<p>A.C. <SPAN name="link2H_4_0005" id="link2H_4_0005"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> SPINOZA. </h2>
<p>Baruch Spinoza, or Espinoza, better known under the name of Benedict
Spinoza (as rendered by himself in the Latin language,) was born at
Amsterdam, in Holland, on the 24th of November, 1632. There is some
uncertainty as to this date, as there are several dates fixed by different
authors, both for his birth and death, but we have adopted the biography
given by Dr. C. H. Bruder, in the preface to his edition of Spinoza's
works. His parents were Jews of the middle, or, perhaps, somewhat humbler
class. His father was originally a Spanish merchant, who, to escape
persecution, had emigrated to Holland. Although the life of our great
philosopher is one full of interesting incidents, and deserves to be
treated fully, we have but room to give a very brief sketch, referring our
readers, who may wish to learn more of Spinoza's life, to Lewes's
"Biographical History of Philosophy," <i>Westminster Review</i>, No. 77,
and "Encyclopædia Brittannica." p. 144. His doctrines we will let speak
for themselves in his own words, trusting thereby to give the reader an
opportunity of knowing who and what Spinoza really was. One man shrinks
with horror from him as an Atheist. Voltaire says, that he was an Atheist,
and taught Atheism. Another calls him "a God-intoxicated man." We present
him a mighty thinker, a master mind, a noble, fearless utterer of free and
noble thoughts, a hard-working, honest, independent man; as one who, two
centuries ago, gave forth to the world a series of thinkings which have
crushed, with resistless force, the theological shell in the centre of
which the priests hide the kernel "truth."</p>
<p>Spinoza appears in his boyhood to have been an apt scholar, and to have
rapidly mastered the tasks set him by his teachers. Full of rabbinical
lore he won the admiration of the Rabbi Moses Mortira, but the pupil rose
higher than his master, and attempted to solve problems which the learned
rabbis were content to reverence as mysteries not capable of solution.
First they remonstrated, then threatened; still Spinoza persevered in his
studies, and in making known the result to those around him. He was
threatened with excommunication, and withdrew himself from the synagogue.
One more effort was made by the rabbis, who offered Spinoza a pension of
about £100 a-year if he would attend the synagogue more frequently, and
consent to be silent with regard to his philosophical thinkings. This
offer he indignantly refused. Reason failing, threats proving futile, and
gold being treated with scorn, one was found sufficiently fanatic to try a
further experiment, which resulted in an attempt on Spinoza's life; the
knife, however, luckily missed its aim, and our hero escaped. At last, in
the year 1660, Spinoza, being then twenty-eight years of age, was solemnly
excommunicated from the synagogue. His friends and relations shut their
doors against him. An outcast from the home of his youth, he gained a
humble livelihood by polishing glasses for microscopes, telescopes, etc.,
at which he was very expert. While thus acquiring, by his own handiwork,
the means of subsistence, he was studying hard, devoting every possible
hour to philosophical research. Spinoza became master of the Dutch,
Hebrew, German, Spanish, Portuguese, and Latin languages, the latter of
which he acquired in the house of one Francis Van den Ende, from whom it
is more than probable he received as much instruction in Atheism as in
Latin. Spinoza only appears to have once fallen in love, and this was with
Van den Ende's daughter, who was herself a good linguist, and who gave
Spinoza instruction in Latin. She, however, although willing to be his
instructress and companion in a philogical path, declined to accept his
love, and thus Spinoza was left to philosophy alone. After his
excommunication he retired to Rhynsburg, near the City of Leyden, in
Holland, and there studied the works of Descartes. Three years afterwards
he published an abridgment of the "Meditations" of the great father of
philosophy, which created a profound sensation. In an appendix to this
abridgment were contained the germs of those thinkings in which the pupil
outdid the master, and the student progressed beyond the philosopher. In
the month of June, 1664, Spinoza removed to Woorburg, a small village near
the Hague, where he was visited by persons from different parts, attracted
by his fame as a philosopher; and at last, after many solicitations he
came to the Hague, and resided there altogether. In 1670 he published his
"Tractatus Theologico-Politicus." This raised him a host of opponents;
many writers rushed eager for the fray, to tilt with the poor Dutch Jew.
His book was officially condemned and forbidden, and a host of refutations
(?) were circulated against it. In spite of the condemnation it has
outlived the refutations.</p>
<p>Spinoza died on the 21st or 22nd of February, 1677, in his forty-fifth
year, and was buried on the 25th of February at the Hague. He was frugal
in his habits, subsisting independently on the earnings of his own hands.
Honorable in all things, he refused to accept the chair of Professor of
Philosophy, offered to him by the Elector, and this because he did not
wish to be circumscribed in his thinking, or in the freedom of utterance
of his thoughts. He also refused a pension offered to him by Louis XIV,
saying that he had no intention of dedicating anything to that monarch.
The following is a list of Spinoza's works:—"Principiorum
Philosophise Renati Descartes;" "Tractatus Theologico-Politicus;"
"Ethica;" "Tractatus Politi-cus;" "De Emandatione Intellectus;"
"Epistolæ;" "Grammaticus Hebracæ," etc. There are also several spurious
works ascribed to Spinoza. The "Tractatus Politicus" has been translated
into English by William Maccall, who seems fully to appreciate the
greatness of the philosopher, although he will not admit the usefulness of
Spinoza's logic. Maccall does not see the utility of that very logic which
compelled him to admit Spinoza's truth. We are not aware of any other
translation of Spinoza's works except that of a small portion of his
"Ethica," by Lewes. This work, which was originally published in 1677,
commenced with eight definitions, which, together with the following
axioms and propositions, were reprinted from the <i>Westminster Review</i>
in the <i>Library of Reason</i>:—</p>
<p>DEFINITIONS.</p>
<p>I. By cause of itself I understand that, the essence of which involves
existence: or that, the nature of which can only be considered as
existent.</p>
<p>II. A thing finite is that which can be limited (terminari potest) by
another thing of the same nature—<i>ergo</i>, body is said to be
finite because it can always be conceived as larger. So thought is limited
by other thoughts. But body does not limit thought, nor thought limit
body.</p>
<p>III. By substance I understand that which is in itself, and is conceived
<i>per se</i>—that is, the conception of which does not require the
conception of anything else as antecedent to it.</p>
<p>IV. By attribute I understand that which the mind perceives as
constituting the very essence of substance.</p>
<p>V. By modes I understand the accidents (affectiones) of substance; or that
which is in something else, through which also it is conceived.</p>
<p>VI. By God I understand the being absolutely infinite; that is, the
substance consisting of infinite attributes, each of which expresses an
infinite and eternal essence.</p>
<p><i>Explication</i>, I say absolutely infinite, but not in <i>suo genere</i>;
for to whatever is infinite, but not in <i>suo genere</i>, we can deny
infinite attributes; but that which is absolutely infinite, to its essence
pertains everything which implies essence, and involves no negation.</p>
<p>VII. That thing is said to be free which exists by the sole necessity of
its nature, and by itself alone is determined to action. But that is
necessary, or rather constrained, which owes its existence to another, and
acts according to certain and determinate causes.</p>
<p>VIII. By eternity I understand existence itself, in as far as it is
conceived necessarily to follow from the sole definition of an eternal
thing.</p>
<p>AXIOMS.</p>
<p>I. Everything which is, is in itself, or in some other thing.</p>
<p>II. That which cannot be conceived through another, <i>per aliud</i> must
be conceived, <i>per se</i>.</p>
<p>III. From a given determinate cause the effect necessarily follows, and <i>vice
versa</i>. If no determinate cause be given, no effect can follow.</p>
<p>IV. The knowledge of an effect depends on the knowledge of the cause, and
includes it.</p>
<p>V. Things that have nothing in common with each other cannot be understood
by means of each other—that is, the conception of one, does not
involve the conception of the other.</p>
<p>VI. A true idea must agree with its original in nature.</p>
<p>VII. Whatever can be clearly conceived as non-existent does not, in its
essence, involve existence.</p>
<p>PROPOSITIONS.</p>
<p>I. Substance is prior in nature to its accidents. Demonstration. Per
definitions three and five.</p>
<p>II. Two substances, having different attributes, have nothing in common
with each other. Dem. This follows from def. three; for each substance
must be conceived in itself and through itself; in other words, the
conception of one does not involve the conception of the other.</p>
<p>III. Of things which have nothing in common, one cannot be the cause of
the other. Dem. If they have nothing in common, then (per axiom five) they
cannot be conceived by means of each other; <i>ergo</i> (per axiom four,)
one cannot be the cause of the other.—Q. E. D.</p>
<p>IV. Two or more distinct things are distinguished among themselves, either
through the diversity of their attributes, or through that of their modes.
Dem. Everything which is, in itself, or in some other thing (per ax. one)—that
is (per def. three and five,) there is nothing out of ourselves (<i>extra
intellectum</i>, outside the intellect) but substance and its modes. There
is nothing out of ourselves whereby things can be distinguished amongst
one another, except substances, or (which is the same thing, per def.
lour) their attributes and modes.</p>
<p>V. It is impossible that there should be two or more substances of the
same nature, or of the same attributes. Dem. If there are many different
substances they must be distinguished by the diversity of their attributes
or of their modes (per prop. 4.) If only by the diversity of their
attributes, it is thereby conceded that there is, nevertheless, only one
substance of the same attribute; but if their diversity of modes, then,
substance being prior in order of time to its modes, it must be considered
independent of them—that is (per def. three and six,) cannot be
conceived as distinguished from another—that is (per prop, four,)
there cannot be many substances, but only one substance.—Q. E. D.</p>
<p>VI. One substance cannot be created by another substance. Dem. There
cannot be two substances with the same attributes (per prop, five)—that
is (per prop. two,) that hare anything in common with each other; and,
therefore (per prop, three,) one cannot be the cause of the other.</p>
<p>Corollary 1. Hence it follows that substance cannot be created by anything
else. For there is nothing in nature except substance and its modes (per
axiom one, and def. three and five.) Now, this substance, not being
produced by another, is self-caused.</p>
<p>Corollary 2. This proposition is more easily to be demonstrated by the
absurdity of its contradiction; for if substance can be produced by
anything else, the conception of it would depend on the conception of the
cause (per axiom four,) and hence (per def. three,) it would not be
substance.</p>
<p>VII. It pertains to the nature of substance to exist. Dem. Substance
cannot be produced by anything else (per coroli. prop, six,) and is
therefore the cause of itself—that is (per def. one,) its essence
necessarily involves existence; or it pertains to the nature of substance
to exist.—Q. E. D.</p>
<p>VIII. All substance is necessarily infinite. Dem. There exists but one
substance of the same attribute; and it must either exist as infinite or
finite. But not finite, for (per def. two) as finite it must be limited by
another substance of the same nature, and in that case there would be two
substances of the same attributes, which (per prop, five) is absurd.
Substance therefore is infinite.—Q. E. D.</p>
<p>"Scholium I.—I do not doubt but that to all who judge confusedly of
things, and are not wont to inquire into first causes, it will be
difficult to admit the demonstration of prop. 7, because they do not
sufficiently distinguish between the modifications of substances, and
substances themselves, and are ignorant of the manner in which things are
produced. Hence it follows, that the commencement which they see natural
things have, they attribute to substances; for he who knows not the true
cause of things, confounds all things, and feigns that trees talk like
men; that men are formed from stones as well as from seeds, and that all
forms can be changed into all other forms. So, also, those who confound
the divine nature with the human, naturally attribute human affections to
God, especially as they are ignorant of how these affections are produced
in the mind. If men attended to the nature of substance, they would not,
in the least, doubt proposition seven; nay, this proposition would be an
axiom to all, and would be numbered among common notions. For by substance
they would understand that which exists in itself, and is concerned
through itself—<i>i.e.</i>, the knowledge of which does not require
the knowledge of anything as antecedent to it. But by modification they
would understand that which is in another thing, the conception of which
is formed by the conception of the thing in which it is, or to which it
belongs. We can have, therefore, correct ideas of non-existent
modifications, because, although out of the understanding they have no
reality, yet their essence is so comprehended in that of another, that
they can be conceived through this other. The truth of substance (out of
the understanding) lies nowhere but in itself, because it is conceived <i>per
se</i>. If therefore any one says he has a clear idea of substance, and
yet doubt whether such substance exist, this would be as much as to say
that he has a true idea, and nevertheless doubts whether it be not false
(as a little attention sufficiently manifests;) or if any man affirms
substance to be created, he at the same time affirms that a true idea has
become false, than which nothing can be more absurd. Hence it is
necessarily confessed that the existence of substance, as well as its
essence, is an eternal truth. And hence we must conclude that there is
only one substance possessing the same attribute, which requires here a
fuller development. I note therefore—1. That the correct definition
of a thing includes and expresses nothing but the nature of the thing
defined. From which follows—2. That no definition includes or
expresses a distinct number of individuals, because it expresses nothing
but the nature of the thing defined; <i>ergo</i>, the definition of a
triangle expresses no more than the nature of a triangle, and not any
fixed number of triangles. 3. There must necessarily be a distinct cause
for the existence of every existing thing. 4. This cause, by reason of
which anything exists, must either be contained in the nature and
definition of the existing thing (viz., that it pertains to its nature to
exist,) or else must be beyond it—must be something different from
it.</p>
<p>"As therefore it pertains to the nature of substance to exist, so must its
definition include a necessary existence, and consequently from its sole
definition we must conclude its existence. But as from its definition, as
already shown in notes two and three, it is not possible to conclude the
existence of many substances—<i>ergo</i>, it necessarily follows
that only one substance of the same nature can exist."</p>
<p>It will be necessary for the reader to remember that Spinoza commenced his
philosophical studies at the same point with Descartes. Both recognized
existence as the primal fact, self-evident and indisputable.</p>
<p>But while Descartes had, in some manner, fashioned a quality—God and
God-created substance—Spinoza only found one, substance, the
definition of which included existence. By his fourth proposition ("of
things which have nothing in common, one cannot be the cause of the other,
") he destroyed the creation theory, because by that theory God is assumed
to be a spirit having nothing in common with matter, yet acting on matter;
and Lewes speaks of the fourth proposition in the following terms:—"This
fallacy has been one of the most influential corrupters of philosophical
speculation. For many years it was undisputed, and most metaphysicians
still adhere to it. The assertion is that only like can act upon like; but
although it is true that <i>like</i> produces (causes) <i>like</i>, it is
also true that like produces <i>unlike</i>; thus fire produces pain when
applied to our bodies; <i>explosion</i> when applied to gunpowder; <i>charcoal</i>
when applied to wood; all these effects are unlike the cause." We cannot
help thinking that in this instance, the usually thoughtful Lewes has
either confused substance with its modes, or, for the sake of producing a
temporary effect, has descended to mere sophism. Spinoza's proposition is,
that <i>substances</i> having nothing in common, cannot act on one
another. Lewes deals with several modes of the same substance as though
they were different substances. Way, more, to make his argument the more
plausible, he entirely ignores in it that <i>noumenon</i> of which he
speaks as underlying all phenomena, and uses each phenomenon as a separate
existence. In each of the instances mentioned, however varied may be the
modification, the essence is the same. They are merely examples of one
portion of the whole acting upon another portion, and there is that in
each mode which is common to the whole, and by means of which the action
takes place.</p>
<p>Much has been said of Spinoza's "God" and "Divine Substance," and we must
refer the reader to Definition Six, in which God is defined as being
"infinite substance." Now, although we should be content to strike the
word "God" out of our own tablet of philosophical nomenclature, as being a
much misused, misrepresented, and entirely useless word, yet we must be
very careful, when we find another man using the word, to get his precise
definition, and not to use any-other ourselves while in his company.</p>
<p>Spinoza, when asked "What name do you attach to infinite substance?" says,
"God."—If he had said any other word we could not have quarrelled
with him so long as he defined the word, and adhered strictly to the terms
of his definition, although we might regret that he had not either coined
a word for himself, or used one less maltreated by the mass. Spinoza said,
"I can only take cognizance of one substance (of which I am part) having
infinite attributes of extension and thought. I take cognizance of
substance by its modes, and in my consciousness of existence. Every thing
is a mode of the attribute of extension, every thought, wish, or feeling,
a mode of the attribute of thought. I call this, substance, with infinite
attributes, God." Spinoza, like all other thinkers, found himself
overpowered by the illimitable vastness of the infinite when attempting to
grasp it by his mental powers, but unlike other men he did not endeavor to
relieve himself by separating himself from that infinite; but, knowing he
was a part of the whole, not divisible from the remainder, he was content
to aim at perfecting his knowledge of existence rather than at dogmatising
upon an indefinable word, which, if it represented anything, professed to
represent an incomprehensible existence far beyond his reach.</p>
<p>We ought not to wonder that in many parts of Spinoza's writings we find
the word "God" treated in a less coherent manner than would be possible
under the definition given in his "Ethics," and for these reasons:—Spinoza,
from his cradle upwards, had been surrounded with books and traditions
sanctified by the past, and impressed on his willing mind by his family,
his tutors, and the heads of his church; a mind like his gathered all that
was given, even more quickly than it was offered, still craving for more—"more
light"—"more light"—and at last light came bursting on the
young thinker like a lightning flash at dark midnight, revealing his mind
in chains, which had been cast round him in his nursery, his school, his
college, his synagogue. By a mighty effort he burst these chains, and
walked forth a free man, despite the entreaties of his family, the
reasonings of the rabbis, the knife of the fanatic, the curse of his
church, and the edict of the state. But should it be a matter of surprise
to us that some of the links of those broken chains should still hang on
the young philosopher, and, seeming to be a part of himself, almost
imperceptibly incline to old ways of thinking, and to old modes of
utterance of those thoughts! Wonder not that a few links bang about him,
but rather that he ever succeeded in breaking those chains at all.
Spinoza, after his secession from his synagogue, became logically an
Atheist; education and early impressions enlarged this into a less
clearly-defined Pantheism; but the logic comes to us naked, disrobed of
all by which it might have been surrounded in Spinoza's mind. If that
logic be correct, then all the theologies of the world are false. We have
presented it to the reader to judge of for himself. Many men have written
against it; of these some have misunderstood, some have misrepresented,
some have failed, and few have left us a proof that they had endeavored to
deal with Spinoza on his own ground. Maccall says, "In the glorious throng
of heroic names, there are few nobler than Spinoza's. Apart altogether
from the estimate we may form of his philosophy, there is something
unspeakably interesting in the life and the character of the man. In his
metaphysical system there are two things exceedingly distinct. There is,
first, the immense and prodigious, but terrible mathematical skeleton,
which his subtle intellect binds up and throws as calmly into space as we
drop a pebble into the water, and whose bones, striking against the wreck
of all that is sacred in belief, or bold in speculation, rattle a wild
response to our wildest phantasies, and drive us almost to think in
despair that thinking is madness; and there is, secondly, the divinest
vision of the infinite, and the divinest incense which the intuition of
the infinite ever yet poured forth at the altar of creation."</p>
<p>The "Treatise on Politics" is not Spinoza's greatest work; it is, in all
respects, inferior to the "Ethics," and to the "Theologico-Political
Treatise." But there are in politics certain eternal principles, and it is
for setting forth and elucidating these that the Treatise of Spinoza is so
valuable.</p>
<p>In the second chapter of that Treatise, after defining what he means by
nature, etc., he, on the sixth section, proceeds as follows:—"But
many believe that the ignorant disturb more than follow the order of
nature, and conceive of men in nature as a state within the state. For
they assert that the human mind has not been produced by any natural
causes, but created immediately by God, and thereby rendered so
independent of other things as to have absolute power of determining
itself, and of using reason aright. But experience teaches us more than
enough, that it is no more in our power to have a sound mind than a sound
body. Since, moreover, everything, as far as it is able, strives to
conserve its being, we cannot doubt that if it were equally in our power
to live according to the prescripts of reason, as to be led by blind
desire, all would seek the guidance of reason and live wisely, which is
not the case. For every one is the slave of the particular pleasure to
which he is most attached. Nor do theologians remove the difficulty when
they assert that this inability is a vice, or a sin of human nature, which
derives its origin from the fall of the first parent. For if it was in the
power of the first man to stand rather than to fall, and if he was sound
in faculty, and had perfect control over his own mind, how did it happen
that he, the wise and prudent, fell? But they say he was deceived and
tempted by the devil. But who was it that led astray and tempted the devil
himself? Who, I ask, rendered this the most excellent of intelligent
creatures so mad, that he wished to be greater than God? Could he render
himself thus mad—he who had a sane mind, and strove as much as in
him lay to conserve his being? How, moreover, could it happen that the
first man in possession of his entire mental faculties, and master of his
will, should be both open to temptation, and suffer himself to be robbed
of his mind? For if he had the power of using his reason aright, he could
not be deceived; for as far as in him lay, he necessarily sought to
conserve his own being, and the sanity of his mind. But it is supposed he
had this in his power, therefore he necessarily conserved his sane mind,
neither could he be deceived. Which is evidently false from his history;
and, consequently, it must be granted that it was not in the power of the
first person to use reason aright, but that he, like us, was subject to
passions."</p>
<p>Spinoza is scarcely likely to become a great favorite with the "Woman's
Rights Convention." In his ninth chapter of the same Treatise, he says,
"If by nature women were equal to men, and excelled as much as they in
strength of mind and in talent, truly amongst nations, so many and so
different, some would be found where both sexes ruled equally, and others
where the men were ruled by the women, and so educated as to be inferior
to them in talent; but as this has never happened, we are justified in
assuming that women, by nature, have not an equal right with men, but that
they are necessarily obedient to men, and thus it can never happen that
both sexes can equally rule, and still less that men be ruled by women."</p>
<p>Lewes, in his seventh chapter on Modern Philosophy, thus sums up Spinoza's
teachings and their result. He says:—</p>
<p>"The doctrine of Spinoza was of great importance, if for nothing more than
having brought about the first crisis in modern philosophy. His doctrine
was so clearly stated, and so rigorously deduced from admitted premises,
that he brought philosophy into this dilemma:—</p>
<p>"'Either my premises are correct; and we must admit that every clear and
distinct idea is absolutely true; true not only subjectively, but
objectively.</p>
<p>"'If so, my objection is true;</p>
<p>"'Or my premises are false; the voice of consciousness is not the voice of
truth;</p>
<p>"'And if so, then is my system false, but all philosophy is impossible;
since the only ground of certitude—our consciousness—is
pronounced unstable, our only means of knowing the truth is pronounced
fallacious.'"</p>
<p>"Spinozism or scepticism, choose between them, for you have no other
choice.</p>
<p>"Mankind refused, however, to make a choice. If the principles which
Descartes had established could have no other result than Spinozism, it
was worth while inquiring whether those principles might not themselves be
modified.</p>
<p>"The ground of discussion was shifted, psychology took the place of
ontology. It was Descartes's theory of knowledge which led to Spinozism;
that theory must therefore he examined; that theory becomes the great
subject of discussion. Before deciding upon the merits of any system which
embraced the great questions of creation, the Deity, immortality, etc.,
men saw that it was necessary to decide upon the competency of the human
mind to solve such problems. All knowledge must be obtained either through
experience or independent of experience. Knowledge dependent on experience
must necessarily be merely knowledge of <i>phenomena</i>. All are agreed
that experience can only be experience of ourselves as modified by
objects. All are agreed that to know things <i>per se—noumena</i>—we
must know them through some other channel then experience. Have we or have
we not that other channel? This is the problem."</p>
<p>"Thus, before we can dogmatize upon on to logical subjects, we must settle
this question—Can we transcend the sphere of our consciousness, and
know things <i>per se</i>?"</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />