<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0002" id="link2H_4_0002"></SPAN></p>
<h2> ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO. </h2>
<p>Plato's doctrine of ideas has attained an imaginary clearness and
definiteness which is not to be found in his own writings. The popular
account of them is partly derived from one or two passages in his
Dialogues interpreted without regard to their poetical environment. It is
due also to the misunderstanding of him by the Aristotelian school; and
the erroneous notion has been further narrowed and has become fixed by the
realism of the schoolmen. This popular view of the Platonic ideas may be
summed up in some such formula as the following: 'Truth consists not in
particulars, but in universals, which have a place in the mind of God, or
in some far-off heaven. These were revealed to men in a former state of
existence, and are recovered by reminiscence (anamnesis) or association
from sensible things. The sensible things are not realities, but shadows
only, in relation to the truth.' These unmeaning propositions are hardly
suspected to be a caricature of a great theory of knowledge, which Plato
in various ways and under many figures of speech is seeking to unfold.
Poetry has been converted into dogma; and it is not remarked that the
Platonic ideas are to be found only in about a third of Plato's writings
and are not confined to him. The forms which they assume are numerous, and
if taken literally, inconsistent with one another. At one time we are in
the clouds of mythology, at another among the abstractions of mathematics
or metaphysics; we pass imperceptibly from one to the other. Reason and
fancy are mingled in the same passage. The ideas are sometimes described
as many, coextensive with the universals of sense and also with the first
principles of ethics; or again they are absorbed into the single idea of
good, and subordinated to it. They are not more certain than facts, but
they are equally certain (Phaedo). They are both personal and impersonal.
They are abstract terms: they are also the causes of things; and they are
even transformed into the demons or spirits by whose help God made the
world. And the idea of good (Republic) may without violence be converted
into the Supreme Being, who 'because He was good' created all things
(Tim.).</p>
<p>It would be a mistake to try and reconcile these differing modes of
thought. They are not to be regarded seriously as having a distinct
meaning. They are parables, prophecies, myths, symbols, revelations,
aspirations after an unknown world. They derive their origin from a deep
religious and contemplative feeling, and also from an observation of
curious mental phenomena. They gather up the elements of the previous
philosophies, which they put together in a new form. Their great diversity
shows the tentative character of early endeavours to think. They have not
yet settled down into a single system. Plato uses them, though he also
criticises them; he acknowledges that both he and others are always
talking about them, especially about the Idea of Good; and that they are
not peculiar to himself (Phaedo; Republic; Soph.). But in his later
writings he seems to have laid aside the old forms of them. As he proceeds
he makes for himself new modes of expression more akin to the Aristotelian
logic.</p>
<p>Yet amid all these varieties and incongruities, there is a common meaning
or spirit which pervades his writings, both those in which he treats of
the ideas and those in which he is silent about them. This is the spirit
of idealism, which in the history of philosophy has had many names and
taken many forms, and has in a measure influenced those who seemed to be
most averse to it. It has often been charged with inconsistency and
fancifulness, and yet has had an elevating effect on human nature, and has
exercised a wonderful charm and interest over a few spirits who have been
lost in the thought of it. It has been banished again and again, but has
always returned. It has attempted to leave the earth and soar heavenwards,
but soon has found that only in experience could any solid foundation of
knowledge be laid. It has degenerated into pantheism, but has again
emerged. No other knowledge has given an equal stimulus to the mind. It is
the science of sciences, which are also ideas, and under either aspect
require to be defined. They can only be thought of in due proportion when
conceived in relation to one another. They are the glasses through which
the kingdoms of science are seen, but at a distance. All the greatest
minds, except when living in an age of reaction against them, have
unconsciously fallen under their power.</p>
<p>The account of the Platonic ideas in the Meno is the simplest and
clearest, and we shall best illustrate their nature by giving this first
and then comparing the manner in which they are described elsewhere, e.g.
in the Phaedrus, Phaedo, Republic; to which may be added the criticism of
them in the Parmenides, the personal form which is attributed to them in
the Timaeus, the logical character which they assume in the Sophist and
Philebus, and the allusion to them in the Laws. In the Cratylus they dawn
upon him with the freshness of a newly-discovered thought.</p>
<p>The Meno goes back to a former state of existence, in which men did and
suffered good and evil, and received the reward or punishment of them
until their sin was purged away and they were allowed to return to earth.
This is a tradition of the olden time, to which priests and poets bear
witness. The souls of men returning to earth bring back a latent memory of
ideas, which were known to them in a former state. The recollection is
awakened into life and consciousness by the sight of the things which
resemble them on earth. The soul evidently possesses such innate ideas
before she has had time to acquire them. This is proved by an experiment
tried on one of Meno's slaves, from whom Socrates elicits truths of
arithmetic and geometry, which he had never learned in this world. He must
therefore have brought them with him from another.</p>
<p>The notion of a previous state of existence is found in the verses of
Empedocles and in the fragments of Heracleitus. It was the natural answer
to two questions, 'Whence came the soul? What is the origin of evil?' and
prevailed far and wide in the east. It found its way into Hellas probably
through the medium of Orphic and Pythagorean rites and mysteries. It was
easier to think of a former than of a future life, because such a life has
really existed for the race though not for the individual, and all men
come into the world, if not 'trailing clouds of glory,' at any rate able
to enter into the inheritance of the past. In the Phaedrus, as well as in
the Meno, it is this former rather than a future life on which Plato is
disposed to dwell. There the Gods, and men following in their train, go
forth to contemplate the heavens, and are borne round in the revolutions
of them. There they see the divine forms of justice, temperance, and the
like, in their unchangeable beauty, but not without an effort more than
human. The soul of man is likened to a charioteer and two steeds, one
mortal, the other immortal. The charioteer and the mortal steed are in
fierce conflict; at length the animal principle is finally overpowered,
though not extinguished, by the combined energies of the passionate and
rational elements. This is one of those passages in Plato which, partaking
both of a philosophical and poetical character, is necessarily indistinct
and inconsistent. The magnificent figure under which the nature of the
soul is described has not much to do with the popular doctrine of the
ideas. Yet there is one little trait in the description which shows that
they are present to Plato's mind, namely, the remark that the soul, which
had seen truths in the form of the universal, cannot again return to the
nature of an animal.</p>
<p>In the Phaedo, as in the Meno, the origin of ideas is sought for in a
previous state of existence. There was no time when they could have been
acquired in this life, and therefore they must have been recovered from
another. The process of recovery is no other than the ordinary law of
association, by which in daily life the sight of one thing or person
recalls another to our minds, and by which in scientific enquiry from any
part of knowledge we may be led on to infer the whole. It is also argued
that ideas, or rather ideals, must be derived from a previous state of
existence because they are more perfect than the sensible forms of them
which are given by experience. But in the Phaedo the doctrine of ideas is
subordinate to the proof of the immortality of the soul. 'If the soul
existed in a previous state, then it will exist in a future state, for a
law of alternation pervades all things.' And, 'If the ideas exist, then
the soul exists; if not, not.' It is to be observed, both in the Meno and
the Phaedo, that Socrates expresses himself with diffidence. He speaks in
the Phaedo of the words with which he has comforted himself and his
friends, and will not be too confident that the description which he has
given of the soul and her mansions is exactly true, but he 'ventures to
think that something of the kind is true.' And in the Meno, after dwelling
upon the immortality of the soul, he adds, 'Of some things which I have
said I am not altogether confident' (compare Apology; Gorgias). From this
class of uncertainties he exempts the difference between truth and
appearance, of which he is absolutely convinced.</p>
<p>In the Republic the ideas are spoken of in two ways, which though not
contradictory are different. In the tenth book they are represented as the
genera or general ideas under which individuals having a common name are
contained. For example, there is the bed which the carpenter makes, the
picture of the bed which is drawn by the painter, the bed existing in
nature of which God is the author. Of the latter all visible beds are only
the shadows or reflections. This and similar illustrations or explanations
are put forth, not for their own sake, or as an exposition of Plato's
theory of ideas, but with a view of showing that poetry and the mimetic
arts are concerned with an inferior part of the soul and a lower kind of
knowledge. On the other hand, in the 6th and 7th books of the Republic we
reach the highest and most perfect conception, which Plato is able to
attain, of the nature of knowledge. The ideas are now finally seen to be
one as well as many, causes as well as ideas, and to have a unity which is
the idea of good and the cause of all the rest. They seem, however, to
have lost their first aspect of universals under which individuals are
contained, and to have been converted into forms of another kind, which
are inconsistently regarded from the one side as images or ideals of
justice, temperance, holiness and the like; from the other as hypotheses,
or mathematical truths or principles.</p>
<p>In the Timaeus, which in the series of Plato's works immediately follows
the Republic, though probably written some time afterwards, no mention
occurs of the doctrine of ideas. Geometrical forms and arithmetical ratios
furnish the laws according to which the world is created. But though the
conception of the ideas as genera or species is forgotten or laid aside,
the distinction of the visible and intellectual is as firmly maintained as
ever. The IDEA of good likewise disappears and is superseded by the
conception of a personal God, who works according to a final cause or
principle of goodness which he himself is. No doubt is expressed by Plato,
either in the Timaeus or in any other dialogue, of the truths which he
conceives to be the first and highest. It is not the existence of God or
the idea of good which he approaches in a tentative or hesitating manner,
but the investigations of physiology. These he regards, not seriously, as
a part of philosophy, but as an innocent recreation (Tim.).</p>
<p>Passing on to the Parmenides, we find in that dialogue not an exposition
or defence of the doctrine of ideas, but an assault upon them, which is
put into the mouth of the veteran Parmenides, and might be ascribed to
Aristotle himself, or to one of his disciples. The doctrine which is
assailed takes two or three forms, but fails in any of them to escape the
dialectical difficulties which are urged against it. It is admitted that
there are ideas of all things, but the manner in which individuals partake
of them, whether of the whole or of the part, and in which they become
like them, or how ideas can be either within or without the sphere of
human knowledge, or how the human and divine can have any relation to each
other, is held to be incapable of explanation. And yet, if there are no
universal ideas, what becomes of philosophy? (Parmenides.) In the Sophist
the theory of ideas is spoken of as a doctrine held not by Plato, but by
another sect of philosophers, called 'the Friends of Ideas,' probably the
Megarians, who were very distinct from him, if not opposed to him
(Sophist). Nor in what may be termed Plato's abridgement of the history of
philosophy (Soph.), is any mention made such as we find in the first book
of Aristotle's Metaphysics, of the derivation of such a theory or of any
part of it from the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics, the Heracleiteans, or even
from Socrates. In the Philebus, probably one of the latest of the Platonic
Dialogues, the conception of a personal or semi-personal deity expressed
under the figure of mind, the king of all, who is also the cause, is
retained. The one and many of the Phaedrus and Theaetetus is still working
in the mind of Plato, and the correlation of ideas, not of 'all with all,'
but of 'some with some,' is asserted and explained. But they are spoken of
in a different manner, and are not supposed to be recovered from a former
state of existence. The metaphysical conception of truth passes into a
psychological one, which is continued in the Laws, and is the final form
of the Platonic philosophy, so far as can be gathered from his own
writings (see especially Laws). In the Laws he harps once more on the old
string, and returns to general notions:—these he acknowledges to be
many, and yet he insists that they are also one. The guardian must be made
to recognize the truth, for which he has contended long ago in the
Protagoras, that the virtues are four, but they are also in some sense one
(Laws; compare Protagoras).</p>
<p>So various, and if regarded on the surface only, inconsistent, are the
statements of Plato respecting the doctrine of ideas. If we attempted to
harmonize or to combine them, we should make out of them, not a system,
but the caricature of a system. They are the ever-varying expression of
Plato's Idealism. The terms used in them are in their substance and
general meaning the same, although they seem to be different. They pass
from the subject to the object, from earth (diesseits) to heaven
(jenseits) without regard to the gulf which later theology and philosophy
have made between them. They are also intended to supplement or explain
each other. They relate to a subject of which Plato himself would have
said that 'he was not confident of the precise form of his own statements,
but was strong in the belief that something of the kind was true.' It is
the spirit, not the letter, in which they agree—the spirit which
places the divine above the human, the spiritual above the material, the
one above the many, the mind before the body.</p>
<p>The stream of ancient philosophy in the Alexandrian and Roman times widens
into a lake or sea, and then disappears underground to reappear after many
ages in a distant land. It begins to flow again under new conditions, at
first confined between high and narrow banks, but finally spreading over
the continent of Europe. It is and is not the same with ancient
philosophy. There is a great deal in modern philosophy which is inspired
by ancient. There is much in ancient philosophy which was 'born out of due
time; and before men were capable of understanding it. To the fathers of
modern philosophy, their own thoughts appeared to be new and original, but
they carried with them an echo or shadow of the past, coming back by
recollection from an elder world. Of this the enquirers of the seventeenth
century, who to themselves appeared to be working out independently the
enquiry into all truth, were unconscious. They stood in a new relation to
theology and natural philosophy, and for a time maintained towards both an
attitude of reserve and separation. Yet the similarities between modern
and ancient thought are greater far than the differences. All philosophy,
even that part of it which is said to be based upon experience, is really
ideal; and ideas are not only derived from facts, but they are also prior
to them and extend far beyond them, just as the mind is prior to the
senses.</p>
<p>Early Greek speculation culminates in the ideas of Plato, or rather in the
single idea of good. His followers, and perhaps he himself, having arrived
at this elevation, instead of going forwards went backwards from
philosophy to psychology, from ideas to numbers. But what we perceive to
be the real meaning of them, an explanation of the nature and origin of
knowledge, will always continue to be one of the first problems of
philosophy.</p>
<p>Plato also left behind him a most potent instrument, the forms of logic—arms
ready for use, but not yet taken out of their armoury. They were the late
birth of the early Greek philosophy, and were the only part of it which
has had an uninterrupted hold on the mind of Europe. Philosophies come and
go; but the detection of fallacies, the framing of definitions, the
invention of methods still continue to be the main elements of the
reasoning process.</p>
<p>Modern philosophy, like ancient, begins with very simple conceptions. It
is almost wholly a reflection on self. It might be described as a
quickening into life of old words and notions latent in the semi-barbarous
Latin, and putting a new meaning into them. Unlike ancient philosophy, it
has been unaffected by impressions derived from outward nature: it arose
within the limits of the mind itself. From the time of Descartes to Hume
and Kant it has had little or nothing to do with facts of science. On the
other hand, the ancient and mediaeval logic retained a continuous
influence over it, and a form like that of mathematics was easily
impressed upon it; the principle of ancient philosophy which is most
apparent in it is scepticism; we must doubt nearly every traditional or
received notion, that we may hold fast one or two. The being of God in a
personal or impersonal form was a mental necessity to the first thinkers
of modern times: from this alone all other ideas could be deduced. There
had been an obscure presentiment of 'cognito, ergo sum' more than 2000
years previously. The Eleatic notion that being and thought were the same
was revived in a new form by Descartes. But now it gave birth to
consciousness and self-reflection: it awakened the 'ego' in human nature.
The mind naked and abstract has no other certainty but the conviction of
its own existence. 'I think, therefore I am;' and this thought is God
thinking in me, who has also communicated to the reason of man his own
attributes of thought and extension—these are truly imparted to him
because God is true (compare Republic). It has been often remarked that
Descartes, having begun by dismissing all presuppositions, introduces
several: he passes almost at once from scepticism to dogmatism. It is more
important for the illustration of Plato to observe that he, like Plato,
insists that God is true and incapable of deception (Republic)—that
he proceeds from general ideas, that many elements of mathematics may be
found in him. A certain influence of mathematics both on the form and
substance of their philosophy is discernible in both of them. After making
the greatest opposition between thought and extension, Descartes, like
Plato, supposes them to be reunited for a time, not in their own nature
but by a special divine act (compare Phaedrus), and he also supposes all
the parts of the human body to meet in the pineal gland, that alone
affording a principle of unity in the material frame of man. It is
characteristic of the first period of modern philosophy, that having begun
(like the Presocratics) with a few general notions, Descartes first falls
absolutely under their influence, and then quickly discards them. At the
same time he is less able to observe facts, because they are too much
magnified by the glasses through which they are seen. The common logic
says 'the greater the extension, the less the comprehension,' and we may
put the same thought in another way and say of abstract or general ideas,
that the greater the abstraction of them, the less are they capable of
being applied to particular and concrete natures.</p>
<p>Not very different from Descartes in his relation to ancient philosophy is
his successor Spinoza, who lived in the following generation. The system
of Spinoza is less personal and also less dualistic than that of
Descartes. In this respect the difference between them is like that
between Xenophanes and Parmenides. The teaching of Spinoza might be
described generally as the Jewish religion reduced to an abstraction and
taking the form of the Eleatic philosophy. Like Parmenides, he is
overpowered and intoxicated with the idea of Being or God. The greatness
of both philosophies consists in the immensity of a thought which excludes
all other thoughts; their weakness is the necessary separation of this
thought from actual existence and from practical life. In neither of them
is there any clear opposition between the inward and outward world. The
substance of Spinoza has two attributes, which alone are cognizable by
man, thought and extension; these are in extreme opposition to one
another, and also in inseparable identity. They may be regarded as the two
aspects or expressions under which God or substance is unfolded to man.
Here a step is made beyond the limits of the Eleatic philosophy. The
famous theorem of Spinoza, 'Omnis determinatio est negatio,' is already
contained in the 'negation is relation' of Plato's Sophist. The grand
description of the philosopher in Republic VI, as the spectator of all
time and all existence, may be paralleled with another famous expression
of Spinoza, 'Contemplatio rerum sub specie eternitatis.' According to
Spinoza finite objects are unreal, for they are conditioned by what is
alien to them, and by one another. Human beings are included in the number
of them. Hence there is no reality in human action and no place for right
and wrong. Individuality is accident. The boasted freedom of the will is
only a consciousness of necessity. Truth, he says, is the direction of the
reason towards the infinite, in which all things repose; and herein lies
the secret of man's well-being. In the exaltation of the reason or
intellect, in the denial of the voluntariness of evil (Timaeus; Laws)
Spinoza approaches nearer to Plato than in his conception of an infinite
substance. As Socrates said that virtue is knowledge, so Spinoza would
have maintained that knowledge alone is good, and what contributes to
knowledge useful. Both are equally far from any real experience or
observation of nature. And the same difficulty is found in both when we
seek to apply their ideas to life and practice. There is a gulf fixed
between the infinite substance and finite objects or individuals of
Spinoza, just as there is between the ideas of Plato and the world of
sense.</p>
<p>Removed from Spinoza by less than a generation is the philosopher
Leibnitz, who after deepening and intensifying the opposition between mind
and matter, reunites them by his preconcerted harmony (compare again
Phaedrus). To him all the particles of matter are living beings which
reflect on one another, and in the least of them the whole is contained.
Here we catch a reminiscence both of the omoiomere, or similar particles
of Anaxagoras, and of the world-animal of the Timaeus.</p>
<p>In Bacon and Locke we have another development in which the mind of man is
supposed to receive knowledge by a new method and to work by observation
and experience. But we may remark that it is the idea of experience,
rather than experience itself, with which the mind is filled. It is a
symbol of knowledge rather than the reality which is vouchsafed to us. The
Organon of Bacon is not much nearer to actual facts than the Organon of
Aristotle or the Platonic idea of good. Many of the old rags and ribbons
which defaced the garment of philosophy have been stripped off, but some
of them still adhere. A crude conception of the ideas of Plato survives in
the 'forms' of Bacon. And on the other hand, there are many passages of
Plato in which the importance of the investigation of facts is as much
insisted upon as by Bacon. Both are almost equally superior to the
illusions of language, and are constantly crying out against them, as
against other idols.</p>
<p>Locke cannot be truly regarded as the author of sensationalism any more
than of idealism. His system is based upon experience, but with him
experience includes reflection as well as sense. His analysis and
construction of ideas has no foundation in fact; it is only the dialectic
of the mind 'talking to herself.' The philosophy of Berkeley is but the
transposition of two words. For objects of sense he would substitute
sensations. He imagines himself to have changed the relation of the human
mind towards God and nature; they remain the same as before, though he has
drawn the imaginary line by which they are divided at a different point.
He has annihilated the outward world, but it instantly reappears governed
by the same laws and described under the same names.</p>
<p>A like remark applies to David Hume, of whose philosophy the central
principle is the denial of the relation of cause and effect. He would
deprive men of a familiar term which they can ill afford to lose; but he
seems not to have observed that this alteration is merely verbal and does
not in any degree affect the nature of things. Still less did he remark
that he was arguing from the necessary imperfection of language against
the most certain facts. And here, again, we may find a parallel with the
ancients. He goes beyond facts in his scepticism, as they did in their
idealism. Like the ancient Sophists, he relegates the more important
principles of ethics to custom and probability. But crude and unmeaning as
this philosophy is, it exercised a great influence on his successors, not
unlike that which Locke exercised upon Berkeley and Berkeley upon Hume
himself. All three were both sceptical and ideal in almost equal degrees.
Neither they nor their predecessors had any true conception of language or
of the history of philosophy. Hume's paradox has been forgotten by the
world, and did not any more than the scepticism of the ancients require to
be seriously refuted. Like some other philosophical paradoxes, it would
have been better left to die out. It certainly could not be refuted by a
philosophy such as Kant's, in which, no less than in the previously
mentioned systems, the history of the human mind and the nature of
language are almost wholly ignored, and the certainty of objective
knowledge is transferred to the subject; while absolute truth is reduced
to a figment, more abstract and narrow than Plato's ideas, of 'thing in
itself,' to which, if we reason strictly, no predicate can be applied.</p>
<p>The question which Plato has raised respecting the origin and nature of
ideas belongs to the infancy of philosophy; in modern times it would no
longer be asked. Their origin is only their history, so far as we know it;
there can be no other. We may trace them in language, in philosophy, in
mythology, in poetry, but we cannot argue a priori about them. We may
attempt to shake them off, but they are always returning, and in every
sphere of science and human action are tending to go beyond facts. They
are thought to be innate, because they have been familiar to us all our
lives, and we can no longer dismiss them from our mind. Many of them
express relations of terms to which nothing exactly or nothing at all in
rerum natura corresponds. We are not such free agents in the use of them
as we sometimes imagine. Fixed ideas have taken the most complete
possession of some thinkers who have been most determined to renounce
them, and have been vehemently affirmed when they could be least explained
and were incapable of proof. The world has often been led away by a word
to which no distinct meaning could be attached. Abstractions such as
'authority,' 'equality,' 'utility,' 'liberty,' 'pleasure,' 'experience,'
'consciousness,' 'chance,' 'substance,' 'matter,' 'atom,' and a heap of
other metaphysical and theological terms, are the source of quite as much
error and illusion and have as little relation to actual facts as the
ideas of Plato. Few students of theology or philosophy have sufficiently
reflected how quickly the bloom of a philosophy passes away; or how hard
it is for one age to understand the writings of another; or how nice a
judgment is required of those who are seeking to express the philosophy of
one age in the terms of another. The 'eternal truths' of which
metaphysicians speak have hardly ever lasted more than a generation. In
our own day schools or systems of philosophy which have once been famous
have died before the founders of them. We are still, as in Plato's age,
groping about for a new method more comprehensive than any of those which
now prevail; and also more permanent. And we seem to see at a distance the
promise of such a method, which can hardly be any other than the method of
idealized experience, having roots which strike far down into the history
of philosophy. It is a method which does not divorce the present from the
past, or the part from the whole, or the abstract from the concrete, or
theory from fact, or the divine from the human, or one science from
another, but labours to connect them. Along such a road we have proceeded
a few steps, sufficient, perhaps, to make us reflect on the want of method
which prevails in our own day. In another age, all the branches of
knowledge, whether relating to God or man or nature, will become the
knowledge of 'the revelation of a single science' (Symp.), and all things,
like the stars in heaven, will shed their light upon one another.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />