is what is
meant by the terms logical and rational. The everyday conception of water
is more available for ordinary uses of drinking, washing, irrigation,
etc., than the chemist's notion of it. The latter's description of it as
H20 is superior from the standpoint of place and use in inquiry. It states
the nature of water in a way which connects it with knowledge of other
things, indicating to one who understands it how the knowledge is arrived
at and its bearings upon other portions of knowledge of the structure of
things. Strictly speaking, it does not indicate the objective relations of
water any more than does a statement that water is transparent, fluid,
without taste or odor, satisfying to thirst, etc. It is just as true that
water has these relations as that it is constituted by two molecules of
hydrogen in combination with one of oxygen. But for the particular purpose
of conducting discovery with a view to ascertainment of fact, the latter
relations are fundamental. The more one emphasizes organization as a mark
of science, then, the more he is committed to a recognition of the primacy
of method in the definition of science. For method defines the kind of
organization in virtue of which science is science.</p>
<p>4. Subject Matter as Social. Our next chapters will take up various school
activities and studies and discuss them as successive stages in that
evolution of knowledge which we have just been discussing. It remains to
say a few words upon subject matter as social, since our prior remarks
have been mainly concerned with its intellectual aspect. A difference in
breadth and depth exists even in vital knowledge; even in the data and
ideas which are relevant to real problems and which are motivated by
purposes. For there is a difference in the social scope of purposes and
the social importance of problems. With the wide range of possible
material to select from, it is important that education (especially in all
its phases short of the most specialized) should use a criterion of social
worth. All information and systematized scientific subject matter have
been worked out under the conditions of social life and have been
transmitted by social means. But this does not prove that all is of equal
value for the purposes of forming the disposition and supplying the
equipment of members of present society. The scheme of a curriculum must
take account of the adaptation of studies to the needs of the existing
community life; it must select with the intention of improving the life we
live in common so that the future shall be better than the past. Moreover,
the curriculum must be planned with reference to placing essentials first,
and refinements second. The things which are socially most fundamental,
that is, which have to do with the experiences in which the widest groups
share, are the essentials. The things which represent the needs of
specialized groups and technical pursuits are secondary. There is truth in
the saying that education must first be human and only after that
professional. But those who utter the saying frequently have in mind in
the term human only a highly specialized class: the class of learned men
who preserve the classic traditions of the past. They forget that material
is humanized in the degree in which it connects with the common interests
of men as men. Democratic society is peculiarly dependent for its
maintenance upon the use in forming a course of study of criteria which
are broadly human. Democracy cannot flourish where the chief influences in
selecting subject matter of instruction are utilitarian ends narrowly
conceived for the masses, and, for the higher education of the few, the
traditions of a specialized cultivated class. The notion that the
"essentials" of elementary education are the three R's mechanically
treated, is based upon ignorance of the essentials needed for realization
of democratic ideals. Unconsciously it assumes that these ideals are
unrealizable; it assumes that in the future, as in the past, getting a
livelihood, "making a living," must signify for most men and women doing
things which are not significant, freely chosen, and ennobling to those
who do them; doing things which serve ends unrecognized by those engaged
in them, carried on under the direction of others for the sake of
pecuniary reward. For preparation of large numbers for a life of this
sort, and only for this purpose, are mechanical efficiency in reading,
writing, spelling and figuring, together with attainment of a certain
amount of muscular dexterity, "essentials." Such conditions also infect
the education called liberal, with illiberality. They imply a somewhat
parasitic cultivation bought at the expense of not having the
enlightenment and discipline which come from concern with the deepest
problems of common humanity. A curriculum which acknowledges the social
responsibilities of education must present situations where problems are
relevant to the problems of living together, and where observation and
information are calculated to develop social insight and interest.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM14" id="link2H_SUMM14"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. The subject matter of education consists primarily of the </h2>
<p>meanings which supply content to existing social life. The continuity of
social life means that many of these meanings are contributed to present
activity by past collective experience. As social life grows more complex,
these factors increase in number and import. There is need of special
selection, formulation, and organization in order that they may be
adequately transmitted to the new generation. But this very process tends
to set up subject matter as something of value just by itself, apart from
its function in promoting the realization of the meanings implied in the
present experience of the immature. Especially is the educator exposed to
the temptation to conceive his task in terms of the pupil's ability to
appropriate and reproduce the subject matter in set statements,
irrespective of its organization into his activities as a developing
social member. The positive principle is maintained when the young begin
with active occupations having a social origin and use, and proceed to a
scientific insight in the materials and laws involved, through
assimilating into their more direct experience the ideas and facts
communicated by others who have had a larger experience. 1 Since the
learned man should also still be a learner, it will be understood that
these contrasts are relative, not absolute. But in the earlier stages of
learning at least they are practically all-important.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />