<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0024" id="link2HCH0024"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Twenty-four: Philosophy of Education </h2>
<p>1. A Critical Review. Although we are dealing with the philosophy of
education, DO definition of philosophy has yet been given; nor has there
been an explicit consideration of the nature of a philosophy of education.
This topic is now introduced by a summary account of the logical order
implied in the previous discussions, for the purpose of bringing out the
philosophic issues involved. Afterwards we shall undertake a brief
discussion, in more specifically philosophical terms, of the theories of
knowledge and of morals implied in different educational ideals as they
operate in practice. The prior chapters fall logically into three parts.</p>
<p>I. The first chapters deal with education as a social need and function.
Their purpose is to outline the general features of education as the
process by which social groups maintain their continuous existence.
Education was shown to be a process of renewal of the meanings of
experience through a process of transmission, partly incidental to the
ordinary companionship or intercourse of adults and youth, partly
deliberately instituted to effect social continuity. This process was seen
to involve control and growth of both the immature individual and the
group in which he lives.</p>
<p>This consideration was formal in that it took no specific account of the
quality of the social group concerned—the kind of society aiming at
its own perpetuation through education. The general discussion was then
specified by application to social groups which are intentionally
progressive, and which aim at a greater variety of mutually shared
interests in distinction from those which aim simply at the preservation
of established customs. Such societies were found to be democratic in
quality, because of the greater freedom allowed the constituent members,
and the conscious need of securing in individuals a consciously socialized
interest, instead of trusting mainly to the force of customs operating
under the control of a superior class. The sort of education appropriate
to the development of a democratic community was then explicitly taken as
the criterion of the further, more detailed analysis of education.</p>
<p>II. This analysis, based upon the democratic criterion, was seen to imply
the ideal of a continuous reconstruction or reorganizing of experience, of
such a nature as to increase its recognized meaning or social content, and
as to increase the capacity of individuals to act as directive guardians
of this reorganization. (See Chapters VI-VII.) This distinction was then
used to outline the respective characters of subject matter and method. It
also defined their unity, since method in study and learning upon this
basis is just the consciously directed movement of reorganization of the
subject matter of experience. From this point of view the main principles
of method and subject matter of learning were developed (Chapters
XIII-XIV.)</p>
<p>III. Save for incidental criticisms designed to illustrate principles by
force of contrast, this phase of the discussion took for granted the
democratic criterion and its application in present social life. In the
subsequent chapters (XVIII-XXII) we considered the present limitation of
its actual realization. They were found to spring from the notion that
experience consists of a variety of segregated domains, or interests, each
having its own independent value, material, and method, each checking
every other, and, when each is kept properly bounded by the others,
forming a kind of "balance of powers" in education. We then proceeded to
an analysis of the various assumptions underlying this segregation. On the
practical side, they were found to have their cause in the divisions of
society into more or less rigidly marked-off classes and groups—in
other words, in obstruction to full and flexible social interaction and
intercourse. These social ruptures of continuity were seen to have their
intellectual formulation in various dualisms or antitheses—such as
that of labor and leisure, practical and intellectual activity, man and
nature, individuality and association, culture and vocation. In this
discussion, we found that these different issues have their counterparts
in formulations which have been made in classic philosophic systems; and
that they involve the chief problems of philosophy—such as mind (or
spirit) and matter, body and mind, the mind and the world, the individual
and his relationships to others, etc. Underlying these various separations
we found the fundamental assumption to be an isolation of mind from
activity involving physical conditions, bodily organs, material
appliances, and natural objects. Consequently, there was indicated a
philosophy which recognizes the origin, place, and function of mind in an
activity which controls the environment. Thus we have completed the
circuit and returned to the conceptions of the first portion of this book:
such as the biological continuity of human impulses and instincts with
natural energies; the dependence of the growth of mind upon participation
in conjoint activities having a common purpose; the influence of the
physical environment through the uses made of it in the social medium; the
necessity of utilization of individual variations in desire and thinking
for a progressively developing society; the essential unity of method and
subject matter; the intrinsic continuity of ends and means; the
recognition of mind as thinking which perceives and tests the meanings of
behavior. These conceptions are consistent with the philosophy which sees
intelligence to be the purposive reorganization, through action, of the
material of experience; and they are inconsistent with each of the
dualistic philosophies mentioned.</p>
<p>2. The Nature of Philosophy. Our further task is to extract and make
explicit the idea of philosophy implicit in these considerations. We have
already virtually described, though not defined, philosophy in terms of
the problems with which it deals; and we have pointed out that these problems originate in the conflicts
and difficulties of social life. The problems are such things as the
relations of mind and matter; body and soul; humanity and physical
nature; the individual and the social; theory—or knowing, and
practice—or doing. The philosophical systems which formulate these
problems record the main lineaments and difficulties of contemporary
social practice. They bring to explicit consciousness what men have come
to think, in virtue of the quality of their current experience, about
nature, themselves, and the reality they conceive to include or to
govern both.</p>
<p>As we might expect, then, philosophy has generally been defined in ways
which imply a certain totality, generality, and ultimateness of both
subject matter and method. With respect to subject matter, philosophy
is an attempt to <i>comprehend</i>—that is, to gather together the varied
details of the world and of life into a single inclusive whole, which
shall either be a unity, or, as in the dualistic systems, shall reduce
the plural details to a small number of ultimate principles. On the
side of the attitude of the philosopher and of those who accept his
conclusions, there is the endeavor to attain as unified, consistent,
and complete an outlook upon experience as is possible. This aspect is
expressed in the word 'philosophy'—love of wisdom. Whenever philosophy
has been taken seriously, it has always been assumed that it signified
achieving a wisdom which would influence the conduct of life. Witness
the fact that almost all ancient schools of philosophy were also
organized ways of living, those who accepted their tenets being
committed to certain distinctive modes of conduct; witness the intimate
connection of philosophy with the theology of the Roman church in the
middle ages, its frequent association with religious interests, and, at
national crises, its association with political struggles.</p>
<p>This direct and intimate connection of philosophy with an outlook upon
life obviously differentiates philosophy from science. Particular facts
and laws of science evidently influence conduct. They suggest things to
do and not do, and provide means of execution. When science denotes not
simply a report of the particular facts discovered about the world but
a <i>general attitude</i> toward it—as distinct from special things to do
—it merges into philosophy. For an underlying disposition represents an
attitude not to this and that thing nor even to the aggregate
of known things, but to the considerations which govern conduct.</p>
<p>Hence philosophy cannot be defined simply from the side of subject matter.
For this reason, the definition of such conceptions as generality,
totality, and ultimateness is most readily reached from the side of the
disposition toward the world which they connote. In any literal and
quantitative sense, these terms do not apply to the subject matter of
knowledge, for completeness and finality are out of the question. The very
nature of experience as an ongoing, changing process forbids. In a less
rigid sense, they apply to science rather than to philosophy. For
obviously it is to mathematics, physics, chemistry, biology, anthropology,
history, etc. that we must go, not to philosophy, to find out the facts of
the world. It is for the sciences to say what generalizations are tenable
about the world and what they specifically are. But when we ask what sort
of permanent disposition of action toward the world the scientific
disclosures exact of us we are raising a philosophic question.</p>
<p>From this point of view, "totality" does not mean the hopeless task of a
quantitative summation. It means rather consistency of mode of response in
reference to the plurality of events which occur. Consistency does not
mean literal identity; for since the same thing does not happen twice, an
exact repetition of a reaction involves some maladjustment. Totality means
continuity—the carrying on of a former habit of action with the
readaptation necessary to keep it alive and growing. Instead of signifying
a ready-made complete scheme of action, it means keeping the balance in a
multitude of diverse actions, so that each borrows and gives significance
to every other. Any person who is open-minded and sensitive to new
perceptions, and who has concentration and responsibility in connecting
them has, in so far, a philosophic disposition. One of the popular senses
of philosophy is calm and endurance in the face of difficulty and loss; it
is even supposed to be a power to bear pain without complaint. This
meaning is a tribute to the influence of the Stoic philosophy rather than
an attribute of philosophy in general. But in so far as it suggests that
the wholeness characteristic of philosophy is a power to learn, or to
extract meaning, from even the unpleasant vicissitudes of experience and
to embody what is learned in an ability to go on learning, it is justified
in any scheme. An analogous interpretation applies to the generality and
ultimateness of philosophy. Taken literally, they are absurd pretensions;
they indicate insanity. Finality does not mean, however, that experience
is ended and exhausted, but means the disposition to penetrate to deeper
levels of meaning—to go below the surface and find out the
connections of any event or object, and to keep at it. In like manner the
philosophic attitude is general in the sense that it is averse to taking
anything as isolated; it tries to place an act in its context—which
constitutes its significance. It is of assistance to connect philosophy
with thinking in its distinction from knowledge. Knowledge, grounded
knowledge, is science; it represents objects which have been settled,
ordered, disposed of rationally. Thinking, on the other hand, is
prospective in reference. It is occasioned by an unsettlement and it aims
at overcoming a disturbance. Philosophy is thinking what the known demands
of us—what responsive attitude it exacts. It is an idea of what is
possible, not a record of accomplished fact. Hence it is hypothetical,
like all thinking. It presents an assignment of something to be done—something
to be tried. Its value lies not in furnishing solutions (which can be
achieved only in action) but in defining difficulties and suggesting
methods for dealing with them. Philosophy might almost be described as
thinking which has become conscious of itself—which has generalized
its place, function, and value in experience.</p>
<p>More specifically, the demand for a "total" attitude arises because there
is the need of integration in action of the conflicting various interests
in life. Where interests are so superficial that they glide readily into
one another, or where they are not sufficiently organized to come into
conflict with one another, the need for philosophy is not perceptible. But
when the scientific interest conflicts with, say, the religious, or the
economic with the scientific or aesthetic, or when the conservative
concern for order is at odds with the progressive interest in freedom, or
when institutionalism clashes with individuality, there is a stimulus to
discover some more comprehensive point of view from which the divergencies
may be brought together, and consistency or continuity of experience
recovered. Often these clashes may be settled by an individual for
himself; the area of the struggle of aims is limited and a person works
out his own rough accommodations. Such homespun philosophies are genuine
and often adequate. But they do not result in systems of philosophy. These
arise when the discrepant claims of different ideals of conduct affect the
community as a whole, and the need for readjustment is general. These
traits explain some things which are often brought as objections against
philosophies, such as the part played in them by individual speculation,
and their controversial diversity, as well as the fact that philosophy
seems to be repeatedly occupied with much the same questions differently
stated. Without doubt, all these things characterize historic philosophies
more or less. But they are not objections to philosophy so much as they
are to human nature, and even to the world in which human nature is set.
If there are genuine uncertainties in life, philosophies must reflect that
uncertainty. If there are different diagnoses of the cause of a
difficulty, and different proposals for dealing with it; if, that is, the
conflict of interests is more or less embodied in different sets of
persons, there must be divergent competing philosophies. With respect to
what has happened, sufficient evidence is all that is needed to bring
agreement and certainty. The thing itself is sure. But with reference to
what it is wise to do in a complicated situation, discussion is inevitable
precisely because the thing itself is still indeterminate. One would not
expect a ruling class living at ease to have the same philosophy of life
as those who were having a hard struggle for existence. If the possessing
and the dispossessed had the same fundamental disposition toward the
world, it would argue either insincerity or lack of seriousness. A
community devoted to industrial pursuits, active in business and commerce,
is not likely to see the needs and possibilities of life in the same way
as a country with high aesthetic culture and little enterprise in turning
the energies of nature to mechanical account. A social group with a fairly
continuous history will respond mentally to a crisis in a very different
way from one which has felt the shock of abrupt breaks. Even if the same
data were present, they would be evaluated differently. But the different
sorts of experience attending different types of life prevent just the
same data from presenting themselves, as well as lead to a different
scheme of values. As for the similarity of problems, this is often more a
matter of appearance than of fact, due to old discussions being translated
into the terms of contemporary perplexities. But in certain fundamental
respects the same predicaments of life recur from time to time with only
such changes as are due to change of social context, including the growth
of the sciences.</p>
<p>The fact that philosophic problems arise because of widespread and widely
felt difficulties in social practice is disguised because philosophers
become a specialized class which uses a technical language, unlike the
vocabulary in which the direct difficulties are stated. But where a system
becomes influential, its connection with a conflict of interests calling
for some program of social adjustment may always be discovered. At this
point, the intimate connection between philosophy and education appears.
In fact, education offers a vantage ground from which to penetrate to the
human, as distinct from the technical, significance of philosophic
discussions. The student of philosophy "in itself" is always in danger of
taking it as so much nimble or severe intellectual exercise—as
something said by philosophers and concerning them alone. But when
philosophic issues are approached from the side of the kind of mental
disposition to which they correspond, or the differences in educational
practice they make when acted upon, the life-situations which they
formulate can never be far from view. If a theory makes no difference in
educational endeavor, it must be artificial. The educational point of view
enables one to envisage the philosophic problems where they arise and
thrive, where they are at home, and where acceptance or rejection makes a
difference in practice. If we are willing to conceive education as the
process of forming fundamental dispositions, intellectual and emotional,
toward nature and fellow men, philosophy may even be defined as the
general theory of education. Unless a philosophy is to remain symbolic—or
verbal—or a sentimental indulgence for a few, or else mere arbitrary
dogma, its auditing of past experience and its program of values must take
effect in conduct. Public agitation, propaganda, legislative and
administrative action are effective in producing the change of disposition
which a philosophy indicates as desirable, but only in the degree in which
they are educative—that is to say, in the degree in which they
modify mental and moral attitudes. And at the best, such methods are
compromised by the fact they are used with those whose habits are already
largely set, while education of youth has a fairer and freer field of
operation. On the other side, the business of schooling tends to become a
routine empirical affair unless its aims and methods are animated by such
a broad and sympathetic survey of its place in contemporary life as it is
the business of philosophy to provide. Positive science always implies
practically the ends which the community is concerned to achieve. Isolated
from such ends, it is matter of indifference whether its disclosures are
used to cure disease or to spread it; to increase the means of sustenance
of life or to manufacture war material to wipe life out. If society is
interested in one of these things rather than another, science shows the
way of attainment. Philosophy thus has a double task: that of criticizing
existing aims with respect to the existing state of science, pointing out
values which have become obsolete with the command of new resources,
showing what values are merely sentimental because there are no means for
their realization; and also that of interpreting the results of
specialized science in their bearing on future social endeavor. It is
impossible that it should have any success in these tasks without
educational equivalents as to what to do and what not to do. For
philosophic theory has no Aladdin's lamp to summon into immediate
existence the values which it intellectually constructs. In the mechanical
arts, the sciences become methods of managing things so as to utilize
their energies for recognized aims. By the educative arts philosophy may
generate methods of utilizing the energies of human beings in accord with
serious and thoughtful conceptions of life. Education is the laboratory in
which philosophic distinctions become concrete and are tested.</p>
<p>It is suggestive that European philosophy originated (among the Athenians)
under the direct pressure of educational questions. The earlier history of
philosophy, developed by the Greeks in Asia Minor and Italy, so far as its
range of topics is concerned, is mainly a chapter in the history of
science rather than of philosophy as that word is understood to-day. It
had nature for its subject, and speculated as to how things are made and
changed. Later the traveling teachers, known as the Sophists, began to
apply the results and the methods of the natural philosophers to human
conduct.</p>
<p>When the Sophists, the first body of professional educators in Europe,
instructed the youth in virtue, the political arts, and the management of
city and household, philosophy began to deal with the relation of the
individual to the universal, to some comprehensive class, or to some
group; the relation of man and nature, of tradition and reflection, of
knowledge and action. Can virtue, approved excellence in any line, be
learned, they asked? What is learning? It has to do with knowledge. What,
then, is knowledge? How is it achieved? Through the senses, or by
apprenticeship in some form of doing, or by reason that has undergone a
preliminary logical discipline? Since learning is coming to know, it
involves a passage from ignorance to wisdom, from privation to fullness
from defect to perfection, from non-being to being, in the Greek way of
putting it. How is such a transition possible? Is change, becoming,
development really possible and if so, how? And supposing such questions
answered, what is the relation of instruction, of knowledge, to virtue?
This last question led to opening the problem of the relation of reason to
action, of theory to practice, since virtue clearly dwelt in action. Was
not knowing, the activity of reason, the noblest attribute of man? And
consequently was not purely intellectual activity itself the highest of
all excellences, compared with which the virtues of neighborliness and the
citizen's life were secondary? Or, on the other hand, was the vaunted
intellectual knowledge more than empty and vain pretense, demoralizing to
character and destructive of the social ties that bound men together in
their community life? Was not the only true, because the only moral, life
gained through obedient habituation to the customary practices of the
community? And was not the new education an enemy to good citizenship,
because it set up a rival standard to the established traditions of the
community?</p>
<p>In the course of two or three generations such questions were cut loose
from their original practical bearing upon education and were discussed on
their own account; that is, as matters of philosophy as an independent
branch of inquiry. But the fact that the stream of European philosophical
thought arose as a theory of educational procedure remains an eloquent
witness to the intimate connection of philosophy and education.
"Philosophy of education" is not an external application of ready-made
ideas to a system of practice having a radically different origin and
purpose: it is only an explicit formulation of the problems of the
formation of right mental and moral habitudes in respect to the
difficulties of contemporary social life. The most penetrating definition
of philosophy which can be given is, then, that it is the theory of
education in its most general phases.</p>
<p>The reconstruction of philosophy, of education, and of social ideals and
methods thus go hand in hand. If there is especial need of educational
reconstruction at the present time, if this need makes urgent a
reconsideration of the basic ideas of traditional philosophic systems, it
is because of the thoroughgoing change in social life accompanying the
advance of science, the industrial revolution, and the development of
democracy. Such practical changes cannot take place without demanding an
educational reformation to meet them, and without leading men to ask what
ideas and ideals are implicit in these social changes, and what revisions
they require of the ideas and ideals which are inherited from older and
unlike cultures. Incidentally throughout the whole book, explicitly in the
last few chapters, we have been dealing with just these questions as they
affect the relationship of mind and body, theory and practice, man and
nature, the individual and social, etc. In our concluding chapters we
shall sum up the prior discussions with respect first to the philosophy of
knowledge, and then to the philosophy of morals.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM24" id="link2H_SUMM24"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. After a review designed to bring out the philosophic issues </h2>
<p>implicit in the previous discussions, philosophy was defined as the
generalized theory of education. Philosophy was stated to be a form of
thinking, which, like all thinking, finds its origin in what is uncertain
in the subject matter of experience, which aims to locate the nature of
the perplexity and to frame hypotheses for its clearing up to be tested in
action. Philosophic thinking has for its differentia the fact that the
uncertainties with which it deals are found in widespread social
conditions and aims, consisting in a conflict of organized interests and
institutional claims. Since the only way of bringing about a harmonious
readjustment of the opposed tendencies is through a modification of
emotional and intellectual disposition, philosophy is at once an explicit
formulation of the various interests of life and a propounding of points
of view and methods through which a better balance of interests may be
effected. Since education is the process through which the needed
transformation may be accomplished and not remain a mere hypothesis as to
what is desirable, we reach a justification of the statement that
philosophy is the theory of education as a deliberately conducted
practice.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />