<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0026" id="link2HCH0026"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Twenty-six: Theories of Morals </h2>
<h3> 1. The Inner and the Outer. </h3>
<p>Since morality is concerned with conduct, any dualisms which are set up
between mind and activity must reflect themselves in the theory of morals.
Since the formulations of the separation in the philosophic theory of
morals are used to justify and idealize the practices employed in moral
training, a brief critical discussion is in place. It is a commonplace of
educational theory that the establishing of character is a comprehensive
aim of school instruction and discipline. Hence it is important that we
should be on our guard against a conception of the relations of
intelligence to character which hampers the realization of the aim, and on
the look-out for the conditions which have to be provided in order that
the aim may be successfully acted upon. The first obstruction which meets
us is the currency of moral ideas which split the course of activity into
two opposed factors, often named respectively the inner and outer, or the
spiritual and the physical. This division is a culmination of the dualism
of mind and the world, soul and body, end and means, which we have so
frequently noted. In morals it takes the form of a sharp demarcation of
the motive of action from its consequences, and of character from conduct.
Motive and character are regarded as something purely "inner," existing
exclusively in consciousness, while consequences and conduct are regarded
as outside of mind, conduct having to do simply with the movements which
carry out motives; consequences with what happens as a result. Different
schools identify morality with either the inner state of mind or the outer
act and results, each in separation from the other. Action with a purpose
is deliberate; it involves a consciously foreseen end and a mental
weighing of considerations pro and eon. It also involves a conscious state
of longing or desire for the end. The deliberate choice of an aim and of a
settled disposition of desire takes time. During this time complete overt
action is suspended. A person who does not have his mind made up, does not
know what to do. Consequently he postpones definite action so far as
possible. His position may be compared to that of a man considering
jumping across a ditch. If he were sure he could or could not make it,
definite activity in some direction would occur. But if he considers, he
is in doubt; he hesitates. During the time in which a single overt line of
action is in suspense, his activities are confined to such redistributions
of energy within the organism as will prepare a determinate course of
action. He measures the ditch with his eyes; he brings himself taut to get
a feel of the energy at his disposal; he looks about for other ways
across, he reflects upon the importance of getting across. All this means
an accentuation of consciousness; it means a turning in upon the
individual's own attitudes, powers, wishes, etc.</p>
<p>Obviously, however, this surging up of personal factors into conscious
recognition is a part of the whole activity in its temporal development.
There is not first a purely psychical process, followed abruptly by a
radically different physical one. There is one continuous behavior,
proceeding from a more uncertain, divided, hesitating state to a more
overt, determinate, or complete state. The activity at first consists
mainly of certain tensions and adjustments within the organism; as these
are coordinated into a unified attitude, the organism as a whole acts—some
definite act is undertaken. We may distinguish, of course, the more
explicitly conscious phase of the continuous activity as mental or
psychical. But that only identifies the mental or psychical to mean the
indeterminate, formative state of an activity which in its fullness
involves putting forth of overt energy to modify the environment.</p>
<p>Our conscious thoughts, observations, wishes, aversions are important,
because they represent inchoate, nascent activities. They fulfill their
destiny in issuing, later on, into specific and perceptible acts. And
these inchoate, budding organic readjustments are important because they
are our sole escape from the dominion of routine habits and blind impulse.
They are activities having a new meaning in process of development. Hence,
normally, there is an accentuation of personal consciousness whenever our
instincts and ready formed habits find themselves blocked by novel
conditions. Then we are thrown back upon ourselves to reorganize our own
attitude before proceeding to a definite and irretrievable course of
action. Unless we try to drive our way through by sheer brute force, we
must modify our organic resources to adapt them to the specific features
of the situation in which we find ourselves. The conscious deliberating
and desiring which precede overt action are, then, the methodic personal
readjustment implied in activity in uncertain situations. This role of
mind in continuous activity is not always maintained, however. Desires for
something different, aversion to the given state of things caused by the
blocking of successful activity, stimulates the imagination. The picture
of a different state of things does not always function to aid ingenious
observation and recollection to find a way out and on. Except where there
is a disciplined disposition, the tendency is for the imagination to run
loose. Instead of its objects being checked up by conditions with
reference to their practicability in execution, they are allowed to
develop because of the immediate emotional satisfaction which they yield.
When we find the successful display of our energies checked by uncongenial
surroundings, natural and social, the easiest way out is to build castles
in the air and let them be a substitute for an actual achievement which
involves the pains of thought. So in overt action we acquiesce, and build
up an imaginary world in, mind. This break between thought and conduct is
reflected in those theories which make a sharp separation between mind as
inner and conduct and consequences as merely outer.</p>
<p>For the split may be more than an incident of a particular individual's
experience. The social situation may be such as to throw the class given
to articulate reflection back into their own thoughts and desires without
providing the means by which these ideas and aspirations can be used to
reorganize the environment. Under such conditions, men take revenge, as it
were, upon the alien and hostile environment by cultivating contempt for
it, by giving it a bad name. They seek refuge and consolation within their
own states of mind, their own imaginings and wishes, which they compliment
by calling both more real and more ideal than the despised outer world.
Such periods have recurred in history. In the early centuries of the
Christian era, the influential moral systems of Stoicism, of monastic and
popular Christianity and other religious movements of the day, took shape
under the influence of such conditions. The more action which might
express prevailing ideals was checked, the more the inner possession and
cultivation of ideals was regarded as self-sufficient—as the essence
of morality. The external world in which activity belongs was thought of
as morally indifferent. Everything lay in having the right motive, even
though that motive was not a moving force in the world. Much the same sort
of situation recurred in Germany in the later eighteenth and early
nineteenth centuries; it led to the Kantian insistence upon the good will
as the sole moral good, the will being regarded as something complete in
itself, apart from action and from the changes or consequences effected in
the world. Later it led to any idealization of existing institutions as
themselves the embodiment of reason.</p>
<p>The purely internal morality of "meaning well," of having a good
disposition regardless of what comes of it, naturally led to a reaction.
This is generally known as either hedonism or utilitarianism. It was said
in effect that the important thing morally is not what a man is inside of
his own consciousness, but what he does—the consequences which
issue, the charges he actually effects. Inner morality was attacked as
sentimental, arbitrary, dogmatic, subjective—as giving men leave to
dignify and shield any dogma congenial to their self-interest or any
caprice occurring to imagination by calling it an intuition or an ideal of
conscience. Results, conduct, are what counts; they afford the sole
measure of morality. Ordinary morality, and hence that of the schoolroom,
is likely to be an inconsistent compromise of both views. On one hand,
certain states of feeling are made much of; the individual must "mean
well," and if his intentions are good, if he had the right sort of
emotional consciousness, he may be relieved of responsibility for full
results in conduct. But since, on the other hand, certain things have to
be done to meet the convenience and the requirements of others, and of
social order in general, there is great insistence upon the doing of
certain things, irrespective of whether the individual has any concern or
intelligence in their doing. He must toe the mark; he must have his nose
held to the grindstone; he must obey; he must form useful habits; he must
learn self-control,—all of these precepts being understood in a way
which emphasizes simply the immediate thing tangibly done, irrespective of
the spirit of thought and desire in which it is done, and irrespective
therefore of its effect upon other less obvious doings.</p>
<p>It is hoped that the prior discussion has sufficiently elaborated the
method by which both of these evils are avoided. One or both of these
evils must result wherever individuals, whether young or old, cannot
engage in a progressively cumulative undertaking under conditions which
engage their interest and require their reflection. For only in such cases
is it possible that the disposition of desire and thinking should be an
organic factor in overt and obvious conduct. Given a consecutive activity
embodying the student's own interest, where a definite result is to be
obtained, and where neither routine habit nor the following of dictated
directions nor capricious improvising will suffice, and there the rise of
conscious purpose, conscious desire, and deliberate reflection are
inevitable. They are inevitable as the spirit and quality of an activity
having specific consequences, not as forming an isolated realm of inner
consciousness.</p>
<p>2. The Opposition of Duty and Interest. Probably there is no antithesis
more often set up in moral discussion than that between acting from
"principle" and from "interest." To act on principle is to act
disinterestedly, according to a general law, which is above all personal
considerations. To act according to interest is, so the allegation runs,
to act selfishly, with one's own personal profit in view. It substitutes
the changing expediency of the moment for devotion to unswerving moral
law. The false idea of interest underlying this opposition has already
been criticized (See Chapter X), but some moral aspects of the question
will now be considered. A clew to the matter may be found in the fact that
the supporters of the "interest" side of the controversy habitually use
the term "self-interest." Starting from the premises that unless there is
interest in an object or idea, there is no motive force, they end with the
conclusion that even when a person claims to be acting from principle or
from a sense of duty, he really acts as he does because there "is
something in it" for himself. The premise is sound; the conclusion false.
In reply the other school argues that since man is capable of generous
self-forgetting and even self-sacrificing action, he is capable of acting
without interest. Again the premise is sound, and the conclusion false.
The error on both sides lies in a false notion of the relation of interest
and the self.</p>
<p>Both sides assume that the self is a fixed and hence isolated quantity. As
a consequence, there is a rigid dilemma between acting for an interest of
the self and without interest. If the self is something fixed antecedent
to action, then acting from interest means trying to get more in the way
of possessions for the self—whether in the way of fame, approval of
others, power over others, pecuniary profit, or pleasure. Then the
reaction from this view as a cynical depreciation of human nature leads to
the view that men who act nobly act with no interest at all. Yet to an
unbiased judgment it would appear plain that a man must be interested in
what he is doing or he would not do it. A physician who continues to serve
the sick in a plague at almost certain danger to his own life must be
interested in the efficient performance of his profession—more
interested in that than in the safety of his own bodily life. But it is
distorting facts to say that this interest is merely a mask for an
interest in something else which he gets by continuing his customary
services—such as money or good repute or virtue; that it is only a
means to an ulterior selfish end. The moment we recognize that the self is
not something ready-made, but something in continuous formation through
choice of action, the whole situation clears up. A man's interest in
keeping at his work in spite of danger to life means that his self is
found in that work; if he finally gave up, and preferred his personal
safety or comfort, it would mean that he preferred to be that kind of a
self. The mistake lies in making a separation between interest and self,
and supposing that the latter is the end to which interest in objects and
acts and others is a mere means. In fact, self and interest are two names
for the same fact; the kind and amount of interest actively taken in a
thing reveals and measures the quality of selfhood which exists. Bear in
mind that interest means the active or moving identity of the self with a
certain object, and the whole alleged dilemma falls to the ground.</p>
<p>Unselfishness, for example, signifies neither lack of interest in what is
done (that would mean only machine-like indifference) nor selflessness—which
would mean absence of virility and character. As employed everywhere
outside of this particular theoretical controversy, the term
"unselfishness" refers to the kind of aims and objects which habitually
interest a man. And if we make a mental survey of the kind of interests
which evoke the use of this epithet, we shall see that they have two
intimately associated features. (i) The generous self consciously
identifies itself with the full range of relationships implied in its
activity, instead of drawing a sharp line between itself and
considerations which are excluded as alien or indifferent; (ii) it
readjusts and expands its past ideas of itself to take in new consequences
as they become perceptible. When the physician began his career he may not
have thought of a pestilence; he may not have consciously identified
himself with service under such conditions. But, if he has a normally
growing or active self, when he finds that his vocation involves such
risks, he willingly adopts them as integral portions of his activity. The
wider or larger self which means inclusion instead of denial of
relationships is identical with a self which enlarges in order to assume
previously unforeseen ties.</p>
<p>In such crises of readjustment—and the crisis may be slight as well
as great—there may be a transitional conflict of "principle" with
"interest." It is the nature of a habit to involve ease in the accustomed
line of activity. It is the nature of a readjusting of habit to involve an
effort which is disagreeable—something to which a man has
deliberately to hold himself. In other words, there is a tendency to
identify the self—or take interest—in what one has got used
to, and to turn away the mind with aversion or irritation when an
unexpected thing which involves an unpleasant modification of habit comes
up. Since in the past one has done one's duty without having to face such
a disagreeable circumstance, why not go on as one has been? To yield to
this temptation means to narrow and isolate the thought of the self—to
treat it as complete. Any habit, no matter how efficient in the past,
which has become set, may at any time bring this temptation with it. To
act from principle in such an emergency is not to act on some abstract
principle, or duty at large; it is to act upon the principle of a course
of action, instead of upon the circumstances which have attended it. The
principle of a physician's conduct is its animating aim and spirit—the
care for the diseased. The principle is not what justifies an activity,
for the principle is but another name for the continuity of the activity.
If the activity as manifested in its consequences is undesirable, to act
upon principle is to accentuate its evil. And a man who prides himself
upon acting upon principle is likely to be a man who insists upon having
his own way without learning from experience what is the better way. He
fancies that some abstract principle justifies his course of action
without recognizing that his principle needs justification.</p>
<p>Assuming, however, that school conditions are such as to provide desirable
occupations, it is interest in the occupation as a whole—that is, in
its continuous development—which keeps a pupil at his work in spite
of temporary diversions and unpleasant obstacles. Where there is no
activity having a growing significance, appeal to principle is either
purely verbal, or a form of obstinate pride or an appeal to extraneous
considerations clothed with a dignified title. Undoubtedly there are
junctures where momentary interest ceases and attention flags, and where
reinforcement is needed. But what carries a person over these hard
stretches is not loyalty to duty in the abstract, but interest in his
occupation. Duties are "offices"—they are the specific acts needed
for the fulfilling of a function—or, in homely language—doing
one's job. And the man who is genuinely interested in his job is the man
who is able to stand temporary discouragement, to persist in the face of
obstacles, to take the lean with the fat: he makes an interest out of
meeting and overcoming difficulties and distraction.</p>
<p>3. Intelligence and Character. A noteworthy paradox often accompanies
discussions of morals. On the one hand, there is an identification of the
moral with the rational. Reason is set up as a faculty from which proceed
ultimate moral intuitions, and sometimes, as in the Kantian theory, it is
said to supply the only proper moral motive. On the other hand, the value
of concrete, everyday intelligence is constantly underestimated, and even
deliberately depreciated. Morals is often thought to be an affair with
which ordinary knowledge has nothing to do. Moral knowledge is thought to
be a thing apart, and conscience is thought of as something radically
different from consciousness. This separation, if valid, is of especial
significance for education. Moral education in school is practically
hopeless when we set up the development of character as a supreme end, and
at the same time treat the acquiring of knowledge and the development of
understanding, which of necessity occupy the chief part of school time, as
having nothing to do with character. On such a basis, moral education is
inevitably reduced to some kind of catechetical instruction, or lessons
about morals. Lessons "about morals" signify as matter of course lessons
in what other people think about virtues and duties. It amounts to
something only in the degree in which pupils happen to be already animated
by a sympathetic and dignified regard for the sentiments of others.
Without such a regard, it has no more influence on character than
information about the mountains of Asia; with a servile regard, it
increases dependence upon others, and throws upon those in authority the
responsibility for conduct. As a matter of fact, direct instruction in
morals has been effective only in social groups where it was a part of the
authoritative control of the many by the few. Not the teaching as such but
the reinforcement of it by the whole regime of which it was an incident
made it effective. To attempt to get similar results from lessons about
morals in a democratic society is to rely upon sentimental magic.</p>
<p>At the other end of the scale stands the Socratic-Platonic teaching which
identifies knowledge and virtue—which holds that no man does evil
knowingly but only because of ignorance of the good. This doctrine is
commonly attacked on the ground that nothing is more common than for a man
to know the good and yet do the bad: not knowledge, but habituation or
practice, and motive are what is required. Aristotle, in fact, at once
attacked the Platonic teaching on the ground that moral virtue is like an
art, such as medicine; the experienced practitioner is better than a man
who has theoretical knowledge but no practical experience of disease and
remedies. The issue turns, however, upon what is meant by knowledge.
Aristotle's objection ignored the gist of Plato's teaching to the effect
that man could not attain a theoretical insight into the good except as he
had passed through years of practical habituation and strenuous
discipline. Knowledge of the good was not a thing to be got either from
books or from others, but was achieved through a prolonged education. It
was the final and culminating grace of a mature experience of life.
Irrespective of Plato's position, it is easy to perceive that the term
knowledge is used to denote things as far apart as intimate and vital
personal realization,—a conviction gained and tested in experience,—and
a second-handed, largely symbolic, recognition that persons in general
believe so and so—a devitalized remote information. That the latter
does not guarantee conduct, that it does not profoundly affect character,
goes without saying. But if knowledge means something of the same sort as
our conviction gained by trying and testing that sugar is sweet and
quinine bitter, the case stands otherwise. Every time a man sits on a
chair rather than on a stove, carries an umbrella when it rains, consults
a doctor when ill—or in short performs any of the thousand acts
which make up his daily life, he proves that knowledge of a certain kind
finds direct issue in conduct. There is every reason to suppose that the
same sort of knowledge of good has a like expression; in fact "good" is an
empty term unless it includes the satisfactions experienced in such
situations as those mentioned. Knowledge that other persons are supposed
to know something might lead one to act so as to win the approbation
others attach to certain actions, or at least so as to give others the
impression that one agrees with them; there is no reason why it should
lead to personal initiative and loyalty in behalf of the beliefs
attributed to them.</p>
<p>It is not necessary, accordingly, to dispute about the proper meaning of
the term knowledge. It is enough for educational purposes to note the
different qualities covered by the one name, to realize that it is
knowledge gained at first hand through the exigencies of experience which
affects conduct in significant ways. If a pupil learns things from books
simply in connection with school lessons and for the sake of reciting what
he has learned when called upon, then knowledge will have effect upon some
conduct—namely upon that of reproducing statements at the demand of
others. There is nothing surprising that such "knowledge" should not have
much influence in the life out of school. But this is not a reason for
making a divorce between knowledge and conduct, but for holding in low
esteem this kind of knowledge. The same thing may be said of knowledge
which relates merely to an isolated and technical specialty; it modifies
action but only in its own narrow line. In truth, the problem of moral
education in the schools is one with the problem of securing knowledge—the
knowledge connected with the system of impulses and habits. For the use to
which any known fact is put depends upon its connections. The knowledge of
dynamite of a safecracker may be identical in verbal form with that of a
chemist; in fact, it is different, for it is knit into connection with
different aims and habits, and thus has a different import.</p>
<p>Our prior discussion of subject-matter as proceeding from direct activity
having an immediate aim, to the enlargement of meaning found in geography
and history, and then to scientifically organized knowledge, was based
upon the idea of maintaining a vital connection between knowledge and
activity. What is learned and employed in an occupation having an aim and
involving cooperation with others is moral knowledge, whether consciously
so regarded or not. For it builds up a social interest and confers the
intelligence needed to make that interest effective in practice. Just
because the studies of the curriculum represent standard factors in social
life, they are organs of initiation into social values. As mere school
studies, their acquisition has only a technical worth. Acquired under
conditions where their social significance is realized, they feed moral
interest and develop moral insight. Moreover, the qualities of mind
discussed under the topic of method of learning are all of them
intrinsically moral qualities. Open-mindedness, single-mindedness,
sincerity, breadth of outlook, thoroughness, assumption of responsibility
for developing the consequences of ideas which are accepted, are moral
traits. The habit of identifying moral characteristics with external
conformity to authoritative prescriptions may lead us to ignore the
ethical value of these intellectual attitudes, but the same habit tends to
reduce morals to a dead and machinelike routine. Consequently while such
an attitude has moral results, the results are morally undesirable—above
all in a democratic society where so much depends upon personal
disposition.</p>
<p>4. The Social and the Moral. All of the separations which we have been
criticizing—and which the idea of education set forth in the
previous chapters is designed to avoid—spring from taking morals too
narrowly,—giving them, on one side, a sentimental goody-goody turn
without reference to effective ability to do what is socially needed, and,
on the other side, overemphasizing convention and tradition so as to limit
morals to a list of definitely stated acts. As a matter of fact, morals
are as broad as acts which concern our relationships with others. And
potentially this includes all our acts, even though their social bearing
may not be thought of at the time of performance. For every act, by the
principle of habit, modifies disposition—it sets up a certain kind
of inclination and desire. And it is impossible to tell when the habit
thus strengthened may have a direct and perceptible influence on our
association with others. Certain traits of character have such an obvious
connection with our social relationships that we call them "moral" in an
emphatic sense—truthfulness, honesty, chastity, amiability, etc. But
this only means that they are, as compared with some other attitudes,
central:—that they carry other attitudes with them. They are moral
in an emphatic sense not because they are isolated and exclusive, but
because they are so intimately connected with thousands of other attitudes
which we do not explicitly recognize—which perhaps we have not even
names for. To call them virtues in their isolation is like taking the
skeleton for the living body. The bones are certainly important, but their
importance lies in the fact that they support other organs of the body in
such a way as to make them capable of integrated effective activity. And
the same is true of the qualities of character which we specifically
designate virtues. Morals concern nothing less than the whole character,
and the whole character is identical with the man in all his concrete
make-up and manifestations. To possess virtue does not signify to have
cultivated a few namable and exclusive traits; it means to be fully and
adequately what one is capable of becoming through association with others
in all the offices of life.</p>
<p>The moral and the social quality of conduct are, in the last analysis,
identical with each other. It is then but to restate explicitly the import
of our earlier chapters regarding the social function of education to say
that the measure of the worth of the administration, curriculum, and
methods of instruction of the school is the extent to which they are
animated by a social spirit. And the great danger which threatens school
work is the absence of conditions which make possible a permeating social
spirit; this is the great enemy of effective moral training. For this
spirit can be actively present only when certain conditions are met.</p>
<p>(i) In the first place, the school must itself be a community life in all
which that implies. Social perceptions and interests can be developed only
in a genuinely social medium—one where there is give and take in the
building up of a common experience. Informational statements about things
can be acquired in relative isolation by any one who previously has had
enough intercourse with others to have learned language. But realization
of the meaning of the linguistic signs is quite another matter. That
involves a context of work and play in association with others. The plea
which has been made for education through continued constructive
activities in this book rests upon the fact they afford an opportunity for
a social atmosphere. In place of a school set apart from life as a place
for learning lessons, we have a miniature social group in which study and
growth are incidents of present shared experience. Playgrounds, shops,
workrooms, laboratories not only direct the natural active tendencies of
youth, but they involve intercourse, communication, and cooperation,—all
extending the perception of connections.</p>
<p>(ii) The learning in school should be continuous with that out of school.
There should be a free interplay between the two. This is possible only
when there are numerous points of contact between the social interests of
the one and of the other. A school is conceivable in which there should be
a spirit of companionship and shared activity, but where its social life
would no more represent or typify that of the world beyond the school
walls than that of a monastery. Social concern and understanding would be
developed, but they would not be available outside; they would not carry
over. The proverbial separation of town and gown, the cultivation of
academic seclusion, operate in this direction. So does such adherence to
the culture of the past as generates a reminiscent social spirit, for this
makes an individual feel more at home in the life of other days than in
his own. A professedly cultural education is peculiarly exposed to this
danger. An idealized past becomes the refuge and solace of the spirit;
present-day concerns are found sordid, and unworthy of attention. But as a
rule, the absence of a social environment in connection with which
learning is a need and a reward is the chief reason for the isolation of
the school; and this isolation renders school knowledge inapplicable to
life and so infertile in character.</p>
<p>A narrow and moralistic view of morals is responsible for the failure to
recognize that all the aims and values which are desirable in education
are themselves moral. Discipline, natural development, culture, social
efficiency, are moral traits—marks of a person who is a worthy
member of that society which it is the business of education to further.
There is an old saying to the effect that it is not enough for a man to be
good; he must be good for something. The something for which a man must be
good is capacity to live as a social member so that what he gets from
living with others balances with what he contributes. What he gets and
gives as a human being, a being with desires, emotions, and ideas, is not
external possessions, but a widening and deepening of conscious life—a
more intense, disciplined, and expanding realization of meanings. What he
materially receives and gives is at most opportunities and means for the
evolution of conscious life. Otherwise, it is neither giving nor taking,
but a shifting about of the position of things in space, like the stirring
of water and sand with a stick. Discipline, culture, social efficiency,
personal refinement, improvement of character are but phases of the growth
of capacity nobly to share in such a balanced experience. And education is
not a mere means to such a life. Education is such a life. To maintain
capacity for such education is the essence of morals. For conscious life
is a continual beginning afresh.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM26" id="link2H_SUMM26"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. The most important problem of moral education in the school </h2>
<p>concerns the relationship of knowledge and conduct. For unless the
learning which accrues in the regular course of study affects character,
it is futile to conceive the moral end as the unifying and culminating end
of education. When there is no intimate organic connection between the
methods and materials of knowledge and moral growth, particular lessons
and modes of discipline have to be resorted to: knowledge is not
integrated into the usual springs of action and the outlook on life, while
morals become moralistic—a scheme of separate virtues.</p>
<p>The two theories chiefly associated with the separation of learning from
activity, and hence from morals, are those which cut off inner disposition
and motive—the conscious personal factor—and deeds as purely
physical and outer; and which set action from interest in opposition to
that from principle. Both of these separations are overcome in an
educational scheme where learning is the accompaniment of continuous
activities or occupations which have a social aim and utilize the
materials of typical social situations. For under such conditions, the
school becomes itself a form of social life, a miniature community and one
in close interaction with other modes of associated experience beyond
school walls. All education which develops power to share effectively in
social life is moral. It forms a character which not only does the
particular deed socially necessary but one which is interested in that
continuous readjustment which is essential to growth. Interest in learning
from all the contacts of life is the essential moral interest.</p>
<div style="height: 6em;">
<br/><br/><br/><br/><br/><br/></div>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />