<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0022" id="link2HCH0022"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Twenty-two: The Individual and the World </h2>
<p>1. Mind as Purely Individual. We have been concerned with the influences
which have effected a division between work and leisure, knowing and
doing, man and nature. These influences have resulted in splitting up the
subject matter of education into separate studies. They have also found
formulation in various philosophies which have opposed to each other body
and mind, theoretical knowledge and practice, physical mechanism and ideal
purpose. Upon the philosophical side, these various dualisms culminate in
a sharp demarcation of individual minds from the world, and hence from one
another. While the connection of this philosophical position with
educational procedure is not so obvious as is that of the points
considered in the last three chapters, there are certain educational
considerations which correspond to it; such as the antithesis supposed to
exist between subject matter (the counterpart of the world) and method
(the counterpart of mind); such as the tendency to treat interest as
something purely private, without intrinsic connection with the material
studied. Aside from incidental educational bearings, it will be shown in
this chapter that the dualistic philosophy of mind and the world implies
an erroneous conception of the relationship between knowledge and social
interests, and between individuality or freedom, and social control and
authority. The identification of the mind with the individual self and of
the latter with a private psychic consciousness is comparatively modern.
In both the Greek and medieval periods, the rule was to regard the
individual as a channel through which a universal and divine intelligence
operated. The individual was in no true sense the knower; the knower was
the "Reason" which operated through him. The individual interfered at his
peril, and only to the detriment of the truth. In the degree in which the
individual rather than reason "knew," conceit, error, and opinion were
substituted for true knowledge. In Greek life, observation was acute and
alert; and thinking was free almost to the point of irresponsible
speculations. Accordingly the consequences of the theory were only such as
were consequent upon the lack of an experimental method. Without such a
method individuals could not engage in knowing, and be checked up by the
results of the inquiries of others. Without such liability to test by
others, the minds of men could not be intellectually responsible; results
were to be accepted because of their aesthetic consistency, agreeable
quality, or the prestige of their authors. In the barbarian period,
individuals were in a still more humble attitude to truth; important
knowledge was supposed to be divinely revealed, and nothing remained for
the minds of individuals except to work it over after it had been received
on authority. Aside from the more consciously philosophic aspects of these
movements, it never occurs to any one to identify mind and the personal
self wherever beliefs are transmitted by custom.</p>
<p>In the medieval period there was a religious individualism. The deepest
concern of life was the salvation of the individual soul. In the later
Middle Ages, this latent individualism found conscious formulation in the
nominalistic philosophies, which treated the structure of knowledge as
something built up within the individual through his own acts, and mental
states. With the rise of economic and political individualism after the
sixteenth century, and with the development of Protestantism, the times
were ripe for an emphasis upon the rights and duties of the individual in
achieving knowledge for himself. This led to the view that knowledge is
won wholly through personal and private experiences. As a consequence,
mind, the source and possessor of knowledge, was thought of as wholly
individual. Thus upon the educational side, we find educational reformers,
like Montaigne, Bacon, Locke, henceforth vehemently denouncing all
learning which is acquired on hearsay, and asserting that even if beliefs
happen to be true, they do not constitute knowledge unless they have grown
up in and been tested by personal experience. The reaction against
authority in all spheres of life, and the intensity of the struggle,
against great odds, for freedom of action and inquiry, led to such an
emphasis upon personal observations and ideas as in effect to isolate
mind, and set it apart from the world to be known.</p>
<p>This isolation is reflected in the great development of that branch of
philosophy known as epistemology—the theory of knowledge. The
identification of mind with the self, and the setting up of the self as
something independent and self-sufficient, created such a gulf between the
knowing mind and the world that it became a question how knowledge was
possible at all. Given a subject—the knower—and an object—the
thing to be known—wholly separate from one another, it is necessary
to frame a theory to explain how they get into connection with each other
so that valid knowledge may result. This problem, with the allied one of
the possibility of the world acting upon the mind and the mind acting upon
the world, became almost the exclusive preoccupation of philosophic
thought.</p>
<p>The theories that we cannot know the world as it really is but only the
impressions made upon the mind, or that there is no world beyond the
individual mind, or that knowledge is only a certain association of the
mind's own states, were products of this preoccupation. We are not
directly concerned with their truth; but the fact that such desperate
solutions were widely accepted is evidence of the extent to which mind had
been set over the world of realities. The increasing use of the term
"consciousness" as an equivalent for mind, in the supposition that there
is an inner world of conscious states and processes, independent of any
relationship to nature and society, an inner world more truly and
immediately known than anything else, is evidence of the same fact. In
short, practical individualism, or struggle for greater freedom of thought
in action, was translated into philosophic subjectivism.</p>
<p>2. Individual Mind as the Agent of Reorganization. It should be obvious
that this philosophic movement misconceived the significance of the
practical movement. Instead of being its transcript, it was a perversion.
Men were not actually engaged in the absurdity of striving to be free from
connection with nature and one another. They were striving for greater
freedom in nature and society. They wanted greater power to initiate
changes in the world of things and fellow beings; greater scope of
movement and consequently greater freedom in observations and ideas
implied in movement. They wanted not isolation from the world, but a more
intimate connection with it. They wanted to form their beliefs about it at
first hand, instead of through tradition. They wanted closer union with
their fellows so that they might influence one another more effectively
and might combine their respective actions for mutual aims.</p>
<p>So far as their beliefs were concerned, they felt that a great deal which
passed for knowledge was merely the accumulated opinions of the past, much
of it absurd and its correct portions not understood when accepted on
authority. Men must observe for themselves, and form their own theories
and personally test them. Such a method was the only alternative to the
imposition of dogma as truth, a procedure which reduced mind to the formal
act of acquiescing in truth. Such is the meaning of what is sometimes
called the substitution of inductive experimental methods of knowing for
deductive. In some sense, men had always used an inductive method in
dealing with their immediate practical concerns. Architecture,
agriculture, manufacture, etc., had to be based upon observation of the
activities of natural objects, and ideas about such affairs had to be
checked, to some extent, by results. But even in such things there was an
undue reliance upon mere custom, followed blindly rather than
understandingly. And this observational-experimental method was restricted
to these "practical" matters, and a sharp distinction maintained between
practice and theoretical knowledge or truth. (See Ch. XX.) The rise of
free cities, the development of travel, exploration, and commerce, the
evolution of new methods of producing commodities and doing business,
threw men definitely upon their own resources. The reformers of science
like Galileo, Descartes, and their successors, carried analogous methods
into ascertaining the facts about nature. An interest in discovery took
the place of an interest in systematizing and "proving" received beliefs.</p>
<p>A just philosophic interpretation of these movements would, indeed, have
emphasized the rights and responsibilities of the individual in gaining
knowledge and personally testing beliefs, no matter by what authorities
they were vouched for. But it would not have isolated the individual from
the world, and consequently isolated individuals—in theory—from
one another. It would have perceived that such disconnection, such rupture
of continuity, denied in advance the possibility of success in their
endeavors. As matter of fact every individual has grown up, and always
must grow up, in a social medium. His responses grow intelligent, or gain
meaning, simply because he lives and acts in a medium of accepted meanings
and values. (See ante, p. 30.) Through social intercourse, through sharing
in the activities embodying beliefs, he gradually acquires a mind of his
own. The conception of mind as a purely isolated possession of the self is
at the very antipodes of the truth. The self achieves mind in the degree
in which knowledge of things is incarnate in the life about him; the self
is not a separate mind building up knowledge anew on its own account.</p>
<p>Yet there is a valid distinction between knowledge which is objective and
impersonal, and thinking which is subjective and personal. In one sense,
knowledge is that which we take for granted. It is that which is settled,
disposed of, established, under control. What we fully know, we do not
need to think about. In common phrase, it is certain, assured. And this
does not mean a mere feeling of certainty. It denotes not a sentiment, but
a practical attitude, a readiness to act without reserve or quibble. Of
course we may be mistaken. What is taken for knowledge—for fact and
truth—at a given time may not be such. But everything which is
assumed without question, which is taken for granted in our intercourse
with one another and nature is what, at the given time, is called
knowledge. Thinking on the contrary, starts, as we have seen, from doubt
or uncertainty. It marks an inquiring, hunting, searching attitude,
instead of one of mastery and possession. Through its critical process
true knowledge is revised and extended, and our convictions as to the
state of things reorganized. Clearly the last few centuries have been
typically a period of revision and reorganization of beliefs. Men did not
really throw away all transmitted beliefs concerning the realities of
existence, and start afresh upon the basis of their private, exclusive
sensations and ideas. They could not have done so if they had wished to,
and if it had been possible general imbecility would have been the only
outcome. Men set out from what had passed as knowledge, and critically
investigated the grounds upon which it rested; they noted exceptions; they
used new mechanical appliances to bring to light data inconsistent with
what had been believed; they used their imaginations to conceive a world
different from that in which their forefathers had put their trust. The
work was a piecemeal, a retail, business. One problem was tackled at a
time. The net results of all the revisions amounted, however, to a
revolution of prior conceptions of the world. What occurred was a
reorganization of prior intellectual habitudes, infinitely more efficient
than a cutting loose from all connections would have been.</p>
<p>This state of affairs suggests a definition of the role of the individual,
or the self, in knowledge; namely, the redirection, or reconstruction of
accepted beliefs. Every new idea, every conception of things differing
from that authorized by current belief, must have its origin in an
individual. New ideas are doubtless always sprouting, but a society
governed by custom does not encourage their development. On the contrary,
it tends to suppress them, just because they are deviations from what is
current. The man who looks at things differently from others is in such a
community a suspect character; for him to persist is generally fatal. Even
when social censorship of beliefs is not so strict, social conditions may
fail to provide the appliances which are requisite if new ideas are to be
adequately elaborated; or they may fail to provide any material support
and reward to those who entertain them. Hence they remain mere fancies,
romantic castles in the air, or aimless speculations. The freedom of
observation and imagination involved in the modern scientific revolution
were not easily secured; they had to be fought for; many suffered for
their intellectual independence. But, upon the whole, modern European
society first permitted, and then, in some fields at least, deliberately
encouraged the individual reactions which deviate from what custom
prescribes. Discovery, research, inquiry in new lines, inventions, finally
came to be either the social fashion, or in some degree tolerable.
However, as we have already noted, philosophic theories of knowledge were
not content to conceive mind in the individual as the pivot upon which
reconstruction of beliefs turned, thus maintaining the continuity of the
individual with the world of nature and fellow men. They regarded the
individual mind as a separate entity, complete in each person, and
isolated from nature and hence from other minds. Thus a legitimate
intellectual individualism, the attitude of critical revision of former
beliefs which is indispensable to progress, was explicitly formulated as a
moral and social individualism. When the activities of mind set out from
customary beliefs and strive to effect transformations of them which will
in turn win general conviction, there is no opposition between the
individual and the social. The intellectual variations of the individual
in observation, imagination, judgment, and invention are simply the
agencies of social progress, just as conformity to habit is the agency of
social conservation. But when knowledge is regarded as originating and
developing within an individual, the ties which bind the mental life of
one to that of his fellows are ignored and denied.</p>
<p>When the social quality of individualized mental operations is denied, it
becomes a problem to find connections which will unite an individual with
his fellows. Moral individualism is set up by the conscious separation of
different centers of life. It has its roots in the notion that the
consciousness of each person is wholly private, a self-inclosed continent,
intrinsically independent of the ideas, wishes, purposes of everybody
else. But when men act, they act in a common and public world. This is the
problem to which the theory of isolated and independent conscious minds
gave rise: Given feelings, ideas, desires, which have nothing to do with
one another, how can actions proceeding from them be controlled in a
social or public interest? Given an egoistic consciousness, how can action
which has regard for others take place?</p>
<p>Moral philosophies which have started from such premises have developed
four typical ways of dealing with the question. (i) One method represents
the survival of the older authoritative position, with such concessions
and compromises as the progress of events has made absolutely inevitable.
The deviations and departures characterizing an individual are still
looked upon with suspicion; in principle they are evidences of the
disturbances, revolts, and corruptions inhering in an individual apart
from external authoritative guidance. In fact, as distinct from principle,
intellectual individualism is tolerated in certain technical regions—in
subjects like mathematics and physics and astronomy, and in the technical
inventions resulting therefrom. But the applicability of a similar method
to morals, social, legal, and political matters, is denied. In such
matters, dogma is still to be supreme; certain eternal truths made known
by revelation, intuition, or the wisdom of our forefathers set unpassable
limits to individual observation and speculation. The evils from which
society suffers are set down to the efforts of misguided individuals to
transgress these boundaries. Between the physical and the moral sciences,
lie intermediate sciences of life, where the territory is only grudgingly
yielded to freedom of inquiry under the pressure of accomplished fact.
Although past history has demonstrated that the possibilities of human
good are widened and made more secure by trusting to a responsibility
built up within the very process of inquiry, the "authority" theory sets
apart a sacred domain of truth which must be protected from the inroads of
variation of beliefs. Educationally, emphasis may not be put on eternal
truth, but it is put on the authority of book and teacher, and individual
variation is discouraged.</p>
<p>(ii) Another method is sometimes termed rationalism or abstract
intellectualism. A formal logical faculty is set up in distinction from
tradition and history and all concrete subject matter. This faculty of
reason is endowed with power to influence conduct directly. Since it deals
wholly with general and impersonal forms, when different persons act in
accord with logical findings, their activities will be externally
consistent. There is no doubt of the services rendered by this philosophy.
It was a powerful factor in the negative and dissolving criticism of
doctrines having nothing but tradition and class interest behind them; it
accustomed men to freedom of discussion and to the notion that beliefs had
to be submitted to criteria of reasonableness. It undermined the power of
prejudice, superstition, and brute force, by habituating men to reliance
upon argument, discussion, and persuasion. It made for clarity and order
of exposition. But its influence was greater in destruction of old
falsities than in the construction of new ties and associations among men.
Its formal and empty nature, due to conceiving reason as something
complete in itself apart from subject matter, its hostile attitude toward
historical institutions, its disregard of the influence of habit,
instinct, and emotion, as operative factors in life, left it impotent in
the suggestion of specific aims and methods. Bare logic, however important
in arranging and criticizing existing subject matter, cannot spin new
subject matter out of itself. In education, the correlative is trust in
general ready-made rules and principles to secure agreement, irrespective
of seeing to it that the pupil's ideas really agree with one another.</p>
<p>(iii) While this rationalistic philosophy was developing in France,
English thought appealed to the intelligent self-interest of individuals
in order to secure outer unity in the acts which issued from isolated
streams of consciousness. Legal arrangements, especially penal
administration, and governmental regulations, were to be such as to
prevent the acts which proceeded from regard for one's own private
sensations from interfering with the feelings of others. Education was to
instill in individuals a sense that non-interference with others and some
degree of positive regard for their welfare were necessary for security in
the pursuit of one's own happiness. Chief emphasis was put, however, upon
trade as a means of bringing the conduct of one into harmony with that of
others. In commerce, each aims at the satisfaction of his own wants, but
can gain his own profit only by furnishing some commodity or service to
another. Thus in aiming at the increase of his own private pleasurable
states of consciousness, he contributes to the consciousness of others.
Again there is no doubt that this view expressed and furthered a
heightened perception of the values of conscious life, and a recognition
that institutional arrangements are ultimately to be judged by the
contributions which they make to intensifying and enlarging the scope of
conscious experience. It also did much to rescue work, industry, and
mechanical devices from the contempt in which they had been held in
communities founded upon the control of a leisure class. In both ways,
this philosophy promoted a wider and more democratic social concern. But
it was tainted by the narrowness of its fundamental premise: the doctrine
that every individual acts only from regard for his own pleasures and
pains, and that so-called generous and sympathetic acts are only indirect
ways of procuring and assuring one's own comfort. In other words, it made
explicit the consequences inhering in any doctrine which makes mental life
a self-inclosed thing, instead of an attempt to redirect and readapt
common concerns. It made union among men a matter of calculation of
externals. It lent itself to the contemptuous assertions of Carlyle that
it was a doctrine of anarchy plus a constable, and recognized only a "cash
nexus" among men. The educational equivalents of this doctrine in the uses
made of pleasurable rewards and painful penalties are only too obvious.
(iv) Typical German philosophy followed another path. It started from what
was essentially the rationalistic philosophy of Descartes and his French
successors. But while French thought upon the whole developed the idea of
reason in opposition to the religious conception of a divine mind residing
in individuals, German thought (as in Hegel) made a synthesis of the two.
Reason is absolute. Nature is incarnate reason. History is reason in its
progressive unfolding in man. An individual becomes rational only as he
absorbs into himself the content of rationality in nature and in social
institutions. For an absolute reason is not, like the reason of
rationalism, purely formal and empty; as absolute it must include all
content within itself. Thus the real problem is not that of controlling
individual freedom so that some measure of social order and concord may
result, but of achieving individual freedom through developing individual
convictions in accord with the universal law found in the organization of
the state as objective Reason. While this philosophy is usually termed
absolute or objective idealism, it might better be termed, for educational
purposes at least, institutional idealism. (See ante, p. 59.) It idealized
historical institutions by conceiving them as incarnations of an immanent
absolute mind. There can be no doubt that this philosophy was a powerful
influence in rescuing philosophy in the beginning of the nineteenth
century from the isolated individualism into which it had fallen in France
and England. It served also to make the organization of the state more
constructively interested in matters of public concern. It left less to
chance, less to mere individual logical conviction, less to the workings
of private self-interest. It brought intelligence to bear upon the conduct
of affairs; it accentuated the need of nationally organized education in
the interests of the corporate state. It sanctioned and promoted freedom
of inquiry in all technical details of natural and historical phenomena.
But in all ultimate moral matters, it tended to reinstate the principle of
authority. It made for efficiency of organization more than did any of the
types of philosophy previously mentioned, but it made no provision for
free experimental modification of this organization. Political democracy,
with its belief in the right of individual desire and purpose to take part
in readapting even the fundamental constitution of society, was foreign to
it.</p>
<p>3. Educational Equivalents. It is not necessary to consider in detail the
educational counterparts of the various defects found in these various
types of philosophy. It suffices to say that in general the school has
been the institution which exhibited with greatest clearness the assumed
antithesis between purely individualistic methods of learning and social
action, and between freedom and social control. The antithesis is
reflected in the absence of a social atmosphere and motive for learning,
and the consequent separation, in the conduct of the school, between
method of instruction and methods of government; and in the slight
opportunity afforded individual variations. When learning is a phase of
active undertakings which involve mutual exchange, social control enters
into the very process of learning. When the social factor is absent,
learning becomes a carrying over of some presented material into a purely
individual consciousness, and there is no inherent reason why it should
give a more socialized direction to mental and emotional disposition.
There is tendency on the part of both the upholders and the opponents of
freedom in school to identify it with absence of social direction, or,
sometimes, with merely physical unconstraint of movement. But the essence
of the demand for freedom is the need of conditions which will enable an
individual to make his own special contribution to a group interest, and
to partake of its activities in such ways that social guidance shall be a
matter of his own mental attitude, and not a mere authoritative dictation
of his acts. Because what is often called discipline and "government" has
to do with the external side of conduct alone, a similar meaning is
attached, by reaction, to freedom. But when it is perceived that each idea
signifies the quality of mind expressed in action, the supposed opposition
between them falls away. Freedom means essentially the part played by
thinking—which is personal—in learning:—it means
intellectual initiative, independence in observation, judicious invention,
foresight of consequences, and ingenuity of adaptation to them.</p>
<p>But because these are the mental phase of behavior, the needed play of
individuality—or freedom—cannot be separated from opportunity
for free play of physical movements. Enforced physical quietude may be
unfavorable to realization of a problem, to undertaking the observations
needed to define it, and to performance of the experiments which test the
ideas suggested. Much has been said about the importance of
"self-activity" in education, but the conception has too frequently been
restricted to something merely internal—something excluding the free
use of sensory and motor organs. Those who are at the stage of learning
from symbols, or who are engaged in elaborating the implications of a
problem or idea preliminary to more carefully thought-out activity, may
need little perceptible overt activity. But the whole cycle of
self-activity demands an opportunity for investigation and
experimentation, for trying out one's ideas upon things, discovering what
can be done with materials and appliances. And this is incompatible with
closely restricted physical activity. Individual activity has sometimes
been taken as meaning leaving a pupil to work by himself or alone. Relief
from need of attending to what any one else is doing is truly required to
secure calm and concentration. Children, like grown persons, require a
judicious amount of being let alone. But the time, place, and amount of
such separate work is a matter of detail, not of principle. There is no
inherent opposition between working with others and working as an
individual. On the contrary, certain capacities of an individual are not
brought out except under the stimulus of associating with others. That a
child must work alone and not engage in group activities in order to be
free and let his individuality develop, is a notion which measures
individuality by spatial distance and makes a physical thing of it.</p>
<p>Individuality as a factor to be respected in education has a double
meaning. In the first place, one is mentally an individual only as he has
his own purpose and problem, and does his own thinking. The phrase "think
for one's self" is a pleonasm. Unless one does it for one's self, it isn't
thinking. Only by a pupil's own observations, reflections, framing and
testing of suggestions can what he already knows be amplified and
rectified. Thinking is as much an individual matter as is the digestion of
food. In the second place, there are variations of point of view, of
appeal of objects, and of mode of attack, from person to person. When
these variations are suppressed in the alleged interests of uniformity,
and an attempt is made to have a single mold of method of study and
recitation, mental confusion and artificiality inevitably result.
Originality is gradually destroyed, confidence in one's own quality of
mental operation is undermined, and a docile subjection to the opinion of
others is inculcated, or else ideas run wild. The harm is greater now than
when the whole community was governed by customary beliefs, because the
contrast between methods of learning in school and those relied upon
outside the school is greater. That systematic advance in scientific
discovery began when individuals were allowed, and then encouraged, to
utilize their own peculiarities of response to subject matter, no one will
deny. If it is said in objection, that pupils in school are not capable of
any such originality, and hence must be confined to appropriating and
reproducing things already known by the better informed, the reply is
twofold. (i) We are concerned with originality of attitude which is
equivalent to the unforced response of one's own individuality, not with
originality as measured by product. No one expects the young to make
original discoveries of just the same facts and principles as are embodied
in the sciences of nature and man. But it is not unreasonable to expect
that learning may take place under such conditions that from the
standpoint of the learner there is genuine discovery. While immature
students will not make discoveries from the standpoint of advanced
students, they make them from their own standpoint, whenever there is
genuine learning. (ii) In the normal process of becoming acquainted with
subject matter already known to others, even young pupils react in
unexpected ways. There is something fresh, something not capable of being
fully anticipated by even the most experienced teacher, in the ways they
go at the topic, and in the particular ways in which things strike them.
Too often all this is brushed aside as irrelevant; pupils are deliberately
held to rehearsing material in the exact form in which the older person
conceives it. The result is that what is instinctively original in
individuality, that which marks off one from another, goes unused and
undirected. Teaching then ceases to be an educative process for the
teacher. At most he learns simply to improve his existing technique; he
does not get new points of view; he fails to experience any intellectual
companionship. Hence both teaching and learning tend to become
conventional and mechanical with all the nervous strain on both sides
therein implied.</p>
<p>As maturity increases and as the student has a greater background of
familiarity upon which a new topic is projected, the scope of more or less
random physical experimentation is reduced. Activity is defined or
specialized in certain channels. To the eyes of others, the student may be
in a position of complete physical quietude, because his energies are
confined to nerve channels and to the connected apparatus of the eyes and
vocal organs. But because this attitude is evidence of intense mental
concentration on the part of the trained person, it does not follow that
it should be set up as a model for students who still have to find their
intellectual way about. And even with the adult, it does not cover the
whole circuit of mental energy. It marks an intermediate period, capable
of being lengthened with increased mastery of a subject, but always coming
between an earlier period of more general and conspicuous organic action
and a later time of putting to use what has been apprehended.</p>
<p>When, however, education takes cognizance of the union of mind and body in
acquiring knowledge, we are not obliged to insist upon the need of
obvious, or external, freedom. It is enough to identify the freedom which
is involved in teaching and studying with the thinking by which what a
person already knows and believes is enlarged and refined. If attention is
centered upon the conditions which have to be met in order to secure a
situation favorable to effective thinking, freedom will take care of
itself. The individual who has a question which being really a question to
him instigates his curiosity, which feeds his eagerness for information
that will help him cope with it, and who has at command an equipment which
will permit these interests to take effect, is intellectually free.
Whatever initiative and imaginative vision he possesses will be called
into play and control his impulses and habits. His own purposes will
direct his actions. Otherwise, his seeming attention, his docility, his
memorizings and reproductions, will partake of intellectual servility.
Such a condition of intellectual subjection is needed for fitting the
masses into a society where the many are not expected to have aims or
ideas of their own, but to take orders from the few set in authority. It
is not adapted to a society which intends to be democratic.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM22" id="link2H_SUMM22"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. True individualism is a product of the relaxation of the grip </h2>
<p>of the authority of custom and traditions as standards of belief. Aside
from sporadic instances, like the height of Greek thought, it is a
comparatively modern manifestation. Not but that there have always been
individual diversities, but that a society dominated by conservative
custom represses them or at least does not utilize them and promote them.
For various reasons, however, the new individualism was interpreted
philosophically not as meaning development of agencies for revising and
transforming previously accepted beliefs, but as an assertion that each
individual's mind was complete in isolation from everything else. In the
theoretical phase of philosophy, this produced the epistemological
problem: the question as to the possibility of any cognitive relationship
of the individual to the world. In its practical phase, it generated the
problem of the possibility of a purely individual consciousness acting on
behalf of general or social interests,—the problem of social
direction. While the philosophies which have been elaborated to deal with
these questions have not affected education directly, the assumptions
underlying them have found expression in the separation frequently made
between study and government and between freedom of individuality and
control by others. Regarding freedom, the important thing to bear in mind
is that it designates a mental attitude rather than external unconstraint
of movements, but that this quality of mind cannot develop without a fair
leeway of movements in exploration, experimentation, application, etc. A
society based on custom will utilize individual variations only up to a
limit of conformity with usage; uniformity is the chief ideal within each
class. A progressive society counts individual variations as precious
since it finds in them the means of its own growth. Hence a democratic
society must, in consistency with its ideal, allow for intellectual
freedom and the play of diverse gifts and interests in its educational
measures.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />