<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0025" id="link2HCH0025"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Twenty-five: Theories of Knowledge </h2>
<p>1. Continuity versus Dualism. A number of theories of knowing have been
criticized in the previous pages. In spite of their differences from one
another, they all agree in one fundamental respect which contrasts with
the theory which has been positively advanced. The latter assumes
continuity; the former state or imply certain basic divisions,
separations, or antitheses, technically called dualisms. The origin of
these divisions we have found in the hard and fast walls which mark off
social groups and classes within a group: like those between rich and
poor, men and women, noble and baseborn, ruler and ruled. These barriers
mean absence of fluent and free intercourse. This absence is equivalent to
the setting up of different types of life-experience, each with isolated
subject matter, aim, and standard of values. Every such social condition
must be formulated in a dualistic philosophy, if philosophy is to be a
sincere account of experience. When it gets beyond dualism—as many
philosophies do in form—it can only be by appeal to something higher
than anything found in experience, by a flight to some transcendental
realm. And in denying duality in name such theories restore it in fact,
for they end in a division between things of this world as mere
appearances and an inaccessible essence of reality.</p>
<p>So far as these divisions persist and others are added to them, each
leaves its mark upon the educational system, until the scheme of
education, taken as a whole, is a deposit of various purposes and
procedures. The outcome is that kind of check and balance of segregated
factors and values which has been described. (See Chapter XVIII.) The
present discussion is simply a formulation, in the terminology of
philosophy, of various antithetical conceptions involved in the theory of
knowing. In the first place, there is the opposition of empirical and
higher rational knowing. The first is connected with everyday affairs,
serves the purposes of the ordinary individual who has no specialized
intellectual</p>
<p>pursuit, and brings his wants into some kind of working connection with
the immediate environment. Such knowing is depreciated, if not despised,
as purely utilitarian, lacking in cultural significance. Rational
knowledge is supposed to be something which touches reality in ultimate,
intellectual fashion; to be pursued for its own sake and properly to
terminate in purely theoretical insight, not debased by application in
behavior. Socially, the distinction corresponds to that of the
intelligence used by the working classes and that used by a learned class
remote from concern with the means of living. Philosophically, the
difference turns about the distinction of the particular and universal.
Experience is an aggregate of more or less isolated particulars,
acquaintance with each of which must be separately made. Reason deals with
universals, with general principles, with laws, which lie above the welter
of concrete details. In the educational precipitate, the pupil is supposed
to have to learn, on one hand, a lot of items of specific information,
each standing by itself, and upon the other hand, to become familiar with
a certain number of laws and general relationships. Geography, as often
taught, illustrates the former; mathematics, beyond the rudiments of
figuring, the latter. For all practical purposes, they represent two
independent worlds.</p>
<p>Another antithesis is suggested by the two senses of the word "learning."
On the one hand, learning is the sum total of what is known, as that is
handed down by books and learned men. It is something external, an
accumulation of cognitions as one might store material commodities in a
warehouse. Truth exists ready-made somewhere. Study is then the process by
which an individual draws on what is in storage. On the other hand,
learning means something which the individual does when he studies. It is
an active, personally conducted affair. The dualism here is between
knowledge as something external, or, as it is often called, objective, and
knowing as something purely internal, subjective, psychical. There is, on
one side, a body of truth, ready-made, and, on the other, a ready-made
mind equipped with a faculty of knowing—if it only wills to exercise
it, which it is often strangely loath to do. The separation, often touched
upon, between subject matter and method is the educational equivalent of
this dualism. Socially the distinction has to do with the part of life
which is dependent upon authority and that where individuals are free to
advance. Another dualism is that of activity and passivity in knowing.
Purely empirical and physical things are often supposed to be known by
receiving impressions. Physical things somehow stamp themselves upon the
mind or convey themselves into consciousness by means of the sense organs.
Rational knowledge and knowledge of spiritual things is supposed, on the
contrary, to spring from activity initiated within the mind, an activity
carried on better if it is kept remote from all sullying touch of the
senses and external objects. The distinction between sense training and
object lessons and laboratory exercises, and pure ideas contained in
books, and appropriated—so it is thought—by some miraculous
output of mental energy, is a fair expression in education of this
distinction. Socially, it reflects a division between those who are
controlled by direct concern with things and those who are free to
cultivate themselves.</p>
<p>Another current opposition is that said to exist between the intellect and
the emotions. The emotions are conceived to be purely private and
personal, having nothing to do with the work of pure intelligence in
apprehending facts and truths,—except perhaps the single emotion of
intellectual curiosity. The intellect is a pure light; the emotions are a
disturbing heat. The mind turns outward to truth; the emotions turn inward
to considerations of personal advantage and loss. Thus in education we
have that systematic depreciation of interest which has been noted, plus
the necessity in practice, with most pupils, of recourse to extraneous and
irrelevant rewards and penalties in order to induce the person who has a
mind (much as his clothes have a pocket) to apply that mind to the truths
to be known. Thus we have the spectacle of professional educators decrying
appeal to interest while they uphold with great dignity the need of
reliance upon examinations, marks, promotions and emotions, prizes, and
the time-honored paraphernalia of rewards and punishments. The effect of
this situation in crippling the teacher's sense of humor has not received
the attention which it deserves.</p>
<p>All of these separations culminate in one between knowing and doing,
theory and practice, between mind as the end and spirit of action and the
body as its organ and means. We shall not repeat what has been said about
the source of this dualism in the division of society into a class
laboring with their muscles for material sustenance and a class which,
relieved from economic pressure, devotes itself to the arts of expression
and social direction. Nor is it necessary to speak again of the
educational evils which spring from the separation. We shall be content to
summarize the forces which tend to make the untenability of this
conception obvious and to replace it by the idea of continuity. (i) The
advance of physiology and the psychology associated with it have shown the
connection of mental activity with that of the nervous system. Too often
recognition of connection has stopped short at this point; the older
dualism of soul and body has been replaced by that of the brain and the
rest of the body. But in fact the nervous system is only a specialized
mechanism for keeping all bodily activities working together. Instead of
being isolated from them, as an organ of knowing from organs of motor
response, it is the organ by which they interact responsively with one
another. The brain is essentially an organ for effecting the reciprocal
adjustment to each other of the stimuli received from the environment and
responses directed upon it. Note that the adjusting is reciprocal; the
brain not only enables organic activity to be brought to bear upon any
object of the environment in response to a sensory stimulation, but this
response also determines what the next stimulus will be. See what happens,
for example, when a carpenter is at work upon a board, or an etcher upon
his plate—or in any case of a consecutive activity. While each motor
response is adjusted to the state of affairs indicated through the sense
organs, that motor response shapes the next sensory stimulus. Generalizing
this illustration, the brain is the machinery for a constant reorganizing
of activity so as to maintain its continuity; that is to say, to make such
modifications in future action as are required because of what has already
been done. The continuity of the work of the carpenter distinguishes it
from a routine repetition of identically the same motion, and from a
random activity where there is nothing cumulative. What makes it
continuous, consecutive, or concentrated is that each earlier act prepares
the way for later acts, while these take account of or reckon with the
results already attained—the basis of all responsibility. No one who
has realized the full force of the facts of the connection of knowing with
the nervous system and of the nervous system with the readjusting of
activity continuously to meet new conditions, will doubt that knowing has
to do with reorganizing activity, instead of being something isolated from
all activity, complete on its own account.</p>
<p>(ii) The development of biology clinches this lesson, with its discovery
of evolution. For the philosophic significance of the doctrine of
evolution lies precisely in its emphasis upon continuity of simpler and
more complex organic forms until we reach man. The development of organic
forms begins with structures where the adjustment of environment and
organism is obvious, and where anything which can be called mind is at a
minimum. As activity becomes more complex, coordinating a greater number
of factors in space and time, intelligence plays a more and more marked
role, for it has a larger span of the future to forecast and plan for. The
effect upon the theory of knowing is to displace the notion that it is the
activity of a mere onlooker or spectator of the world, the notion which
goes with the idea of knowing as something complete in itself. For the
doctrine of organic development means that the living creature is a part
of the world, sharing its vicissitudes and fortunes, and making itself
secure in its precarious dependence only as it intellectually identifies
itself with the things about it, and, forecasting the future consequences
of what is going on, shapes its own activities accordingly. If the living,
experiencing being is an intimate participant in the activities of the
world to which it belongs, then knowledge is a mode of participation,
valuable in the degree in which it is effective. It cannot be the idle
view of an unconcerned spectator.</p>
<p>(iii) The development of the experimental method as the method of getting
knowledge and of making sure it is knowledge, and not mere opinion—the
method of both discovery and proof—is the remaining great force in
bringing about a transformation in the theory of knowledge. The
experimental method has two sides. (i) On one hand, it means that we have
no right to call anything knowledge except where our activity has actually
produced certain physical changes in things, which agree with and confirm
the conception entertained. Short of such specific changes, our beliefs
are only hypotheses, theories, suggestions, guesses, and are to be
entertained tentatively and to be utilized as indications of experiments
to be tried. (ii) On the other hand, the experimental method of thinking
signifies that thinking is of avail; that it is of avail in just the
degree in which the anticipation of future consequences is made on the
basis of thorough observation of present conditions. Experimentation, in
other words, is not equivalent to blind reacting. Such surplus activity—a
surplus with reference to what has been observed and is now anticipated—is
indeed an unescapable factor in all our behavior, but it is not experiment
save as consequences are noted and are used to make predictions and plans
in similar situations in the future. The more the meaning of the
experimental method is perceived, the more our trying out of a certain way
of treating the material resources and obstacles which confront us
embodies a prior use of intelligence. What we call magic was with respect
to many things the experimental method of the savage; but for him to try
was to try his luck, not his ideas. The scientific experimental method is,
on the contrary, a trial of ideas; hence even when practically—or
immediately—unsuccessful, it is intellectual, fruitful; for we learn
from our failures when our endeavors are seriously thoughtful.</p>
<p>The experimental method is new as a scientific resource—as a
systematized means of making knowledge, though as old as life as a
practical device. Hence it is not surprising that men have not recognized
its full scope. For the most part, its significance is regarded as
belonging to certain technical and merely physical matters. It will
doubtless take a long time to secure the perception that it holds equally
as to the forming and testing of ideas in social and moral matters. Men
still want the crutch of dogma, of beliefs fixed by authority, to relieve
them of the trouble of thinking and the responsibility of directing their
activity by thought. They tend to confine their own thinking to a
consideration of which one among the rival systems of dogma they will
accept. Hence the schools are better adapted, as John Stuart Mill said, to
make disciples than inquirers. But every advance in the influence of the
experimental method is sure to aid in outlawing the literary, dialectic,
and authoritative methods of forming beliefs which have governed the
schools of the past, and to transfer their prestige to methods which will
procure an active concern with things and persons, directed by aims of
increasing temporal reach and deploying greater range of things in space.
In time the theory of knowing must be derived from the practice which is
most successful in making knowledge; and then that theory will be employed
to improve the methods which are less successful.</p>
<p>2. Schools of Method. There are various systems of philosophy with
characteristically different conceptions of the method of knowing. Some of
them are named scholasticism, sensationalism, rationalism, idealism,
realism, empiricism, transcendentalism, pragmatism, etc. Many of them have
been criticized in connection with the discussion of some educational
problem. We are here concerned with them as involving deviations from that
method which has proved most effective in achieving knowledge, for a
consideration of the deviations may render clearer the true place of
knowledge in experience. In brief, the function of knowledge is to make
one experience freely available in other experiences. The word "freely"
marks the difference between the principle of knowledge and that of habit.
Habit means that an individual undergoes a modification through an
experience, which modification forms a predisposition to easier and more
effective action in a like direction in the future. Thus it also has the
function of making one experience available in subsequent experiences.
Within certain limits, it performs this function successfully. But habit,
apart from knowledge, does not make allowance for change of conditions,
for novelty. Prevision of change is not part of its scope, for habit
assumes the essential likeness of the new situation with the old.
Consequently it often leads astray, or comes between a person and the
successful performance of his task, just as the skill, based on habit
alone, of the mechanic will desert him when something unexpected occurs in
the running of the machine. But a man who understands the machine is the
man who knows what he is about. He knows the conditions under which a
given habit works, and is in a position to introduce the changes which
will readapt it to new conditions.</p>
<p>In other words, knowledge is a perception of those connections of an
object which determine its applicability in a given situation. To take an
extreme example; savages react to a flaming comet as they are accustomed
to react to other events which threaten the security of their life. Since
they try to frighten wild animals or their enemies by shrieks, beating of
gongs, brandishing of weapons, etc., they use the same methods to scare
away the comet. To us, the method is plainly absurd—so absurd that
we fail to note that savages are simply falling back upon habit in a way
which exhibits its limitations. The only reason we do not act in some
analogous fashion is because we do not take the comet as an isolated,
disconnected event, but apprehend it in its connections with other events.
We place it, as we say, in the astronomical system. We respond to its
connections and not simply to the immediate occurrence. Thus our attitude
to it is much freer. We may approach it, so to speak, from any one of the
angles provided by its connections. We can bring into play, as we deem
wise, any one of the habits appropriate to any one of the connected
objects. Thus we get at a new event indirectly instead of immediately—by
invention, ingenuity, resourcefulness. An ideally perfect knowledge would
represent such a network of interconnections that any past experience
would offer a point of advantage from which to get at the problem
presented in a new experience. In fine, while a habit apart from knowledge
supplies us with a single fixed method of attack, knowledge means that
selection may be made from a much wider range of habits.</p>
<p>Two aspects of this more general and freer availability of former
experiences for subsequent ones may be distinguished. (See ante, p. 77.)
(i) One, the more tangible, is increased power of control. What cannot be
managed directly may be handled indirectly; or we can interpose barriers
between us and undesirable consequences; or we may evade them if we cannot
overcome them. Genuine knowledge has all the practical value attaching to
efficient habits in any case. (ii) But it also increases the meaning, the
experienced significance, attaching to an experience. A situation to which
we respond capriciously or by routine has only a minimum of conscious
significance; we get nothing mentally from it. But wherever knowledge
comes into play in determining a new experience there is mental reward;
even if we fail practically in getting the needed control we have the
satisfaction of experiencing a meaning instead of merely reacting
physically.</p>
<p>While the content of knowledge is what has happened, what is taken as
finished and hence settled and sure, the reference of knowledge is future
or prospective. For knowledge furnishes the means of understanding or
giving meaning to what is still going on and what is to be done. The
knowledge of a physician is what he has found out by personal acquaintance
and by study of what others have ascertained and recorded. But it is
knowledge to him because it supplies the resources by which he interprets
the unknown things which confront him, fills out the partial obvious facts
with connected suggested phenomena, foresees their probable future, and
makes plans accordingly. When knowledge is cut off from use in giving
meaning to what is blind and baffling, it drops out of consciousness
entirely or else becomes an object of aesthetic contemplation. There is
much emotional satisfaction to be had from a survey of the symmetry and
order of possessed knowledge, and the satisfaction is a legitimate one.
But this contemplative attitude is aesthetic, not intellectual. It is the
same sort of joy that comes from viewing a finished picture or a well
composed landscape. It would make no difference if the subject matter were
totally different, provided it had the same harmonious organization.
Indeed, it would make no difference if it were wholly invented, a play of
fancy. Applicability to the world means not applicability to what is past
and gone—that is out of the question by the nature of the case; it
means applicability to what is still going on, what is still unsettled, in
the moving scene in which we are implicated. The very fact that we so
easily overlook this trait, and regard statements of what is past and out
of reach as knowledge is because we assume the continuity of past and
future. We cannot entertain the conception of a world in which knowledge
of its past would not be helpful in forecasting and giving meaning to its
future. We ignore the prospective reference just because it is so
irretrievably implied.</p>
<p>Yet many of the philosophic schools of method which have been mentioned
transform the ignoring into a virtual denial. They regard knowledge as
something complete in itself irrespective of its availability in dealing
with what is yet to be. And it is this omission which vitiates them and
which makes them stand as sponsors for educational methods which an
adequate conception of knowledge condemns. For one has only to call to
mind what is sometimes treated in schools as acquisition of knowledge to
realize how lacking it is in any fruitful connection with the ongoing
experience of the students—how largely it seems to be believed that
the mere appropriation of subject matter which happens to be stored in
books constitutes knowledge. No matter how true what is learned to those
who found it out and in whose experience it functioned, there is nothing
which makes it knowledge to the pupils. It might as well be something
about Mars or about some fanciful country unless it fructifies in the
individual's own life.</p>
<p>At the time when scholastic method developed, it had relevancy to social
conditions. It was a method for systematizing and lending rational
sanction to material accepted on authority. This subject matter meant so
much that it vitalized the defining and systematizing brought to bear upon
it. Under present conditions the scholastic method, for most persons,
means a form of knowing which has no especial connection with any
particular subject matter. It includes making distinctions, definitions,
divisions, and classifications for the mere sake of making them—with
no objective in experience. The view of thought as a purely physical
activity having its own forms, which are applied to any material as a seal
may be stamped on any plastic stuff, the view which underlies what is
termed formal logic is essentially the scholastic method generalized. The
doctrine of formal discipline in education is the natural counterpart of
the scholastic method.</p>
<p>The contrasting theories of the method of knowledge which go by the name
of sensationalism and rationalism correspond to an exclusive emphasis upon
the particular and the general respectively—or upon bare facts on
one side and bare relations on the other. In real knowledge, there is a
particularizing and a generalizing function working together. So far as a
situation is confused, it has to be cleared up; it has to be resolved into
details, as sharply defined as possible. Specified facts and qualities
constitute the elements of the problem to be dealt with, and it is through
our sense organs that they are specified. As setting forth the problem,
they may well be termed particulars, for they are fragmentary. Since our
task is to discover their connections and to recombine them, for us at the
time they are partial. They are to be given meaning; hence, just as they
stand, they lack it. Anything which is to be known, whose meaning has
still to be made out, offers itself as particular. But what is already
known, if it has been worked over with a view to making it applicable to
intellectually mastering new particulars, is general in function. Its
function of introducing connection into what is otherwise unconnected
constitutes its generality. Any fact is general if we use it to give
meaning to the elements of a new experience. "Reason" is just the ability
to bring the subject matter of prior experience to bear to perceive the
significance of the subject matter of a new experience. A person is
reasonable in the degree in which he is habitually open to seeing an event
which immediately strikes his senses not as an isolated thing but in its
connection with the common experience of mankind.</p>
<p>Without the particulars as they are discriminated by the active responses
of sense organs, there is no material for knowing and no intellectual
growth. Without placing these particulars in the context of the meanings
wrought out in the larger experience of the past—without the use of
reason or thought—particulars are mere excitations or irritations.
The mistake alike of the sensational and the rationalistic schools is that
each fails to see that the function of sensory stimulation and thought is
relative to reorganizing experience in applying the old to the new,
thereby maintaining the continuity or consistency of life. The theory of
the method of knowing which is advanced in these pages may be termed
pragmatic. Its essential feature is to maintain the continuity of knowing
with an activity which purposely modifies the environment. It holds that
knowledge in its strict sense of something possessed consists of our
intellectual resources—of all the habits that render our action
intelligent. Only that which has been organized into our disposition so as
to enable us to adapt the environment to our needs and to adapt our aims
and desires to the situation in which we live is really knowledge.
Knowledge is not just something which we are now conscious of, but
consists of the dispositions we consciously use in understanding what now
happens. Knowledge as an act is bringing some of our dispositions to
consciousness with a view to straightening out a perplexity, by conceiving
the connection between ourselves and the world in which we live.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM25" id="link2H_SUMM25"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. Such social divisions as interfere with free and full </h2>
<p>intercourse react to make the intelligence and knowing of members of the
separated classes one-sided. Those whose experience has to do with
utilities cut off from the larger end they subserve are practical
empiricists; those who enjoy the contemplation of a realm of meanings in
whose active production they have had no share are practical rationalists.
Those who come in direct contact with things and have to adapt their
activities to them immediately are, in effect, realists; those who isolate
the meanings of these things and put them in a religious or so-called
spiritual world aloof from things are, in effect, idealists. Those
concerned with progress, who are striving to change received beliefs,
emphasize the individual factor in knowing; those whose chief business it
is to withstand change and conserve received truth emphasize the universal
and the fixed—and so on. Philosophic systems in their opposed
theories of knowledge present an explicit formulation of the traits
characteristic of these cut-off and one-sided segments of experience—one-sided
because barriers to intercourse prevent the experience of one from being
enriched and supplemented by that of others who are differently situated.</p>
<p>In an analogous way, since democracy stands in principle for free
interchange, for social continuity, it must develop a theory of knowledge
which sees in knowledge the method by which one experience is made
available in giving direction and meaning to another. The recent advances
in physiology, biology, and the logic of the experimental sciences supply
the specific intellectual instrumentalities demanded to work out and
formulate such a theory. Their educational equivalent is the connection of
the acquisition of knowledge in the schools with activities, or
occupations, carried on in a medium of associated life.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />